Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-dfsvx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T20:18:28.905Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

47 - Human dignity and war

from Part V - Conflicts and violence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 March 2015

Andreas Hasenclever
Affiliation:
University of Tübingen
Marcus Düwell
Affiliation:
Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
Jens Braarvig
Affiliation:
Universitetet i Oslo
Roger Brownsword
Affiliation:
King's College London
Dietmar Mieth
Affiliation:
Eberhard-Karls-Universität Tübingen, Germany
Get access

Summary

War as moral evil

War as sustained combat between political communities is a moral evil (Walzer 2006; Levy and Thompson 2010). War signals the breakdown of law and order and develops a deadly dynamic of its own. Conflicts are no longer settled by moral reasoning, legal adjudication or political negotiation, but by well-organized armed forces. War always goes along with death and destruction. Troops are moved strategically to overcome violent resistance and to defeat an enemy. As a rule, not only fighters are victimized on the battlefield, but entire societies suffer. The number of non-combatants dying from the direct and indirect consequences of sustained combat such as economic shortages, famines, displacement or disrupted healthcare and social security systems by far exceeds military casualties. Additionally, warfare goes along with the categorization, and, in most cases, dehumanization of opponents. Adversaries are no longer considered individual human beings but enemies who may be killed without further justification. Given the recent increase in ethnic conflicts, the traditional distinction between combatants and non-combatants blurs even further. War was never restricted to the battlefield, but today's wars more than ever target civilian populations. Depending on the severity of the fighting and the number of atrocities committed, it takes a generation or more to overcome the social disruptions of war and to re-establish a robust peace among former combatants and their successors.

Human dignity, by contrast, requires the peaceful settlements of disputes among as well as within societies (Gewirth 1996: 1–70; Steigleder 1999: 157–75). Individuals and groups should be treated according to established human rights standards. They are entitled to life in peace and their legitimate interests should be protected by appropriate institutions. The distribution of rights and obligations within as well as among societies should be clearly specified and generally respected. In cases of transgression, a public authority should intervene to restore justice and to punish the offender if appropriate and reasonable. As such, the settlement of conflicts by well-recognized human right standards contradicts their settlement by the use of well-organized armed forces. In fact, human dignity requires the abrogation of war.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Cambridge Handbook of Human Dignity
Interdisciplinary Perspectives
, pp. 439 - 445
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bellamy, A. J. 2011. Global Politics and the Responsibility to Protect: From Words to Deeds. London: RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
Buergenthal, T. 2006. ‘The Evolving International Human Rights System’, American Journal of International Law 100(4): 783–807Google Scholar
Chenoweth, E., and Stephan, M. J. 2011. Why Civil Resistance Works: The Strategic Logic of Nonviolent Conflict. New York: Columbia University PressGoogle Scholar
Donnelly, J. 2002. Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University PressGoogle Scholar
Fiala, A. G. 2008. The Just War Myth: The Moral Illusions of War. Lanham, MD: Rowman & LittlefieldGoogle Scholar
Fisher, D. 2011. Morality and War: Can War Be Just in the Twenty-First Century?. Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gewirth, A. 1992. ‘Human Dignity as the Basis of Rights’, in Meyer, M. J. and Parent, W. A. (eds.), The Constitution of Rights: Human Dignity and American Values. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 10–28Google Scholar
Gewirth, A. 1996. The Community of Rights. University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Hidalgo, O. 2009. ‘Der “Krieg” als Deus ex machina – ein agnostizistisches Plädoyer’, in Werkner, I. and Liedhegener, A. (eds.), Gerechter Krieg – gerechter Frieden: Religionen und friedensethische Legitimationen in aktuellen militärischen Konflikten. Wiesbaden: VS Verlag, 83–109CrossRefGoogle Scholar
International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (ICISS). 2001. The Responsibility to Protect: Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty. Ottawa: International Development Research CentreGoogle Scholar
Levy, J. S., and Thompson, W. R. 2010. Causes of War. Chichester: Wiley-BlackwellGoogle Scholar
MacGinty, R. 2010. ‘No War, No Peace: Why So Many Peace Processes Fail to Deliver Peace’, International Politics 47(2): 145–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, J. 2009. Killing in War. Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Orend, B. 2006. The Morality of War. Peterborough (Ontario): Broadview PressGoogle Scholar
Rengger, N. 2002. ‘On the Just War Tradition in the Twenty-First Century’, International Affairs 78(2): 353–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steigleder, K. 1999. Grundlegung der normativen Ethik: Der Ansatz von Alan Gewirth. Freiburg im Breisgau, Munich: AlberGoogle Scholar
Téson, F. R. 2003. ‘The Liberal Case for Humanitarian Intervention’, in Holzgrefe, J. L. and Keohane, R. O. (eds.), Humanitarian Intervention: Ethical, Legal, and Political Dilemmas. Cambridge University Press, 93–129CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallensteen, P. 2012. Understanding Conflict Resolution. London, Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage PublicationsGoogle Scholar
Walzer, M. 2006. Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations. New York: Basic BooksGoogle Scholar
Weiss, T. G. 2007. Humanitarian Intervention: Ideas in Action. Cambridge: Polity PressGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×