Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-8mjnm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T21:01:29.244Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Well-Being as the Object of Moral Consideration

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2008

David Sobel
Affiliation:
Bowling Green State University

Extract

An adequate moral theory must take (at least) each person into account in some way. Some think that the appropriate way to take an agent into account morally involves a consequentialist form of promoting something about her. Others suggest instead that morality requires a Kantian form of respecting something about an agent. I am interested here in pursuing the former line. When we pursue the broadly consequentialist line we come to this question: what should we promote on the agent's behalf when we are taking her into account morally?

Type
Essays
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1998

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Arrow, Kenneth. 1963. Social Choice and Individual Values, 2nd edn.Yale University PressGoogle Scholar
Arrow, Kenneth. 1987. ‘Reflections on the Essays’. In Arrow and the Foundations of the Theory of Economic Policy. Feiwel, George R. (ed.). New York University PressGoogle Scholar
Brandt, Richard. 1979. A Theory of the Good and the Right. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Braybrooke, David. 1987. Meeting Needs. Princeton University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, John. 1991. Weighing Goods. Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Carson, Thomas. 1993. ‘The desire-satisfaction theory of welfare: Overvold's critique and reformulation’. Heil, John (ed.). Rowan and Littlefield PressGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 1983. Impartial Reason. Cornell University PressGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 1986. ‘Agent-centered restrictions from the inside out’. Philosophical Studies, 50:291319CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 1997. ‘Self-interest and self-concern’. Social Philosophy and Policy, 14:158–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 1977. Taking Rights Seriously. Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Frankena, William. 1963. Ethics. Prentice HallGoogle Scholar
Gauthier, David. 1990. [1986] Morals By Agreement. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Harvard University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 1987. ‘Ordinal Utilitarianism’. In Arrow and the Foundations of the Theory of Economic Policy. Feiwel, George R. (ed.). New York University PressGoogle Scholar
Goodin, Robert. 1995. Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy. Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, James. 1986. Well-Being. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1988. ‘Comments’. In Hare and Critics. Senor, and Fotion, (eds.). Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1981. Moral Thinking. Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, John. 1982. ‘Morality and the Theory of Rational Behavior’. In Utilitarianism and Beyond. Sen, and Williams, (eds.). Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, John. 1988. ‘Problems with act-utilitarianism and with malevolent preferences’, In Hare and Critics. Senor, and Fotion, (eds.). Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1956. Critique of Practical Reason. Trans. Beck, L. W.. Macmillan PublishingGoogle Scholar
Kavka, Gregory. 1986. Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory. Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1979. Utilitarianism. Hackett PublishingGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1986. The View From Nowhere. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Overvold, Mark. 1982. ‘Self-Interests and Getting What You Want’. In The Limits of Utilitarianism. Miller, and Williams, (eds.). Minnesota University PressGoogle Scholar
Overvold, Mark. 1980. ‘Self-interest and the concept of self-sacrifice’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10:105–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Overvold, Mark. 1984. ‘Morality, self-interest, and reasons for being moral’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 44:493507CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Railton, Peter. 1986. ‘Facts and values’. Philosophical Topics, 14:529CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of justice. Harvard University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John. 1982. ‘Social Unity and Primary Social Goods’. In Utilitarianism and Beyond. Sen, A. and Williams, B. (eds.). Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Reath, Andrews. 1989. ‘Hedonism, heteronomy, and Kant's Principle of Happiness’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 70:4272CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosati, Connie. 1995. ‘Persons, perspectives, and full information accounts of the good’. Ethics, 105:296325CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 1975. ‘Preference and urgency’. Journal of Philosophy, 72CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel. 1982. The Rejection of Consequentialism. Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1982. ‘Rational Fools’. In his Choice, Welfare, and Measurement. MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1992. Inequality Reexamined. Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Sidgwick, Henry. 1981. The Methods of Ethics. Hackett Publishing CompanyGoogle Scholar
Sobel, David. 1994. ‘Full information accounts of well-being’. Ethics, 104:784810CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sobel, David. 1997. ‘On the subjectivity of welfare’. Ethics, 107:501–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1981. ‘Internal and External Reasons’. In his Moral Luck. Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar