Skip to main content
Log in

When Are Thought Experiments Poor Ones?

  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A characteristic of contemporary analytic philosophy is its ample use of thought experiments. We formulate two features that can lead one to suspect that a given thought experiment is a poor one. Although these features are especially in evidence within the philosophy of mind, they can, surprisingly enough, also be discerned in some celebrated scientific thought experiments. Yet in the latter case the consequences appear to be less disastrous. We conclude that the use of thought experiments is more successful in science than in philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

REFERENCES

  • Atkinson, D. and Peijnenburg, J.: forthcoming, Galileo and Prior Philosophy' Studies in History and Philosophy of Science.

  • Bishop, M. A.: 1999, ‘Why Thought Experiments are not Arguments’ Philosophy of Science 66, 534–541.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. et al.: 1997, The Nature of Consciousness, Cambridge, Mass.-London, the MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borsboom, D., Mellenbergh, G. J. and van Heerden, J.: 2002, ‘Functional Thought Experiments’ Synthese 130(3), 379–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R.: 1991, The Laboratory of the Mind: Thought Experiments in the Natural Sciences, London-New York, Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J.: 1996, The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory, Oxford, Oxford U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P.: 1985, ‘Reduction, Qualia, and the Direct Introspection of Brain States’ Journal of Philosophy 82, 8–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P.: 1989, ‘Knowing Qualia: A Reply to Jackson’ reprinted in: Block 1997.

  • Degenaar, M.: 1996, Molyneux's Problem: Three Centuries of Discussion on the Perception of Forms, Dordrecht, Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C.: 1997, ‘An exchange with Daniel Dennett’ in: J. R. Searle, The Mystery of Consciousness, New York: A New York Review Book.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A.: 1916/1923, ‘The Foundation of the General Theory of Relativity’ in H. A. Lorentz et al., The Principle of Relativity: A Collection of Original Memoirs on the Special and General Theory of Relativity, with notes by A. Sommerfeld. Transl. by W. Perret and G.B. Jeffery (New York, Dover Publications).

  • Einstein, A., Podolsky, B. and Rosen, N.: 1935, ‘Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete?’ Physical Review 47, 777–780.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S.: 1998, ‘Galileo and the Indispensability of Scientific Thought Experiment’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49, 397–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, D. R.: 1981, ‘Reflections on Searle's “Minds, Brains, and Programs’ “, in D. C. Dennett and D. R. Hofstadter (eds), The Mind's I: Fantasies and Reflections on Self and Soul, New York, Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horowitz, T. and Massey, G. J. (eds): 1991, Thought Experiments in Science and Philosophy, Savage, Maryland, Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F.: 1982, ‘Epiphenomenal Qualia’ Philosophical Quarterly 32, 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F.: 1986, ‘What Mary didn't Know’ reprinted in: BLOCK 1997.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jong, W. R. de: 2000, ‘Kants Dialectische Opposities (Kant's Dialectical Oppositions)’ Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte (General Dutch Journal of Philosophy) 92(2), 154–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I.: 1781–1787/1929, Critique of Pure Reason, Hampshire-London, Macmillan Press, Transl. by N. Kemp Smith, 25th edition, 1993.

  • Kim, J.: 1996, Philosophy of Mind, Boulder-Oxford, Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McAllister, J. W.: 1996, ‘The Evidential Significance of Thought Experiment in Science’ Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 27(2), 233–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I.: 1686–1626/1729/1934, Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica, Andrew Motte's 1729 translation into English, revised by Florian Cajori (Berkeley etc., University of California Press). Paperback edition 1966.

  • Norton, J. D.: 1991, Thought Experiments in Einstein's Work, in: Horowitz and Massey.

  • Norton, J. D.: 1996, ‘Are Thought Experiments just what you Thought?’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26(3), 333–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D.: 1984, Reasons and Persons, Oxford, Oxford U.P. 5th reprint with corrections, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pais, A.: 1982, Subtle is the Lord... The Science and the Life of Albert Einstein, Oxford, Oxford U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R.: 1980, ‘Minds, Brains, and Programs’ reprinted in D. C. Dennett and D. R. Hofstadter, The Mind's I: Fantasies and Reflections on Self and Soul, New York, Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R.: 1984, Minds, Brains and Science, reprinted in 1989, London etc: Pelican Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, R.: 1992, Thought Experiments, Oxford, Oxford U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkes, K.: 1988, Real People: Personal Identity Without Thought Experiments, Oxford, Oxford U.P. Paperback Edition 1993.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Peijnenburg, J., Atkinson, D. When Are Thought Experiments Poor Ones?. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 34, 305–322 (2003). https://doi.org/10.1023/B:JGPS.0000005164.26228.f7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/B:JGPS.0000005164.26228.f7

Navigation