Unanimity and majority rule: the calculus of consent reconsidered*

https://doi.org/10.1016/S0176-2680(98)00002-0Get rights and content

Abstract

Economists and political scientists have long debated the socially optimal proportion of a collective decision-making body whose consent should be required in order to reach a decision. In their classic contribution to this debate, Buchanan and Tullock [Buchanan, J.M., Tullock, G., 1962. The Calculus of Consent. Univ. of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor] argued that, in the absence of what they called `decision-making costs', the unanimity rule is socially optimal. The present paper shows that their approach actually leads to the conclusion that the unanimity rule is (almost always) suboptimal. In contrast, simple majority rule—the rule most commonly observed in collective decisions—is found to be socially optimal under plausible conditions.

Introduction

A long-debated issue in the literature of economics and political science is the socially optimal proportion of a collective decision-making body whose consent should be required in order to reach a decision. Buchanan and Tullock (1962)argued in a classic contribution that, in the absence of what they called `decision-making costs', the unanimity rule is socially optimal. Yet casual observation suggests that the simple majority rule is the rule adopted in most committees, legislatures, and popular elections.1 The present paper provides a formal analysis of the optimal collective decision rule, based on the approach of Buchanan and Tullock. It is shown that their approach actually leads to the conclusion that the unanimity rule is (almost always) suboptimal. In contrast, simple majority rule is found to be socially optimal under plausible conditions.

It should be noted at the outset that two different criteria have been used (by two distinct literatures) in the study of collective decision rules. The first criterion is efficiency—this is the criterion used by Buchanan and Tullock (1962). An efficient decision rule maximizes the likelihood that all Kaldor–Hicks efficient proposals are accepted, while all inefficient proposals are rejected. The second criterion may be called stability or `decisiveness': the decision rule should not permit Arrow-type cycles. In binary choices (in which Arrow-type cycles are impossible), the rule should produce a well-defined preference ordering over the two alternatives open to the decision-making body. The criterion of stability is the criterion studied by the voluminous social choice literature.

The present paper combines these two criteria. It is postulated that the socially optimal rule must be efficient, subject to the constraint that it be stable. As Arrow (1951)proved, it is impossible, in general, for a democratic decision rule to satisfy the stability criterion. However, if the number of alternatives is restricted to two, then the stability problem reduces to the problem of pairwise decisiveness (May, 1952). Requiring at least a simple majority suffices to guarantee that a decision rule is pairwise decisive. In order to simplify the analysis and still insure that the stability criterion can be met, we will restrict attention to binary (two-alternative) choices.

The analysis can be extended to decision problems having more than two alternatives, by increasing the lower bound on the required majority rule—provided that voters vote for the proposal closest to their ideal point in Euclidean issue space, and that the density of voters' ideal points is concave. Caplin and Nalebuff (1988)proved that, under these two conditions, there is a lower bound on the required majority rule which guarantees stability; this lower bound rises to a limit of just under 64% as the number of dimensions in the issue space rises to infinity. Note, however, that the Caplin–Nalebuff result is concerned only with the stability criterion.2 In contrast, the present analysis focuses [as Buchanan and Tullock (1962)did] on the relative efficiency of alternative decision rules; my departure from the approach of Buchanan and Tullock is only in requiring that the recommended rule be stable as well as efficient.

Section 2lays the groundwork of the analysis, and presents an intuitive, diagrammatic argument for the inefficiency of the unanimity rule. Section 3formally develops a sufficient condition for the optimality of simple majority rule in binary collective choices. Section 4shows that this sufficient condition is plausible in a simplified model of legislative allocation of public funds for the provision of collective goods demanded by interest groups. Section 5shows that the fact that Buchanan and Tullock (1962)did not arrive at the same result is not due to any difference in assumptions, but rather stems from a subtle inconsistency in their analysis. Once this inconsistency is removed, their model would produce the same result. Section 6concludes the paper.

Section snippets

Preliminaries

We envisage a collective decision-making body, for example, a committee or legislature, consisting of N members. This committee is faced with an exogenously determined set of M independent, binary proposals. For example, it must decide whether to allocate funds to a set of projects whose details (such as the costs and scope of each proposal) were already determined in advance, and the only question is whether to approve or reject the proposals. Before deciding on these M proposals, the

Determining the socially optimal decision rule

Let there be an exogenously determined proposal set, consisting of M independent, binary proposals, indexed by j (j=1,…,M). Each proposal j is supported by a group of members of the decision-making body, whose size, relative to the N-membered decision-making body is sj∈[1/N,1]. Let the number of proposals whose proponent-groups are of size s be m(s). Moreover, let the net value to these proponents of their proposals, for a given group size s, when averaged over all proposals whose

Application: a model of legislative allocation of collective funds

The preceding analysis showed that: (a) the unanimity rule is (almost) never socially optimal, and (b) simple majority rule is socially optimal if νc. How plausible is the condition that νc? In order to answer this question, we analyze a generic public choice problem very similar to that studied by Buchanan and Tullock at a number of points in The Calculus of Consent.7

Let the decision-making body (the `legislature'),

The Buchanan–Tullock model

In this section, we reconsider the model of Buchanan and Tullock (1962)in the light of the preceding analysis. This reconsideration of their model is of interest not only to historians of economic thought. The model of Buchanan and Tullock (1962)is widely used in courses in public economics and public choice. We begin with an overview of the model, and then discuss two possible reasons for the result they obtained.

Concluding remarks

We have found that the assumptions underlying The Calculus of Consent lead to the conclusion that the unanimity rule is suboptimal, while the simple majority rule is optimal under plausible conditions. The conclusion of Buchanan and Tullock (1962), that the unanimity rule is optimal in the absence of decision-making costs, was shown to be the result of an inconsistency in their analysis. Simply stated, this inconsistency is the asymmetrical treatment of type-I and type-II errors in collective

Acknowledgements

An earlier version of this paper was presented at the 1994 meeting of the European Public Choice Society in Valencia, Spain. I am grateful to my former students Ofer Almogi and S. Sheinenzon for their insightful questions, which led to the writing of this paper. I also thank James M. Buchanan and Gordon Tullock for their comments on an earlier draft of this paper, while retaining responsibility for all remaining errors.

References (15)

  • G.H Kramer

    A dynamical model of political equilibrium

    J. Econ. Theory

    (1977)
  • Arrow, K.J., 1951. Social Choice and Individual Values. Wiley, New...
  • Buchanan, J.M., Tullock, G., 1962. The Calculus of Consent. Univ. of Michigan Press, Ann...
  • A Caplin et al.

    On 64%-majority rule

    Econometrica

    (1988)
  • J.C Harsanyi

    Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons of utility

    J. Polit. Econ.

    (1955)
  • J.R Hicks

    The foundations of welfare economics

    Econ. J.

    (1939)
  • N Kaldor

    Welfare propositions of economics and interpersonal comparisons of utility

    Econ. J.

    (1939)
There are more references available in the full text version of this article.

Cited by (26)

  • The option to wait in collective decisions and optimal majority rules

    2012, Journal of Public Economics
    Citation Excerpt :

    The results of this section are very surprising: a high value of γ removes the technological links between periods (i.e., society can simply terminate projects that were implemented earlier, without incurring large expected termination cost, at least if γ is close to 1). Why does this not mean that we are getting closer and closer to a purely static setting in which we know from Guttman (1998) that – with a sufficiently symmetric setup, as we have assumed here – simple majority rule is optimal? Instead, society optimally uses supermajority rules that are even larger than in the basic model and that introduce institutional links between periods when there are fewer technological links (i.e., for γ > 0).

  • Dynamic pivotal politics

    2018, American Political Science Review
View all citing articles on Scopus
View full text