Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Just War Theory and the Ethical Governance of Research

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article analyses current trends in and future expectations of nanotechnology and other key enabling technologies for security as well as dual use nanotechnology from the perspective of the ethical Just War Theory (JWT), interpreted as an instrument to increase the threshold for using armed force for solving conflicts. The aim is to investigate the relevance of the JWT to the ethical governance of research. The analysis gives rise to the following results. From the perspective of the JWT, military research should be evaluated with different criteria than research for civil or civil security applications. From a technological perspective, the boundaries between technologies for civil and military applications are fuzzy. Therefore the JWT offers theoretical grounds for making clear distinctions between research for military, civil security and other applications that are not obvious from a purely technological perspective. Different actors bear responsibility for development of the technology than for resorting to armed force for solving conflicts or for use of weapons and military technologies in combat. Different criteria should be used for moral judgment of decisions made by each type of actor in each context. In addition to evaluation of potential consequences of future use of the weapons or military technologies under development, the JWT also prescribes ethical evaluation of the inherent intent and other foreseeable consequences of the development itself of new military technologies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Risk assessment projects have also been funded on the basis of the constitutional government’s responsibilities for occupational health and safety, environment and public health.

  2. http://www.icrc.org/ihl.nsf/WebART/470-750045?OpenDocument.

  3. This view is contested. To many international lawyers, legitimate preventive self-defence is a contradictio in terminis, even those that like Grotius accept humanitarian intervention.

  4. See also http://www.homelandsecurity.org/hsireports/DHS_ST_RL_Calculator_report20091020.pdf.

  5. In current international law, apart from self-defence, a mandate from the Security Council is required for military action to be legitimate. In the future, European integration could lead to the transfer of authority the national to the EU level. A more thorough discussion on an adequate interpretation of the ethical concept of “legitimate authority” goes beyond the scope of this article.

  6. Exactly what should be the responsibility of the state and what should be left to private parties is a political question that is answered differently in different countries and at different times. There is also a debate on democratising science: giving groups in society other than the scientific community and industry a say in research policy decisions. This debate goes beyond the scope of this article.

  7. This criterion Just Intent should not be interpreted in a psychological way, but as the explicit or implicit purpose of the military technology in question (e.g. the apparent intent of a precision weapon is to limit collateral damage as much as possible, whereas the apparent intent of WMD is to indiscriminately create as many victims as possible).

  8. A commonly accepted requirement of new weapons developed today is that their effects should be scalable.

  9. C.f. literature on codes of conduct for research, dual use life sciences and nanotechnology.

  10. E.g. in several EU funded projects including HIDE www.hideproject.org, RISE www.riseproject.eu and ETICA http://www.etica-project.eu/.

  11. C.f. BTWC: http://www.unog.ch/80256EDD006B8954/(httpAssets)/C4048678A93B6934C1257188004848D0/$file/BWC-text-English.pdf and CWC: http://www.opcw.org/chemical-weapons-convention/.

  12. This presumed aversion of defence contracts in universities is contested by others.

  13. This section largely discusses trends in nanotechnology for civil and dual use applications that have been discussed in public literature, internet sources and events. Explicitly military nanotechnology was outside of the mandate of the project in which these information sources were reviewed. See for reviews of trends in military nanotechnology (Altmann 2006; Simonis and Schilthuizen 2006).

  14. ICT R&D in Europe is located completely in the civilian sector because military demands are not more stringent than civilian.

  15. www.nanowerk.com.

  16. Dutch newspapers reported on this discussion, e.g. Trouw: http://www.trouw.nl/tr/nl/4324/Nieuws/article/detail/1177074/2009/12/28/rsquo-RIVM-stond-er-te-vaak-alleen-voor-rsquo.dhtml and HP/De Tijd, http://test.hpdetijd.nl/2009-11-09/zeven-vragen-over-de-mexicaanse-griep.

  17. E.g. EDRI website, Digital Civil Rights in Europe, http://edri.org/.

  18. On 22 March 2011: http://ec.europa.eu/european_group_ethics/index_en.htm.

  19. René von Schomberg, intervention at ETICA-EGAIS-STOA workshop on IT for a Better Future, European Parliament, 31 March 2011, http://www.etica-project.eu/.

  20. “Dual use” is traditionally a term that implies that certain technologies or other resources can both be used for civil and military applications. However, in philosophical debates, “dual use” can also mean that a technology can be used for good and bad purposes, where the distinction between military and civil uses is not made (C.f. van der Bruggen 2011).

  21. Discussion at RISE/HIDE workshop on the 9th and 10th of December 2010.

  22. In classical JWT, this would be the legitimate government of a sovereign state. Under International Humanitarian Law, legitimate authority may not be limited to national governments, but may also be attributed to some specific supranational bodies. A discussion on the right interpretation of the ethical concept “legitimate authority” goes beyond the scope of this article.

References

  • Altmann, J. (2005). Nanotechnology and preventive arms control. Osnabrück: Deutsche Stiftung Friedensforschung.

    Google Scholar 

  • Altmann, J. (2006). Military nanotechnology: Potential applications and preventive arms control. Contemporary security studies. Oxon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Altmann, J. (2008). Präventive Rüstungskontrolle. Die Friedens-Warte, 83(2–3), 105–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisenhower, D. D. (1961). Militaryindustrial complex speech. Michigan State University. http://coursesa.matrix.msu.edu/~hst306/documents/indust.html. Accessed 22 Sept 2011.

  • Ericson, L. (2007). Introduction: Nanotechnology and biometrics, presentation at biometric consortium conference, 13 September 2007. http://www.biometrics.org/bc2007/presentations/Thu_Sep_13/Session_II/13_Ericson_NANO.pdf. Accessed 31 Jan 2012.

  • EDA (2009). Annual report 2009. Brussels: European Defence Agency. http://www.eda.europa.eu/genericitem.aspx?id=621. Accessed 19 July 2010

  • ESRAB (2006). Meeting the challenge. The European security research agenda. Brussels: European Commission. http://ec.europa.eu/enterprise/policies/security/publications/index_en.htm. Accessed 21 Feb 2012.

  • EU. (2000). Charter of the fundamental rights of the European Union. Official Journal of the European Communities 2000/C 364/01 18/12/2000. http://www.europarl.europa.eu/charter/pdf/text_en.pdf. Accessed 28 Dec 2011.

  • European Commission. (2006). Eurobarometer 66. European commission. http://ec.europa.eu/public_opinion/archives/eb/eb66/eb66_en.htm. Accessed 22 Sept 2011.

  • European Commission. (2007). Special Eurobarometer 266: The role of the European Union in justice, freedom and security policy areas. Brussels: European Commission DG Communication at the request of DG Justice, Freedom and Security. http://ec.europa.eu/public_opinion/archives/ebs/ebs_264_en.pdf. Accessed 22 Sept 2011.

  • European Commission. (2010). Eurobarometer 74. European commission. http://ec.europa.eu/public_opinion/archives/eb/eb74/eb74_publ_en.pdf. Accessed 22 Sept 2011.

  • Greenwood, C. (1998). The law of weaponry at the start of the new millennium. In M. N. Schmitt & L. C. Green (Eds.), The law of armed conflict: Into the next millennium. International law studies (Vol. 71, pp. 185–232). Newport, Rhode Island: Naval War College.

  • Gsponer, A. (2007). From lab to battlefield. Disarmament Diplomacy, 67.

  • Gubrud, M. A. (1997). Nanotechnology and international security. In Proceedings 5th foresight conference on molecular nanotechnology.

  • James, A. D. (2010). Scenario report SANDERA: The future impact of security and defence policies on the European research area. SANDERA project. Manchester: Manchester Institute of Innovation Research. www.sandera.net. Accessed March 2011.

  • Lawand, K. (2006). Reviewing the legality of new weapons. International review of the Red Cross, 2006, 925–930.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leydesdorff, L., & Etzkowitz, H. (1996). Emergence of a triple helix of university—industry—government relations. Science and Public Policy, 23(1996), 279–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lietzau, W. K. (2004). Old laws, new wars: Jus ad Bellum in an age of terrorism. Max Planck Yearbook of United Nations Law, 8, 383–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malsch, I. (2011). Ethics and nanotechnology: Responsible development of nanotechnology at global level in the 21st century. PhD-thesis. Nijmegen: Radboud University.

  • Malsch, I., & Fruelund-Andersen, A. M. (2011). Ethical and societal aspects of nanotechnology enabled ICT and Security Technologies. Observatory nano project. http://www.observatorynano.eu/project/document/3525/. Accessed 22 Sept 2011.

  • Mangan, J. (1949). An historical analysis of the principle of double effect. Theological Studies, 10, 41–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • McIntyre, A. (2011). Doctrine of double effect. In N. Z. Edward (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2011 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/double-effect/. Accessed 31 Jan 2012.

  • Moseley, A. (2009). Just war theory. The internet encyclopaedia of philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/j/justwar.htm. Accessed 9 Feb 2012.

  • Nanoforum (2007). Nanotechnology for civil security. Nanoforum. http://www.nanoforum.org/nf06~modul~showmore~folder~99999~scid~476~.html? action=longview_publication. Accessed 19 July 2010.

  • Nasu, H., & Faunce, T. (2009). Nanotechnology and the international law of weaponry: Towards international regulation of nanoweapons. Journal of Law and Information Science, 20, 21 (online).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nixdorff, K. (2010). Technological developments of relevance to the BWC: What are we talking about? BioWeapons Prevention Project RevCon Discussions. http://www.bwpp.org/revcon-techinfluence.html. Accessed 22 Sept 2011.

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2006). Frontiers of justice: Disability, nationality, species membership (The Tanner Lectures on Human Values). Boston: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Donovan, O. (2003). The just war revisited. Cambridge: Current Issues in Theology.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ObservatoryNano. (2009). General sector reports: Security. ObservatoryNano project. http://www.observatorynano.eu/project/catalogue/2SE/ Accessed 27 Jan 2011.

  • Risser, D. T. (2009). Collective moral responsibility. The internet encyclopaedia of philosophy. Last updated 14 Dec 2009, Originally published: 6 July 2004. http://www.iep.utm.edu/collecti/. Last accessed 15 Oct 2010.

  • Roco, M. C., & Bainbridge, W. S. (2003). Nanotechnology: Societal implicationsmaximizing benefit for humanity. Report of national nanotechnology initiative workshop, 3-5 Dec 2003, Arlington, VA, USA: NSF, http://www.nano.gov/nni_societal_implications.pdf. Last accessed 29 Oct 2010.

  • Roco, M. C., Mirkin, C. A. & Hersham, M C. (Eds.). (2010). Nanotechnology research directions for societal needs in 2020: Retrospective and outlook. Dordrecht: Springer. www.wtec.org/nano2. Accessed 31 Jan 2012.

  • Schmitt, M. N. (2005). Precision attack and international humanitarian law. International Review of the Red Cross, 87(859), 445–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schummer, J. (2001). Ethics of chemical synthesis. HYLE: International Journal for Philosophy of Chemistry, 7(2), 103–124. http://www.hyle.org/journal/issues/7/schummer.htm. Accessed 31 Jan 2012.

  • Simonis, F., Schilthuizen, S. (2006) Nanotechnology: Innovation opportunities for tomorrow’s defence. TNO Science and Industry. www.futuretechnologycenter.nl. Update 2009: http://www.isoconnectors.com/defensie/. Accessed 22 Sept 2011.

  • Üzümcü, A. (2010). Future challenges of the OPCW. Address by Ambassador Ahmet Üzümcü, Director General OPCW, Global Security Research Institute, Keio University, Tokyo, Japan. http://www.opcw.org/search/?search=future. Accessed 22 Sept 2011.

  • Van der Bruggen, K. (2011) Part A: Possibilities or Intentions: The concept of Dual Use reconsidered. In S. Miller, M. Selgelid & K. van der Bruggen, Report on Biosecurity and Dual Use Research; A report for the Dutch Research Council. Delft: 3TU Centre for Ethics. www.ethicsandtechnology.eu

  • van den Hoven, J., & Vermaas, P. (2007). Nano-technology and privacy: On continuous surveillance outside the panopticum. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 32(3), 283–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vlandas, A. (2006) Managing nanotechnology. SGR Newsletter, 32. http://www.sgr.org.uk/resources/managing-nanotechnology Accessed 1 Mar 2011.

  • Walzer, M. (1977). Just and unjust wars: A moral argument with historical illustrations. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G. (2009). Responsibility. The internet encyclopaedia of philosophy, Last updated 9 March 2009. Originally published, 19 July 2006. http://www.iep.utm.edu/responsi/. Accessed 15 Oct 2010.

  • Wils, J.-P. (2007). Dubbel effect. In M. Becker, B. van Stokkom, P. van Tongeren, J.-P. Wils, & L. van de Ethiek (Eds.), Assen: Van Gorcum.

Download references

Acknowledgments

The collection of empirical data on technological trends, foresight, policymakers and stakeholder discussions and ethical and social science literature was supported by the EU in the ObservatoryNano project no. 218528. Comments and suggestions on an earlier version of this article by Marcel Becker and Wim Pelt and an anonymous reviewer are gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ineke Malsch.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Malsch, I. The Just War Theory and the Ethical Governance of Research. Sci Eng Ethics 19, 461–486 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-012-9357-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-012-9357-8

Keywords

Navigation