Abduction 101: Reasoning processes to aid discovery

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.hrmr.2016.08.007Get rights and content

Abstract

We propose that the process of abduction is a useful tool for how management scholars can better develop new explanatory hypotheses and theories. In doing so, we differentiate abduction from the more commonly studied methods of deduction and induction. We briefly explain the various research streams on abductive reasoning and propose a version that is focused more on the process of abductive reasoning and less on the outcomes. We argue that by using contrastive reasoning and by recognizing different triggers of abduction, this process can help guide researchers to the types of causal explanations that are interesting. We conclude with some examples of abduction in the history of management research and a discussion of features of the reasoning processes involved.

Introduction

A Greek word, ἀπαγωγή, is in this sentence. You suspect its presence is related to this special issue's topic—induction. To reach that tentative conclusion, however, you did not do what's ordinarily called induction. It was not an inference based on accumulated evidence, not reasoning from the specific to the general. Nor was it a deductive inference, a conclusion entailed by its premises. Indeed, it was only a reasonable inference, not a definitive conclusion. What makes it reasonable? If it turns out to be true, for example, you won't say “Wow, what a lucky guess!” or “What an amazing coincidence!” In essence a tacit reasoning process led you to form a plausible hypothesis (“I'll bet that Greek word is in some way related to induction”), and ἀπαγωγή has been used as a label for such processes. Understanding how they function will aid conceptual developments in the study of management, and that is what accounts for the otherwise puzzling appearance of a Greek word in our opening sentence.

That word refers to abduction, which Aristotle included with induction and deduction as one of three types of inferences. His spelling of the first two—ἀπαγωγή, for abduction, and ἐπαγωγή, for induction—differs only by an initial letter, whereas the spelling of deduction—συλλoγισμ'oς—does not share a single letter with either of them (Magnani, 2015). The following section portrays the relations among these three types of inferences in a manner consistent with those Greek spellings. We first describe a feature unique to deduction, placing induction and abduction into the shared category of inferences lacking that feature. We discuss how induction and abduction represent variations in this type of inference and then indicate how abduction differs from induction despite sharing the feature of being non-deductive. Next, we describe various forms of abduction, focusing on the process of abductive reasoning rather than the product of it. Singling out one in particular, we describe best-practice uses of it.

Section snippets

Differences among deduction, induction, and abduction

Alive humans breathe. The editors of this special issue are alive, so it is a deductively logical conclusion that they breathe. Once the premises of an argument are accepted as true (viz., that all living humans breathe; that the editors are living humans), deductive inferences are a matter of logical necessity. Unfortunately, this self-contained aspect comes at a price: Inferred conclusions from deductive reasoning add nothing to what is already present in their premises. Breathing is a

Prior views: over-emphasizing abduction as product rather than process

Discussions of abduction can focus on process or product (Aliseda, 2006). Product refers to the outcome of abductive thinking—an explanation. Process is the activity whereby such arguments/explanations take shape (cf. Cornelissen & Durand, 2014). Aliseda (2006) describes the distinction as the conditions that give abductions explanatory power (product) and the types of algorithms that produce explanations (process). Harman (1965) and Lipton (2004), for example, adopted a product outlook in

Toward process: fact versus foil and abductive triggers

Although Harman and Lipton conflated abduction with IBE (cf. Josephson, 2000, Ketokivi and Mantere, 2010), essentially ignoring the former, the wider literature reflects at least three perspectives: “Some researchers do not conceptually discriminate between IBE and abduction or use the term ‘abduction’ as standing for IBE…, but this is wrong….Some others argue that IBE and abduction are conceptually distinct….The most accurate description of the relation between IBE and abduction is to state

Abduction in action: exemplars

As others have noted (Sutton and Staw, 1995, Weick, 1995) there is no cookie-cutter method for developing new theory. Below, however, we outline how some famous theories might have developed as a function of abductive inferences, focusing on abductive anomalies as triggers.

Features characteristic of abductive reasoning processes

The ways to carry out abductive reasoning (henceforth often called simply abductions) are not only multiple but also not easily cast in any kind of sequential pattern. As we lay out some suggestions about how abductions might proceed, therefore, these should not be considered as if they were stages of the process—or even that they are (necessarily) separable. Rather, they can blur together in ways other than what might be conveyed as we present them. The exception, of course, is that somehow

Conclusion

[I]t is crucial that we reach outside traditional notions of deduction and induction, and revisit Charles S. Peirce's third form of reasoning, which he called abduction. (Weick, 2006, p. 1731)

When Karl Weick in the above quotation called attention to Peirce and the importance of abduction, he continued by noting that “the conjectural paradigm, grounded in abductive reasoning, is the foundation of inquiry” (Weick, 2006, p. 1731). The irony is that this foundational piece has not received the

References (37)

  • R. Folger

    The road to fairness and beyond

  • J.E. Grusec

    Social learning theory and developmental psychology: The legacies of Robert Sears and Albert Bandura

    Developmental Psychology

    (1992)
  • N.R. Hanson

    Patterns of discovery, an inquiry into the conceptual foundations of science

    (1958)
  • G.H. Harman

    The inference to the best explanation

    The Philosophical Review

    (1965)
  • J.R. Josephson

    Smart inductive generalizations are abductions

  • M. Ketokivi et al.

    Two strategies for inductive reasoning in organizational research

    Academy of Management Review

    (2010)
  • P. Lipton

    Contrastive explanation and causal triangulation

    Philosophy of Science

    (1991)
  • P. Lipton

    Inference to the best explanation

    (2004)
  • Cited by (53)

    • Lock-ins to transition pathways anchored in contextualized cooperative dynamics: Insights from the historical trajectories of the Walloon dairy cooperatives

      2022, Journal of Rural Studies
      Citation Excerpt :

      On the base of the gathered historical material, the investigation provides an “inference to the best explanation” to this phenomenon (Folger and Stein 2017, 308). Abduction processes, in this regard, act on the register of speculation and fallibility rather than certainty (Catellin 2004; Folger and Stein 2017). However, such heuristic processes plays a role in defining further lines of inquiry, by outlining “what kinds of evidence might increase the prospects of further insights” into a phenomenon (Folger and Stein 2017, 307).

    • Managerial sensemaking of tensions in sustainability: Empirical evidence from Chinese and New Zealand business partnerships

      2021, Journal of Cleaner Production
      Citation Excerpt :

      Peirce generalised this idea to probabilistic inference, and elsewhere his logical account of reasoning was also linked with the analysis-of-figures interpretation analysis. As this study adopted abduction, hence, propositions have been generated to better illustrate the interpretative findings and analysis (Folger and Stein, 2017). The framework (See Fig. 2) describes a process of identification of tensions and their managerial sensemaking.

    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text