Skip to main content
Log in

Derivational robustness, credible substitute systems and mathematical economic models: the case of stability analysis in Walrasian general equilibrium theory

  • Original Paper in Philosophy of Economics
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper supports the literature which argues that derivational robustness can have epistemic import in highly idealized economic models. The defense is based on a particular example from mathematical economic theory, the dynamic Walrasian general equilibrium model. It is argued that derivational robustness first increased and later decreased the credibility of the Walrasian model. The example demonstrates that derivational robustness correctly describes the practices of a particular group of influential economic theorists and provides support for the arguments of philosophers who have offered a general epistemic justification of such practices.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There is not complete agreement on how exactly the terms “idealization” and “isolation” should be used in these discussions. See Morgan (2012, pp. 137, 158) and Morgan and Knuuttila (2012, p. 51) on this issue.

  2. Influential defenders of the isolationist account in the recent literature on economic models include Nancy Cartwight (e.g., 1991) and Uskali Mäki (e.g., 1994, 2009a).

  3. A substitute system is Mäki’s term for a model that is “a freely floating subject of inquiry, unconstrained by any real concern as to how it might be connected to real world facts” and they are “strong failures of representation” (Mäki 2009b, p. 36). For Mäki the alternative to a substitute system is a surrogate system that adequately represents (or at least is intended to represent) the relevant target, but many would argue there is a third alternative – I will use the term credible-substitute models—that do tell us something about certain aspects of the economic world. We learn from them, make inferences with them, and assess credibility-increasing and credibility-decreasing moves within them, while they still tell us less about real economies than fully representational models.

  4. The word “competing” needs to be clarified here. Most who support some version of a fictionalist account would agree that certain economic models do satisfy the requirements of the isolationist account. The problem is that many do not, and these models are often the most influential work economists produce. The problem is not that the isolationist view is incorrect, it is simply that it is not applicable to important theoretical modeling in economics, some of which, the defenders of fictionalist views assert, can also be justified. In other words, isolation may be sufficient for the success of models, but it is not necessary (Grüne-Yanoff 2011; Knuuttila 2009, 2011). Perhaps the best way to think about the issue is to draw an analogy with a much earlier debate in the philosophy of science. Ian Hacking once said that Popper took the positivist dichotomy of science vs. metaphysics/muck and converted it into the three-way distinction of science vs. metaphysics vs. muck (Hacking 1979, pp. 384–385). Similarly, we could replace the isolationist dichotomy of surrogate vs. substitute/muck with an alternative three-way distinction of surrogate vs. credible substitute vs. muck.

  5. The fictionalist view is sometimes called constructionist, but I will employ only the former term to avoid confusion with constructionist views within the sociology of science.

  6. Contributions to this literature include: Cartwright 2009; de Rodríguez and Zamora Bonilla 2009; Grüne-Yanoff 2009a, 2009b, 2011, 2013; Knuuttila 2005, 2009, 2011; Kuorikoski and Lehtinen 2009; Mäki 2009b, 2013; Morgan and Knuuttila 2012; Sugden 2000, 2009; and Weisberg 2007, 2013.

  7. This is a modified version of the characterization of robustness in Odenbaugh and Alexandrova, (2011, p. 764).

  8. The recent literature supporting various types of robustness analysis in economics includes: Guala and Salanti 2003; Kuorikoski and Lehtinen 2009; Kuorikoski et al. 2010, 2012; Lehtinen and Kuorikoski 2007; Lehtinen and Marchionni 2011; Weisberg 2013; and Woodward 2006. For critical remarks on robustness analysis see Cartwright (1991, 2007, 2009), Odenbaugh and Alexandrova (2011), and Reiss (2012). It should be noted that robustness analysis is also an important topic in the philosophy of biology (particularly in systems biology and ecology) and many of the papers discussing robustness in economics also consider biology. I will only be concerned with economics.

  9. “By a model ‘result’ we mean any proposition derivable from a model that is thought to be epistemically or cognitively important in the appropriate scientific community” (Kuorikoski et al. 2010, p. 545).

  10. The assumptions of a perfectly competitive economy also demonstrate how difficult it is to classify the various types of assumptions used in economic models (i.e., how a single assumption can play multiple roles). The key assumption of price-taking behavior is a substantive assumption about the behavior of the agents in the model (and is approximated by some real world agents), yet it is also a very effective tractability assumption since taking prices as parameters greatly simplifies the application of differential calculus to such models.

  11. Attention was given to perfect competition in the work on idealization in economics published in the 1980s and 1990s (e.g., Hamminga 1983 and various papers in Hamminga and De Marchi 1994), but it has received much less attention in the recent literature. Mäki (2001) discusses perfect competition, but from the viewpoint of three economists who criticize it.

  12. McKenzie (2002) provides a fairly recent survey of this type of general equilibrium theory, Quirk and Saposnik (1968) is a text from the period that emphasized stability, and Hahn (1982) provides a useful survey. See Ingrao and Israel (1990) for historical discussion.

  13. For our purposes we can assume p* > 0.

  14. Other specifications were used in the literature such as dpi/dt = kiZi(p) with ki > 0 and dpi/dt = Hi[Zi(p)] with Hi’ > 0, but these differences can be neglected here. These, like (T), are systems of ordinary differential equations where prices change in the direction of excess demand.

  15. Takayama’s symbolism was changed to be consistent with the symbolism used in this paper.

  16. I note in passing that these concerns did motivate economists to try to develop models without some of the undesirable features of (T) – in particular to allow for disequilibrium trading—but the research project was never very successful: see chapter thirteen of Arrow and Hahn (1971) for a survey of the results at that time.

  17. This belief can be thought of as what Mäki calls the ontological way the world works (www) constraint on scientific theorizing. Various scientific communities (and research programs within those communities) have commitments to particular “causal processes that constitute the ways the world works” (Mäki 2001, p. 371) and for most economists that commitment was (and is) to the rational actions of individual agents, not central planners or mechanisms that represent the behavior of a central planner, as the ultimate cause of market phenomena.

  18. See Hands and Mirowski (1998) and the references therein for a discussion of these various testing efforts.

  19. One might think about this as an example of the hierarchy of models (Suppes 1962, 1967), but I will not pursue this idea here.

  20. There is also an argument that robustness analysis in general is only relevant to directional changes, but commitment to this view is not necessary for the argument offered here.

  21. Being a Giffen good means that the good is inferior (consumption decreases with increases in income) and given the budget constraint associated with the standard utility-maximization problem, not all goods can be inferior.

  22. Kuorikoski, Lehtinen and Marchionni do recognize that an assumptions that have dual roles—“a single explicitly stated modelling assumption may simultaneously encode a tractability assumption as well as a substantial assumption” (2010, p. 548)—but do not have a separate category for such assumptions or explicitly define the property of having an economic interpretation.

  23. “There seem to be no examples in the literature of utility and production functions which yield diagonal dominance other than of course the GS case” (Hahn 1982, p. 759)

  24. The most important papers were Debreu (1974), Mantel (1974), and Sonnenschein (1972, 1973). See Shafer and Sonnenschein (1982) for a survey, and Hands (2012), Ingrao and Israel (1990), and Rizvi (2006) for historical discussions.

References

  • Arrow, K. J. (1959). Toward a theory of price adjustment. In M. Abramovitz, A. Alchian, K. J. Arrow, et al. (Eds.), The allocation of economic resources: Essays in honor of Bernard Francis Haley (pp. 41–51). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Arrow, K., & Debreu, G. (1954). Existence of an equilibrium for a competitive economy. Econometrica, 22, 265–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J., & Hahn, F. H. (1971). General competitive analysis. San Francisco: Holden-Day.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J., & Hurwicz, L. (1958). On the stability of the competitive equilibrium I. Econometrica, 26, 522–552.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J., Block, H. D., & Hurwicz, L. (1959). On the stability of the competitive equilibrium II. Econometrica, 27, 82–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aydinonat, N. E. (2007). Models, conjectures and explanations: an analysis of schelling’s checkerboard model of residential segregation. Journal of Economic Methodology, 14, 429–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aydinonat, E. E., & Ylikoski, P. (2014). Understanding with theoretical models. Journal of Economic Methodology, 21, 19–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boumans, M. (2005). How economists model the world to numbers. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1991). Replicability, reproducibility, and robustness: comments on Harry Collins. History of Political Economy, 23, 143–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2007). Hunting causes and using them: Approaches in philosophy and economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2009). If no capacities then no credible worlds, but can models reveal capacities? Erkenntnis, 70, 45–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Rodríguez, D., & Zamora Bonilla, J. (2009). Credibility, idealization, and model building: an inferential approach. Erkenntnis, 70, 101–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G. (1959). Theory of value. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G. (1970). Economies with a finite set of equilibria. Econometrica, 38, 387–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G. (1974). Excess demand functions. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 1, 15–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott-Graves, A., & Weisberg, M. (2014). Idealization. Philosophy Compass, 9, 176–185.

  • Gale, d. (1963). A note on global instability of competitive equilibrium. Naval Research Logistics Quarterly, 10, 81–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A., & Varian, H. R. (1978). Economic models. Journal of Philosophy, 75, 664–677.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2009a). Preface to ‘economic models as credible worlds or as isolating tools. Erkenntnis, 70, 1–2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2009b). Learning from minimal models. Erkenntnis, 70, 81–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2011). Isolation is not characteristic of models. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 25, 119–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2013). Appraising models nonrepresentationally. Philosophy of Science, 80, 850–861.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guala, F., & Salanti, A. (2003). Model robustness in the ‘old’ and ‘new’ growth theory. In N. Salvadori (Ed.), Old and new growth theories: An assessment (pp. 115–126). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1979). Imre Lakatos’s philosophy of science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 30, 381–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, F. H. (1958). Gross substitutes and the dynamic stability of general equilibrium. Econometrica, 26, 169–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, F. H. (1982). “Stability,” in Handbook of mathematical economics, vol. II, Arrow, K. J. and Intriligator M. D (eds.), Amsterdam: North-Holland, 745–793.

  • Hamminga, B. (1983). Neoclassical theory structure and theory development. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hamminga, B., & De Marchi, N. (1994). Idealization and the defense of economics: Notes toward a history. In B. Hamminga & N. De Marchi (Eds.), Idealization VI: Idealization in economics (pp. 11–40). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hands, D. W. (2012). “What a difference a sum (∑) makes: success and failure in the rationalization of demand. Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 34, 379–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hands, D. W., & Mirowski, P. (1998). Harold hotelling and the neoclassical dream. In R. Backhouse, D. Hausman, U. Mäki, & A. Salanti (Eds.), Economics and methodology: Crossing boundaries (pp. 322–397). London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hicks, J. R. (1939). Value and capital: An inquiry into some fundamental principles of economic theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hildenbrand, W. (1994). Market demand: Theory and empirical evidence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ingrao, B., & Israel, G. (1990). The invisible hand: Economic equilibrium in the history of science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T. (2005). Models, representation, and mediation. Philosophy of Science, 72, 1260–1271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T. (2009). Isolating representations versus credible constructions? economic modeling in theory and practice. Erkenntnis, 70, 59–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T. (2011). Modelling and representing: an artefactual appproach to model-based representation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 42, 262–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J., & Lehtinen, A. (2009). Incredible worlds, credible results. Erkenntnis, 119–131.

  • Kuorikoski, J., Lehtinen, A., & Marchionni, C. (2010). Economic modelling as robustness analysis. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, 541–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J., Lehtinen, A., & Marchionni, C. (2012). Robustness analysis disclaimer: please read manual before use! Biology and Philosophy, 61, 891–902.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, O. (1944). Price flexibility and employment. Bloomington: The Principia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehtinen, A., & Kuorikoski, J. (2007). Unrealistic assumptions in rational choice theory. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 27, 891–902.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehtinen, A & Marchionni, C (2011). “Generality in economic models,” Working Paper.

  • Lucas, R. E. (1989). Studies in business-cycle theory. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U (1994). Isolation, idealization and truth in economics. In Idealization VI: Idealization in Economics. B. Hamminga and N. De Marchi (eds.), 147–168 [Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of Science and the Humanities, 38].

  • Mäki, U. (2001). The way the world works (www): towards an ontology of theory choice. In The Economic World View: Studies in the Ontology of Economics (pp. 369–389). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Mäki, U. (2009a). Realistic realism about unrealistic models. In H. Kincaid & D. Ross (Eds.), Oxford handbook of the philosophy of economics (pp. 68–98). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (2009b). MISSing the world. models as isolations and credible surrogate systems. Erkenntnis, 70, 29–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (2013). Contested modeling: The case of economics. In U. Gähde, S. Hartmann, & J. H. Wolf (Eds.), Models, simulations, and the reduction of complexity (pp. 87–116). Berlin: Walter DeGruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mantel, R. R. (1974). On the characterization of aggregate excess demand. Journal of Economic Theory, 7, 348–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenzie, L. W. (1960). Stability of equilibrium and the value of positive excess demand. Econometrica, 28, 606–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenzie, L. W. (2002). Classical general equilibrium theory. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M. S. (2001). Models, stories and the economic world. Journal of Economic Methodology, 8, 361–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M. S. (2012). The world in the model: How economists work and think. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M. S., & Knuuttila, T. (2012). Models and modelling in economics. In U. Mäki (Ed.), Handbook of the philosophy of science, vol. 13, philosophy of economics (pp. 49–87). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Negishi, T. (1958). A note on the stability of an economy where all goods are gross substitutes. Econometrica, 26, 445–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, P. (1959). Some notes on stability conditions. Review of Economic Studies, 26, 1–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J., & Alexandrova, A. (2011). Buyer beware: robustness analysis in economics and biology. Biology and Philosophy, 26, 757–771.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patinkin, D. (1965). Money, interest, and prices: An integration of monetary and value theory (2nd ed.). New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quirk, J., & Saposnik, R. (1968). Introduction to general equilibrium theory and welfare economics. New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J. (2012). The explanatory paradox. Journal of Economic Methodology, 19, 43–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizvi, S., & Turab, A. (2006). The Sonnenschein-Mantel-Debreu results after thirty years. In P. Mirowski & D. W. Hands (Eds.), Agreement on demand: Consumer theory in the twentieth century (pp. 228–45). Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. A. (1941). The stability of equilibrium: comparative statics and dynamics. Econometrica, 9, 97–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. A. (1942). The stability of equilibrium: linear and non-linear systems. Econometrica, 10, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. A. (1947). Foundations of economic analysis. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarf, H. (1960). Some Examples of Global Instability of the Competitive Equilibrium. International Economic Review, 1, 157–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. (1978). Micromotives and macrobehavior. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer, W & Sonnenschein, H (1982). “Market excess demand functions,” in handbook of mathematical economics, vol. II, K. J. Arrow and M. D. Intriligator (eds.), Amsterdam: North-Holland, 671–93.

  • Smale, S. (1976). A convergent process of price adjustment as global newton methods. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 3, 211–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sonnenschein, H. (1972). Market excess demand functions. Econometrica, 40, 549–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sonnenschein, H. (1973). Do Walras’ identity and continuity characterize the class of community excess demand functions? Journal of Economic Theory, 6, 345–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2000). Credible worlds: the status of theoretical models in economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 7, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2009). Credible worlds, capacities and mechanisms. Erkenntnis, 70, 3–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1962). Models of data. In E. Nagel, P. Suppes, & A. Tarski (Eds.), Logic, methodology, and philosophy of science: Proceedings of the 1960 international congress (pp. 252–261). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1967). What is a scientific theory?”. In S. Morgenbesser (Ed.), Philosophy of science today (pp. 55–67). New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takayama, A. (1974). Mathematical economics. Hinsdale: The Dryden Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walras, L (1954). Elements of pure economics. translated by W. Jaffé from the 4th definitive edition, 1926, Homewood, IL: Richard D. Irwin [first edition 1874, Augustus M. Kelley reprint 1977].

  • Weisberg, M. (2007). Three kinds of idealization. Journal of Philosophy, 104, 639–659.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Woodford, M. (2003). Interest and prices: Foundations of a theory of monetary policy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2006). Some varieties of robustness. The Journal of Economic Methodology, 13, 219–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to D. Wade Hands.

Additional information

Helpful comments on earlier drafts were received from Aki Lehtinen, Caterina Marchionni, and two anonymous referees.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hands, D.W. Derivational robustness, credible substitute systems and mathematical economic models: the case of stability analysis in Walrasian general equilibrium theory. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 6, 31–53 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-015-0130-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-015-0130-0

Keywords

Navigation