Elsevier

Neuropsychologia

Volume 48, Issue 1, January 2010, Pages 145-155
Neuropsychologia

Loss of imagery phenomenology with intact visuo-spatial task performance: A case of ‘blind imagination’

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2009.08.024Get rights and content

Abstract

The capacity for imagery, enabling us to visualise absent items and events, is a ubiquitous feature of our experience. This paper describes the case of a patient, MX, who abruptly lost the ability to generate visual images. He rated himself as experiencing almost no imagery on standard questionnaires, yet performed normally on standard tests of perception, visual imagery and visual memory. These unexpected findings were explored using functional MRI scanning (fMRI). Activation patterns while viewing famous faces were not significantly different between MX and controls, including expected activity in the fusiform gyrus. However, during attempted imagery, activation in MX's brain was significantly reduced in a network of posterior regions while activity in frontal regions was increased compared to controls. These findings are interpreted as suggesting that MX adopted a different cognitive strategy from controls when performing the imagery task. Evidence from experimental tasks thought to rely on mental imagery, such as the Brooks’ matrices and mental rotation, support this interpretation. Taken together, these results indicate that successful performance in visual imagery and visual memory tasks can be dissociated from the phenomenal experience of visual imagery.

Introduction

Asked to imagine a familiar item or recall a recent event, most people can call to mind an image that is less vivid than the original but has a visual ‘feel’. This expresses our capacity to experience visual mental imagery. There is a long-standing debate (see review in Bartolomeo, 2008) as to whether this mental experience plays a functional role in cognition: one view suggests that propositional knowledge is sufficient for supporting performance in imagery tasks (e.g. Pylyshyn, 2002), the other that imagery plays a key functional role (Kosslyn et al., 2006, Paivio, 1971). It could be that a range of cognitive strategies might be available to participants in these tasks. For example, imagery tasks might be performed using imagery or by using a propositional strategy. Both strategies might be available to healthy adults, although there is a wide variation in the extent to which people report the experience of visual imagery (e.g. Marks, 1973, McKelvie, 1995, Reisberg et al., 2003). Some subjects may, in other words, have a capacity for ‘blind imagination’, successful use of an alternative strategy to perform imagery tasks in the absence of the experience of imagery. This can be thought as analogous to the phenomenon of ‘blindsight’, characterized by successful performance in visuomotor tasks in the absence of visual perceptual experience.

We describe the case of an individual (MX) who reported the sudden loss of the experience of visual imagery in the absence of any other cognitive deficits. In previous published studies, the loss of visual imagery has been accompanied by impairments in performance on imagery tasks, for example in patients who show severe impairments on imagery tests but have intact perception (e.g. Farah, 1984, Bartolomeo, 2002, Kaski, 2002, Moro et al., 2008) and in patients who show pure representational neglect but no perceptual neglect (Guariglia et al., 1993, Beschin et al., 1997). In striking contrast, despite giving a persuasive description of his mental imagery deficit, MX was unimpaired on a range of standard tests of visual imagery. The main aim of this paper is to investigate the basis for the apparent dissociation between the lack of phenomenological experience in MX and his good performance.

Charcot and Bernard (1883, cited in Young & van de Wal, 1996) anecdotally described the case of an individual ‘Monsieur X’ who reported sudden onset of an inability to experience visual images of objects, such as monuments and buildings, and of familiar people such as close relatives. In this early case the visual imagery deficit was accompanied by some degree of prosopagnosia and clear visual memory impairments. Botez, Olivier, Vézina, Botez and Kaufman (1985) described the single case of a 38-year-old teacher presenting with an inability to experience visual images from birth in the absence of any overt deficits in perception, immediate or delayed visual memory. This example of a more selective deficit suggests that performance on visual imagery tasks might be normal in the absence of a phenomenal experience of visual imagery.

More comparable to MX are the two cases reported by Brain (1954) of sudden onset loss of visualisation, following head injury. One of these worked as a builder who, following a car accident, reported that he could no longer mentally visualise plans for new buildings, or even familiar routes, in stark contrast to his previous experience. Nevertheless he had no difficulty in drawing building plans. The second case sustained a head injury when tripping at work, and subsequently was unable to visualise recently viewed scenes or pages recently read from a book, although his reading and writing remained unimpaired. He also reported being unable to “see anything” when he closed his eyes. However, he could draw a plan of his house or a route from the station. These cases were not tested systematically on the imagery tasks developed from the 1970s onwards, nor, of course, was there any opportunity for detailed structural or functional neuroimaging. Nevertheless, as Brain himself recognised, his cases suggest the existence of dissociation between the (lost) phenomenological experience associated with visual imagery and performance on visual imagery tasks, which was largely intact.

Standard assessment of visual imagery abilities requires subjects to recall visual details, such as the relative length of animals’ tails, or to manipulate shapes ‘in the mind's eye’, for example to decide whether two shapes are in fact two views of a single object. Success in such tasks clearly requires access to a mental representation of the relevant material; it is not clear, however, that it always requires visualisation, the phenomenal experience of a visual image. There may be multiple routes to success in such tasks. For example, if asked about the colour of your mother's eyes you might answer by visualising her face and reading the answer off the resulting mental image, but it is possible to perform the same task by ‘just knowing’ the answer. These alternative strategies have been the focus of the polarised debate (Kosslyn et al., 2006, Pylyshyn, 2002) about whether mental imagery always serves a genuine cognitive function. We will return to the interpretation of our findings, and the imagery debate, in the discussion.

Section snippets

Case report

MX (not actual initials), a 65-year-old recently retired surveyor, accustomed to visualising buildings in his profession, and the faces of friends and family and recent events as he dropped off to sleep, abruptly lost the ability to visualise. His dreams lost their visual content. About 4 days before, he had undergone coronary angioplasty (remodelling of coronary arteries performed from within the arteries), experiencing brief ‘reverberation in my head and tingling in my left arm’. These

Methods

We performed a wide-ranging neuropsychological assessment, comparing the performance of MX on relevant measures with performance of 10 control participants (or in some cases a subgroup of three control participants). The control participants were matched for age (mean 63.4 years, range 55–76), sex (male), IQ and professional background with MX (all were architects). We administered the following standard and bespoke tests: (i) IQ: Wechsler adult intelligence scale-III; (ii) memory: (a) Wechsler

Neuroimaging

Given the apparent inconsistency between MX's insistence that he was unable to experience visual imagery and his normal performance on visual imagery tasks, we used fMRI to investigate JC's brain activation directly during attempted visual imagery.

A set of tasks was adapted from those used by Ishai, Haxby and Ungerleider (2002) in which healthy young adult participants were asked to view pictures of famous faces (perception condition) or to generate mental images (imagery condition) of famous

Experimental behavioural testing

MX reports the loss of the experience of visual imagery, and fails to activate a range of posterior brain regions during attempted imagery. However, he performs well on standard imagery tests. From the fMRI study, it appeared that he was using a different network from controls in performing the imagery task. Here, we consider whether the different activation pattern observed might reflect the use of alternative cognitive strategies. To this end, we used two further, behavioural, tests namely

General discussion

We report the case of a patient who abruptly lost the ability to generate visual images, both voluntarily and spontaneously during dreaming, who rates himself as experiencing almost no imagery on standard questionnaires, and yet performs at normal levels on standard tests of visual imagery and visual memory. His subjective report was corroborated by evidence from functional imaging showing that, while his brain activation on viewing famous faces were identical to that of controls, activation

Acknowledgements

We wish to thank Dr. Stephen Darling who helped us collecting the data on the Mental Rotation task, and Dr Lisa Archibald for assistance with collecting data on control participants in the fMRI simulator. We also thank Prof Ian Marshall for advice regarding the medical physics of the fMRI experiment, and Dr Alumit Ishai for helpful discussions and for assistance with preparing stimuli. We are grateful for the detailed and helpful comments of two anonymous reviewers. A. Zeman was partly

References (71)

  • P.L. Ditunno et al.

    Right hemisphere specialization for mental rotation in normals and brain damaged subjects

    Cortex

    (1990)
  • D. Dulin et al.

    Effects of peripheral and central visual impairment on mental imagery capacity

    Neuroscience and Biobehavioural Reviews

    (2008)
  • J. Duncan et al.

    Common regions of the human frontal lobe recruited by diverse cognitive demands

    Trends in Neurosciences

    (2000)
  • J.K. Eddy et al.

    Reading and listening to high and low imagery sentences

    Journal of Verbal Learning & Verbal Behavior

    (1981)
  • M.J. Farah

    The neurological basis of mental imagery: A componential analysis

    Cognition

    (1984)
  • C.R. Genovese et al.

    Thresholding of statistical maps in functional neuroimaging using the false discovery rate

    Neuroimage

    (2002)
  • J.V. Haxby et al.

    The distributed human neural system for face perception

    Trends in Cognitive Sciences

    (2000)
  • A. Ishai et al.

    Distributed neural systems for the generation of visual images

    Neuron

    (2000)
  • A. Ishai et al.

    Visual imagery of famous faces: Effects of memory and attention revealed by fMRI

    Neuroimage

    (2002)
  • J.A. Maldjian et al.

    An automated method for neuroanatomic and cytoarchitectonic atlas-based interrogation of fMRI data sets

    Neuroimage

    (2003)
  • V. Moro et al.

    Selective deficit of mental visual imagery with intact primary visual cortex and visual perception

    Cortex

    (2008)
  • H. Nelson

    A modified card sorting test sensitive to frontal lobe defects

    Cortex

    (1976)
  • G. Ratcliff

    Spatial thought, mental rotation and the right cerebral hemisphere

    Neuropsychologia

    (1979)
  • S. Saito et al.

    Visual and phonological similarity effects in verbal immediate serial recall: A test with kanji materials

    Journal of Memory and Language

    (2008)
  • P. Servos et al.

    Preserved visual imagery in visual form agnosia

    Neuropsychologia

    (1995)
  • J.E. Shuren et al.

    The role of visual imagery in spelling

    Brain & Language

    (1996)
  • N. Tzourio-Mazoyer et al.

    Automated anatomical labeling of activations in SPM using a macroscopic anatomical parcellation of the MNI MRI single-subject brain

    Neuroimage

    (2002)
  • A.D. Baddeley et al.

    Working memory and the vividness of imagery

    Journal of Experimental Psychology: General

    (2000)
  • A.D. Baddeley et al.

    Spatial working memory

  • A.D. Baddeley et al.

    Imagery and visual working memory

  • M. Behrmann et al.

    Intact mental imagery and impaired visual perception: Dissociable processes in a patient with visual agnosia

    Journal of Experimental Psychology: HPP

    (1994)
  • R. Brain

    Loss of visualization

    Proceedings of the Royal Society of Medicine

    (1954)
  • L.R. Brooks

    The suppression of visualization by reading

    Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology

    (1967)
  • J.W. Brown et al.

    Learned predictions of error likelihood in the anterior cingulate cortex

    Science

    (2005)
  • J.-M. Charcot et al.

    Un cas de suppression brusque et isolée de la vision mentale des signes et des objects (formes et couleurs)

    Le Progrès Médicale

    (1883)
  • Cited by (128)

    • Aphantasia and involuntary imagery

      2024, Consciousness and Cognition
    View all citing articles on Scopus
    1

    Current address: Schools of Psychology and Biosciences, Cardiff University, Cardiff, Wales, UK.

    View full text