Skip to main content
Log in

An Analysis of the Impact of Brain-Computer Interfaces on Autonomy

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Research conducted on Brain-Computer Interfaces (BCIs) has grown considerably during the last decades. With the help of BCIs, users can (re)gain a wide range of functions. Our aim in this paper is to analyze the impact of BCIs on autonomy. To this end, we introduce three abilities that most accounts of autonomy take to be essential: (1) the ability to use information and knowledge to produce reasons; (2) the ability to ensure that intended actions are effectively realized (control); and (3) the ability to enact intentions within concrete relationships and contexts. We then consider the impact of BCI technology on each of these abilities. Although on first glance, BCIs solely enhance self-determination because they restore or improve abilities, we will show that there are other positive, but also negative impacts on user autonomy, which require further philosophical and ethical discussions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In the following we will refer to the more direct/invasive feedback methods when discussing closed loop BCIs.

  2. While it makes sense conceptually to distinguish between passive and (re-)active BCIs, this distinction might not be clear in real-world applications [35]. Implications of passive BCIs become especially troubling in settings where signals like a P300 might be used to extract information from a user that she or he does not actively want to share, see [40, 41].

  3. The term ‘self-determination’ indicates less strong conditions because a rule or law is absent, contrary to ‘autonomy’. A strong and normatively not neutral conception of autonomy as moral self-rule can be traced back to Kant’s account of autonomy, where moral reasoning according to principles that allow for universalizing the maxims of actions is required [44]. We think that the distinction between ‘self-determination’ and ‘autonomy’ is reasonable in many discussions of bioethics and should be made clear more often. Nevertheless, we will use both terms synonymously here, since the distinction is not relevant for the specific aim of this paper. Further, we do not discuss here, how Kant’s understanding of autonomy and of human dignity that must be ascribed to all beings capable of reason, can be reconciled with considering sub-abilities of autonomy. We presuppose that they can build two compatible perspectives on human autonomy.

  4. Volitions usually refer to some ‘inner activity’, with the power of producing changes of the world, usually including bodily movements [45]. Acting in accordance with one’s own reasons is a common presumption in current philosophical discussions about autonomy [46]. In the following, we will mostly refer to the term reasons, but we would like to avoid misunderstandings, which might result from the well-known controversy between philosophical traditions emphasizing the motivating force of reasons (e.g., Kant), or that of emotions or rather passions (e.g., Hume). Reasons can justify, motivate or explain an action; for many authors, reasons include the mental states of a pro-attitude and of a belief [47]. We do not use ‘reasons’ as a normatively laden term (as e.g., Kant) and do not want to neglect the role of emotions in motivating actions in the right way. The question what role emotions play and of how to control and cultivate the ‘right’, ethically appropriate emotions or affective states has been a key issue of discussions about autonomy throughout the history of philosophy, from Aristotle to Stoics, to Kant, etc. There is also a philosophical history, e.g., in the work of Husserl or Sartre, of conceptualizing emotions as intentional, as an important aspect of being in the world, and sometimes even as acts. We assume that emotions can influence non-consciously the attentional focus and decision-making, or the way an action is performed, and they can influence the modulation of behavioral dispositions [48, p. 58–63]. We won’t discuss it here, but we would say that emotions can not only influence in a non-conscious way (e.g., desires), but also inform our critical reflection, our evaluative judgments in important ways [48, 49]. Therefore, emotions also can be a relevant source of autonomous actions in reason-responsive conceptions of autonomy.

  5. Competence is a necessary condition in the conception of Beauchamp and Childress e.g., [57], which in accordance with the classic belief-desire model by Hume, is a property that is present when a person transforms her reasons into actions without external circumstances getting in the way, granted that these reasons are based on that person’s true beliefs. For Hume, it is clear that reasons have instrumental value and are the “slaves” of desires (or passions, in his terminology), which alone motivate our actions [62]. The endorsement of a person’s own reasons and the causal efficacy of her own reasons is also highly relevant, e.g., for coherentist conceptions of autonomy [50, 58, 59].

  6. There is an extensive and old debate about whether akratic actions exist at all and if so, how we can conceptualize them, see e.g., [63, 64].

  7. If we consider persons only as the product of social or external relations, there is little place for the ideas of the internalist conceptions of autonomy. It seems uncontroversial to suggest that individuals are influenced by social and external circumstances and to search for the autonomy-enabling external conditions is important in our view. Yet we grant space for the subject to gain distance from such influences, we find moderate accounts that still allow also for internalist conceptions of autonomy.

  8. As mentioned in Footnote 4, we do not use ‘reasons’ as a normatively laden term and furthermore do not exclude emotions in motivating actions in the right way.

  9. There are other activities where we focus on our brain activity (neuro-feedback training e.g.) in order to gain better results for a certain action.

  10. BCI applications that allow for a better perception of emotions compared to unaided humans is speculative. Nevertheless, emotion perception via BCI already is an aim of current research [39].

  11. Such BCIs could be described for all types, active, reactive and passive and such intelligent systems are under development; see e.g., [67].

  12. There are strong similarities here to the recent discussions of nudging, see e.g., [68, 69] and to discussions of restrictions of choice due to (non-conscious) manipulation [70].

  13. Similar questions have recently been discussed for closed-loop scenarios in BCIs [34, 72]. Goering et al. have pointed out that the user’s agency and autonomy can be undermined if she doubts her authorship of an action due to the way the machine operates [34].

  14. This is analogous to cases where DBS patients sometimes have to choose between symptom relief and neurological or psychological side effects [73].

  15. BCIs could then also be interpreted as an unusual technological option for ‘technologies of the self’, i.e. practices that are supposed to allow a person to gain a productive distance from her passions and desires, in order to augment the ability to carry out intended actions. Practices (usually not in combination with technologies like BCI) to control desires and passions in order to live a self-determined life have been discussed in philosophy since the ancient times, e.g., by Aristotle, the Stoics and in the last century by Foucault.

References

  1. Shih, J.J., D.J. Krusienski, and J.R. Wolpaw. 2012. Brain-computer interfaces in medicine. Mayo Clinic Proceedings 87 (3): 268–279.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Li, G., and D. Zhang. 2017. Brain-computer interface controlling cyborg: A functional brain-to-brain interface between human and cockroach. In Brain-computer interface research. A state-of-the-art summary 4, ed. Christoph Guger, Gernot Müller-Putz, and Brendan Allison, 71–79. Cham: Springer International Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Bouton, C.E., A. Shaikhouni, N.V. Annetta, M.A. Bockbrader, D.A. Friedenberg, D.M. Nielson, G. Sharma, P.B. Sederberg, B.C. Glenn, and W.J. Mysiw. 2016. Restoring cortical control of functional movement in a human with quadriplegia. Nature 533 (7602): 247–250.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Winkler, R. 2017. Elon musk launches Neuralink to connect brains with computers. Wall Street Journal. https://www.wsj.com/articles/elon-musk-launches-neuralink-to-connect-brains-with-computers-1490642652. Accessed 29 Sept 2017.

  5. Chaudhary, U., N. Birbaumer, and A. Ramos-Murguialday. 2016. Brain-computer interfaces for communication and rehabilitation. Nature Reviews Neurology 12 (9): 513–525.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Marchetti, M., and K. Priftis. 2015. Brain–computer interfaces in amyotrophic lateral sclerosis: A metanalysis. Clinical Neurophysiology 126 (6): 1255–1263.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Käthner, I., S. Halder, C. Hintermüller, A. Espinosa, C. Guger, F. Miralles, E. Vargiu, S. Dauwalder, X. Rafael-Palou, and M. Solà. 2017. A multifunctional brain-computer interface intended for home use: An evaluation with healthy participants and potential end users with dry and gel-based electrodes. Frontiers in Neuroscience 11: 286.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Brunner, C., N. Birbaumer, B. Blankertz, D. Guger, A. Kübler, D. Mattia, J. del R. Millán, F. Miralles, A. Nijholt, E. Opisso, N. Ramsey, P. Salomon, and G.R. Müller-Putz. 2015. BNCI horizon 2020: Towards a roadmap for the BCI community. Brain-Computer Interfaces 2 (1): 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  9. De Mul, J., and B. van den Berg. 2011. Remote control: Human autonomy in the age of computer-mediated agency. In Law, human agency, and autonomic computing: The philosophy of law meets the philosophy of technology, ed. Mireille Hildebrandt and Antoinette Rouvroy, 46–64. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Racine, E., and S. Rousseau-Lesage. 2017. The voluntary nature of decision-making in addiction: Static metaphysical views versus epistemologically dynamic views. Bioethics 31 (5): 349–359.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Kallinikos, J. 2011. Technology and accountability: On autonomic computing and human agency. In Law, human agency, and autonomic computing: The philosophy of law meets the philosophy of technology, ed. Mireille Hildebrandt and Antoinette Rouvroy, 161–179. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Nietzsche, F.W. 1998. On the genealogy of morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Foucault, M. 1982. The subject and power. Critical Inquiry 8 (4): 777–795.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Mackenzie, C., and N. Stoljar. 2000. Relational autonomy: Feminist perspectives on automony, agency, and the social self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Kahneman, D. 2011. Thinking, fast and slow. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Verbeek, P.-P. 2011. Subject to technology on autonomic computing and human autonomy. In Law, human agency, and autonomic computing: The philosophy of law meets the philosophy of technology, ed. Mireille Hildebrandt and Antoinette Rouvroy, 27–46. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Graimann, B., B. Allison, and G. Pfurtscheller. 2009. Brain–computer interfaces: A gentle introduction. In Brain-computer interfaces, ed. Bernhard Graimann, Gert Pfurtscheller, and Brendan Allison, 1–27. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Daly, J.J., and J.R. Wolpaw. 2008. Brain–computer interfaces in neurological rehabilitation. Lancet Neurology 7 (11): 1032–1043.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Wolpaw, J.R., N. Birbaumer, D.J. McFarland, G. Pfurtscheller, and T.M. Vaughan. 2002. Brain–computer interfaces for communication and control. Clinical Neurophysiology 113 (6): 767–791.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Lebedev, M.A., and M.A. Nicolelis. 2006. Brain-machine interfaces: Past, present and future. Trends in Neurosciences 29 (9): 536–546.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Yuan, H., and B. He. 2014. Brain-computer interfaces using sensorimotor rhythms: Current state and future perspectives. IEEE Transactions on Bio-Medical Engineering 61 (5): 1425–1435.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Mak, J.N., and J.R. Wolpaw. 2009. Clinical applications of brain-computer interfaces: Current state and future prospects. IEEE Reviews in Biomedical Engineering 2: 187–199.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Schalk, G. 2010. Can electrocorticography (ECoG) support robust and powerful brain-computer interfaces? Frontiers in Neuroengineering 3: 9.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Oxley, T.J., N.L. Opie, S.E. John, G.S. Rind, S.M. Ronayne, T.L. Wheeler, J.W. Judy, A.J. McDonald, A. Dornom, and T.J. Lovell. 2016. Minimally invasive endovascular stent-electrode array for high-fidelity, chronic recordings of cortical neural activity. Nature Biotechnology 34: 320–327.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Salisbury, D.B., T.D. Parsons, K.R. Monden, Z. Trost, and S.J. Driver. 2016. Brain-computer interface for individuals after spinal cord injury. Rehabilitation Psychology 61 (4): 435–441.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Maksimenko, V.A., S. van Heukelum, V.V. Makarov, J. Kelderhuis, A. Lüttjohann, A.A. Koronovskii, A.E. Hramov, and G. van Luijtelaar. 2017. Absence seizure control by a brain computer interface. Scientific Reports 7: 2487.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Zafar, M.B., K.A. Shah, and H.A. Malik. 2017. Prospects of sustainable ADHD treatment through brain-computer interface systems. Paper presented at the 2017 Conference for Innovations in Electrical Engineering and Computational Technologies (ICIEECT) in Karachi, Pakistan.

  28. McFarland, D.J., J. Daly, C. Boulay, and M.A. Parvaz. 2017. Therapeutic applications of BCI technologies. Brain-Computer Interfaces 4 (1–2): 37–52.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ahn, M., M. Lee, J. Choi, and S.C. Jun. 2014. A review of brain-computer interface games and an opinion survey from researchers, developers and users. Sensors 14 (8): 14601–14633.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Grau, C., R. Ginhoux, A. Riera, T.L. Nguyen, H. Chauvat, M. Berg, J.L. Amengual, A. Pascual-Leone, and G. Ruffini. 2014. Conscious brain-to-brain communication in humans using non-invasive technologies. PLoS One 9 (8): e105225.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Rao, R.P.N., A. Stocco, M. Bryan, D. Sarma, T.M. Youngquist, J. Wu, and C.S. Prat. 2014. A direct brain-to-brain interface in humans. PLoS One 9 (11): e111332.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Alonso-Valerdi, L.M., R.A. Salido-Ruiz, and R.A. Ramirez-Mendoza. 2015. Motor imagery based brain–computer interfaces: An emerging technology to rehabilitate motor deficits. Neuropsychologia 79: 354–363.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Flesher, S.N., J.L. Collinger, S.T. Foldes, J.M. Weiss, J.E. Downey, E.C. Tyler-Kabara, S.J. Bensmaia, A.B. Schwartz, M.L. Boninger, and R.A. Gaunt. 2016. Intracortical microstimulation of human somatosensory cortex. Science Translational Medicine 8 (361): 361ra141.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Goering, S., E. Klein, D.D. Dougherty, and A.S. Widge. 2017. Staying in the loop: Relational agency and identity in next-generation DBS for psychiatry. AJOB Neuroscience 8 (2): 59–70.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Zander, T.O., and L.R. Krol. 2017. Team PhyPA: Brain-computer interfacing for everyday human-computer interaction. Periodica Polytechnica Electrical Engineering and Computer Science 61 (2): 209.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Gerjets, P., C. Walter, W. Rosenstiel, M. Bogdan, and T.O. Zander. 2014. Cognitive state monitoring and the design of adaptive instruction in digital environments: Lessons learned from cognitive workload assessment using a passive brain-computer interface approach. Frontiers in Neuroscience 8: 385.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Fan, J., J.W. Wade, A.P. Key, Z. Warren, and N. Sarkar. 2017. EEG-based affect and workload recognition in a virtual driving environment for ASD intervention. IEEE Transactions on Biomedical Engineering 99: 43–51. https://doi.org/10.1109/TBME.2017.2693157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Martel, A., S. Dahne, and B. Blankertz. 2014. EEG predictors of covert vigilant attention. Journal of Neural Engineering 11 (3): 035009.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Mühl, C., B. Allison, A. Nijholt, and G. Chanel. 2014. A survey of affective brain computer interfaces: Principles, state-of-the-art, and challenges. Brain-Computer Interfaces 1 (2): 66–84.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Martinovic, I., D. Davies, M. Frank, D. Perito, T. Ros, and D. Song. 2012. On the feasibility of side-channel attacks with brain-computer interfaces. Presented as part of the 21st USENIX Security Symposium, USENIX Security 12: 143–158.

  41. Bonaci, T., R. Calo, and H. J. Chizeck. 2014. App stores for the brain: Privacy & security in brain-computer interfaces. Proceedings of the IEEE 2014 International Symposium on Ethics in Engineering, Science, and Technology: 47.

  42. Mousavi, M., A.S. Koerner, Q. Zhang, E. Noh, and V.R. de Sa. 2017. Improving motor imagery BCI with user response to feedback. Brain-Computer Interfaces 4 (1–2): 74–86.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Feinberg, Joel. 1986. Harm to self. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Kant, I. 1997 [1785]. Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten [Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals]. In: Ak IV, ed. Mary Gregor, 387–436. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  45. Wilson G. and S. Samuel. 2016. Action. In: The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, winter 2016 edn., ed Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/action. Accessed 29 Sept 2017.

  46. Betzler, M. 2009. Authenticity and self-governance. In Emotions, ethics, and authenticity, ed. Mikko Salmela and Verena Mayer, 51–67. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Davidson, D. 1963. Actions, reasons, and causes. Journal of Philosophy 60 (23): 685–700.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Tappolet, Christine. 2016. Emotions, values, and agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Jones, K. 2003. Emotion, weakness of will, and the normative conception of agency. In Philosophy and the emotions, ed. Anthony Hatzimoysis, 181–200. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Dworkin, Gerald. 1988. The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Racine, E., D. Larivière-Bastien, E. Bell, A. Majnemer, and M. Shevell. 2013. Respect for autonomy in the healthcare context: Observations from a qualitative study of young adults with cerebral palsy. Child: Care, Health and Development 39 (6): 873–879.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Racine, E., and V. Dubljević. 2017. Behavioral and brain-based research on free moral agency: Threat or empowerment? In Neuroethics: Anticipating the future, ed. Judy Illes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Racine, E., and V. Dubljević. 2016. Porous or contextualized autonomy? Knowledge can empower autonomous moral agents. The American Journal of Bioethics 16 (2): 48–50.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Willett, C., E. Anderson, and D. Meyers. 2016. Feminist perspectives on the self. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/feminism-self/. Accessed 25 Feb 2018.

  55. Govier, T. 1993. Self-trust, autonomy, and self-esteem. Hypatia 8 (1): 99–120.

    Google Scholar 

  56. McLeod, C. 2002. Self-trust and reproductive autonomy. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Beauchamp, T., and L. Childress. 2009. Principles of biomedical ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Frankfurt, H.G. 1971. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy 68 (1): 5–20.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Quante, M. 2011. In defence of personal autonomy. Journal of Medical Ethics 37: 597–600.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Oshana, M. 1998. Personal autonomy and society. Journal of Social Philosophy 29: 81–102.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Christman, J. 1991. Autonomy and personal history. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (1): 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Hume, D.. 1975 [1739]. A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  63. Davidson, D. 1970. How is weakness of the will possible? In Moral concepts, ed. Joel Feinberg. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Stroud, S. 2014. Weakness of will. In: The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, spring 2014 edn., ed Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/weakness-will/. Accessed 29 Sept 2017.

  65. Guger, C., R. Spataro, B.Z. Allison, A. Heilinger, R. Ortner, W. Cho, and V. La Bella. 2017. Complete locked-in and locked-in patients: Command following assessment and communication with vibro-tactile P300 and motor imagery brain-computer interface tools. Frontiers in Neuroscience 11: 251.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Arpaly, N. 2000. On acting rationally against one’s best judgment. Ethics 110 (3): 488–513.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Wu, S.L., Y.T. Liu, T.Y. Hsieh, Y.Y. Lin, C.Y. Chen, C.H. Chuang, and C.T. Lin. 2017. Fuzzy integral with particle swarm optimization for a motor-imagery-based brain-computer interface. IEEE Transactions on Fuzzy Systems 25 (1): 21–28.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Bell, E., V. Dubljevic, and E. Racine. 2013. Nudging without ethical fudging: Clarifying physician obligations to avoid ethical compromise. American Journal of Bioethics 13 (6): 18–19.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Cohen, S. 2013. Nudging and informed consent. American Journal of Bioethics 13 (6): 3–11.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Kiesel, A., A. Wagener, W. Kunde, J. Hoffmann, A.J. Fallgatter, and C. Stöcker. 2006. Unconscious manipulation of free choice in humans. Consciousness and Cognition 15 (2): 397–408.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Ihde, D. 2011. Smart? Amsterdam urinals and autonomic computing. In Law, human agency, and autonomic computing: The philosophy of law meets the philosophy of technology, ed. Mireille Hildebrandt and Antoinette Rouvroy, 12–27. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Kellmeyer, P., T. Cochrane, O. Mueller, C. Mitchell, T. Ball, J.J. Fins, and N. Biller-Andorno. 2016. The effects of closed-loop medical devices on the autonomy and accountability of persons and systems. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25 (4): 623–633.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Glannon, W. 2014. Prostheses for the will. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience 8: 79.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Bargh, J.A., and T.L. Chartrand. 1999. The unberable automaticity of being. American Psychologist 54 (7): 462–479.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Schultze-Kraft, M., D. Birman, M. Rusconi, C. Allefeld, K. Görgen, S. Dähne, B. Blankertz, and J.-D. Haynes. 2016. The point of no return in vetoing self-initiated movements. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 113 (4): 1080–1085.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Tamburrini, G. 2009. Brain to computer communication: Ethical perspectives on interaction models. Neuroethics 2 (3): 137–149.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Grübler, G. 2011. Beyond the responsibility gap. Discussion note on responsibility and liability in the use of brain-computer interfaces. AI & Society 26 (4): 377–382.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Verbeek, P.-P. 2014. Some misunderstandings about the moral significance of technology. In The moral status of technical artefacts, ed. Peter-Paul Verbeek and Peter Kroes, 75–88. Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Verbeek, P.-P. 2008. Obstetric ultrasound and the technological mediation of morality: A postphenomenological analysis. Human Studies 31 (1): 11–26.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Kiran, A.H., and P.-P. Verbeek. 2010. Trusting our selves to technology. Knowledge, Technology, and Policy 23 (3–4): 409–427.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Van Den Eede, Y. 2015. Tracing the tracker: A postphenomenological inquiry into self-tracking technologies. In Postphenomenological investigations: Essays on human technology relations, ed. Robert Rosenberger and Peter-Paul Verbeek, 143–158. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Mittelstadt, B. D., P. Allo, M. Taddeo, S. Wachter, and L. Floridi. 2016. The ethics of algorithms: Mapping the debate. Big Data & Society 3 (2): 2053951716679679, 205395171667967.

Download references

Acknowledgments

Writing of this article was supported by a joint grant from the Federal Ministry of Education and Research (BMBF) in Germany, the Canadian Institutes of Health Research and the Fonds de recherche du Québec – Santé (European Research Projects on Ethical, Legal, and Social Aspects (ELSA) of Neurosciences) as well as a career award from the Fonds de recherche du Québec – Santé (ER). We would like to thank the anonymous reviewers for their in depth and constructive review of our paper and for very helpful comments, further we thank Stephanie Simpson, Rose Richards, Mary Clare O’Donnell and Christoph Bublitz for providing helpful comments on a previous version of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Orsolya Friedrich.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Friedrich, O., Racine, E., Steinert, S. et al. An Analysis of the Impact of Brain-Computer Interfaces on Autonomy. Neuroethics 14, 17–29 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-018-9364-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-018-9364-9

Keywords

Navigation