Skip to main content
Log in

Explaining understanding (or understanding explanation)

  • General Philosophy of Science
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In debates about the nature of scientific explanation, one theme repeatedly arises: that explanation is about providing understanding. However, the concept of understanding has only recently been explored in any depth, and this paper attempts to introduce a useful concept of understanding to that literature and explore it. Understanding is a higher level cognition, the recognition of connections between various pieces of knowledge. This conception can be brought to bear on the conceptual issues that have thus far been unclear in the literature. Though this notion of understanding is broad, explaining various concepts of explanation, it is robust enough to underwrite an objective and useful notion of explanation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. E.g., see Hempel (1965), Friedman (1974), Achinstein (1983), Salmon (1989), or Kitcher (1989).

  2. Trout uses “sense of understanding”, as does Ylikoski (2009), who differentiates it from understanding. I will adopt de Regt’s use of “feeling of understanding”, also used by Lipton (2009), who both differentiate it from understanding.

  3. Though I think that understanding is a type of knowledge, the definition of understanding I offer does not depend on that status, and most conclusions reached in this paper could be adapted without detriment if understanding were not a form of knowledge but a distinct, knowledge-like, epistemological achievement.

  4. Truth as a necessary condition for scientific explanation seems to be implicitly or explicitly shared by many authors writing on scientific explanation.

  5. In this paper, I have maintained a neutral position with regards to the nature of knowledge itself. For the most part, I have treated knowledge as propositional knowledge, but I think that this view of understanding is compatible with alternative non-propositional theories of knowledge. Indeed, some philosophers have argued that understanding is non-propositional (see Zagzebski (2001)). I do not think this distinguishes understanding from knowledge, it just highlights the possible distinction between propositional and non-propositional knowledge, which involves a separate debate, but one which does not directly affect the argument presented here.

  6. For example, see (Hempel and Oppenheim 1948; Scriven 1962; Salmon 1989; de Regt and Dieks 2005; Woodward 2009).

  7. See Gopnik (1998, p. 102), who argues that “explanation is to cognition as orgasm is to reproduction.” What motivates children and scientists to “experiment” and expend energy to develop and reorganize theories is the payoff, not in terms of long term goals of survival, but the “distinctive phenomenology of explanation.” The search for explanation is prompted by the “hmm” and the success rewarded by the “aha”.

  8. I do not want to challenge Lipton’s intuitions here, but I could imagine equally well-considered intuitions on the other side—e.g., that the thought experiment is explanatory. And I suspect there is a small but meaningful slippage in language from understanding the necessity of the phenomenon to explaining the phenomenon itself. If those are made consistent, the discrepancy might disappear. I do not think this is any easy question to answer, since it depends a great deal on intuitions about what is and is not an explanation and understanding.

References

  • Achinstein, P. (1983). The nature of explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R. (2008). Innate ideas revisited: for a principle of persistence in infants’ physical reasoning. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 2–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corsini, R. J. (2002). The dictionary of psychology. New York: Brunner-Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cushing, J. T. (1991). Quantum theory and explanatory discourse: endgame for understanding? Philosophy of Science, 58, 337–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W. (2004). Discussion note: making sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 71, 98–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W. (2009). Understanding and scientific explanation. In H. W. de Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 21–42). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. W., & Dieks, D. (2005). A contextual approach to scientific understanding. Synthese, 144, 137–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philosophy, 5–19.

  • Gopnik, A. (1998). Explanation as orgasm. Minds and Machines, 8, 101–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. (2011). Causality. In P. Zelano (Ed.) The Oxford handbook of developmental psychology. New York: Oxford University Press, p. (In Press).

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15, 135–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher & W. Salmon (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 13 (pp. 410–503). Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T., & Merz, M. (2009). Understanding and modeling: An objectual approach. In H. W. de Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 146–168). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Legare, C. H., Gelman, S. A., & Wellman, H. M. (2010). Inconsistency with prior knowledge triggers children’s causal explanatory reasoning. Child Development, 81, 929–944.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2009). Understanding without explanation. In H. W. de Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 43–63). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2009). Knowledge, understanding and epistemic value. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Epistemology: Royal Institute of philosophy supplement: 64. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (1981). Probability, explanation, and information. Synthese, 48, 233–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1989). Four decades of scientific explanation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scriven, M. (1962). Explanation, prediction, and laws. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific explanation, space, and time (pp. 170–230). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. S. (1994). Initial knowledge: six suggestions. Cognition, 50, 431–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J. D. (2002). Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 69, 212–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J. D. (2007). The psychology of scientific explanation. Philosophy Compass, pp. 564–591.

  • Van Camp, W. (2011). Principle theories, constructive theories, and explanation in modern physics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 42, 23–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2009). Scientific explantion. [Online] Available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scientific-explanation/ [Accessed 24 May 2013].

  • Ylikoski, P. (2009). The illusion of depth of understanding in science. In H. W. de Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 100–119). Pittsurgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (2001). Recovering understanding. In M. Steup (Ed.), Knowledge, truth, and duty (pp. 235–251). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wesley Van Camp.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Van Camp, W. Explaining understanding (or understanding explanation). Euro Jnl Phil Sci 4, 95–114 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-013-0077-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-013-0077-y

Keywords

Navigation