Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-2pzkn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-14T22:36:04.845Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Limitations of Hierarchical Organization

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

The concept of levels of organization is prominent in science and central to a variety of debates in philosophy of science. Yet many difficulties plague the concept of universal and discrete hierarchical levels, and these undermine implications commonly ascribed to hierarchical organization. We suggest the concept of scale as a promising alternative. Investigating causal processes at different scales allows for a notion of quasi levels that avoids the difficulties inherent in the classic concept of levels. Our primary focus is ecology, but we suggest how the results generalize to other invocations of hierarchy in science and philosophy of science.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This work was conducted as a part of the Function and Evolution Working Group at the National Institute for Mathematical and Biological Synthesis, sponsored by the National Science Foundation, the US Department of Homeland Security, and the US Department of Agriculture through NSF award EF-0832858, with additional support from the University of Tennessee, Knoxville. We received helpful input from the other members of that working group, from two anonymous referees for Philosophy of Science, and from Melinda Fagan. Potochnik also benefited from the feedback of the members of the philosophy of biology lab group at the University of California, Davis, and the audience of a colloquium at Stanford University.

References

Begon, Michael, Harper, John L., and Townsend, Colin R.. 1986. Ecology: Individuals, Populations, and Communities. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.Google Scholar
Campbell, Donald T. 1974. “‘Downward Causation’ in Hierarchically Organised Biological Systems.” In Studies in the Philosophy of Biology, ed. Ayala, F. and Dobzhansky, T., 179–86. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Clark, James S. 1998. “Why Trees Migrate So Fast: Confronting Theory with Dispersal Biology and the Paleorecord.” American Naturalist 152:204–24.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Corre, Valerie Le, Machon, Nathalie, Petit, Remy J., and Kremer, Antoine. 1997. “Colonization with Long-Distance Seed Dispersal and Genetic Structure of Maternally Inherited Genes in Forest Trees: A Simulation Study.” Genetical Research 69:117–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, Carl F. 2007. Explaining the Brain: Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, Carl F., and Bechtel, William. 2007. “Top-Down Causation without Top-Down Causes.” Biology and Philosophy 22:547–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curnow, R. N., and Ayres, K. L.. 2007. “Population Genetic Models Can Be Used to Study the Evolution of the Interacting Behaviors of Parents and Their Progeny.” Theoretical Population Biology 72:6776.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feibleman, James K. 1954. “Theory of Integrative Levels.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 5 (17): 5966.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry. 1974. “Special Sciences: The Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis.” Synthese 28:97115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garfinkel, Alan. 1981. Forms of Explanation: Rethinking the Questions in Social Theory. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Gaston, Kevin J., and Blackburn, Tim M.. 2000. Pattern and Process in Macroecology. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gregory, Richard D. 2000. “Abundance Patterns of European Breeding Birds.” Ecography 23:201–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guttman, Burton S. 1976. “Is ‘Levels of Organization’ a Useful Biological Concept?BioScience 26 (2): 112–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl. 1966. Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Horgan, Terence E. 1982. “Supervenience and Microphysics.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 63:2943.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hubbell, Stephen P. 2001. A Unified Theory of Biodiversity and Biogeography. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Jagers op Akkerhuis, Gerard A. J. M. 2008. “Analysing Hierarchy in the Organization of Biological and Physical Systems.” Biological Reviews 83:112.Google ScholarPubMed
Kim, Jaegwon. 1999. “Making Sense of Emergence.” Philosophical Studies 95 (1–2): 336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon. 2002. “The Layered Model: Metaphysical Considerations.” Philosophical Explorations 5 (1): 220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitano, Hiroaki. 2002. “Systems Biology: A Brief Overview.” Science 295:1662.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Leibold, M. A., et al. 2004. “The Metacommunity Concept: A Framework for Multi-Scale Community Ecology.” Ecological Letters 7:601–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levin, Simon A. 1992. “The Problem of Pattern and Scale in Ecology.” Ecology 73 (6): 1943–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lidicker, William Z. Jr. 2008. “Levels of Organization in Biology: On the Nature and Nomenclature of Ecology's Fourth Level.” Biological Reviews 83:7178.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
MacArthur, Robert H. 1968. “The Theory of the Niche.” In Population Biology and Evolution, ed. Lewontin, Richard C., 159–76. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press.Google Scholar
Machamer, Peter, Darden, Lindley, and Craver, Carl F.. 2000. “Thinking about Mechanisms.” Philosophy of Science 67 (1): 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magurran, Anne E., and Henderson, Peter A.. 2003. “Explaining the Excess of Rare Species in Natural Species Abundance Distributions.” Nature 422:714–16.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Maurer, Brian A. 1999. Untangling Ecological Complexity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
May, R. M. 1976. “Models for Two Interacting Populations.” In Theoretical Ecology: Principles and Applications, ed. May, R. M., 4970. Philadelphia: Saunders.Google Scholar
McGill, Brian J. 2003. “Does Mother Nature Really Prefer Rare Species or Are Log-Left-Skewed SADs a Sampling Artefact?Ecological Letters 6:766–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGill, Brian J.. 2010. “Ecology: Matters of Scale.” Science 328:575.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McShea, Daniel W. 1991. “Complexity and Evolution: What Everybody Knows.” Biology and Philosophy 6:303–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, Sandra D. Forthcoming. “Emergence: Logical, Functional and Dynamical.” Synthese.Google Scholar
Molles, Manuel C. 2002. Ecology: Concepts and Applications. Boston: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Nagel, Ernest. 1961. The Structure of Science. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Odum, Eugene P. 1959. Fundamentals of Ecology. 2nd ed. Philadelphia: Saunders.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Robert V. 1979. “Transmutations across Hierarchical Levels.” In Systems Analysis of Ecosystems, ed. Innes, G. S. and O’Neill, Robert V., 5978. Fairland, MD: International Co-operative.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Robert V., DeAngelis, D. L., Waide, J. B., and Allen, T. F. H.. 1986. A Hierarchical Concept of Ecosystems. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Oppenheim, Paul, and Putnam, Hilary. 1958. “Unity of Science as a Working Hypothesis.” In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 2, ed. Herbert Feigl, Michael Scriven, and Grover Maxwell, 3–36. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Peters, Robert H. 1983. The Ecological Implications of Body Size. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Potochnik, Angela. 2010a. “Explanatory Independence and Epistemic Interdependence: A Case Study of the Optimality Approach.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61 (1): 213–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Potochnik, Angela. 2010b. “Levels of Explanation Reconceived.” Philosophy of Science 77 (1): 5972.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Potochnik, Angela. 2011. “A Neurathian Conception of the Unity of Science.” Erkenntnis 34 (3): 305–19.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1975. “Philosophy and Our Mental Life.” In Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2, Mind, Language and Reality, 291303. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ricklefs, Robert E. 2008. The Economy of Nature. 6th ed. New York: Freeman.Google Scholar
Rueger, Alexander, and McGivern, Patrick. 2010. “Hierarchies and Levels of Reality.” Synthese 176:379–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sadava, David, Heller, H. Craig, Orians, Gordon H., Purves, William K., and Hillis, David. 2008. Life: The Science of Biology. 8th ed. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.Google Scholar
Sazima, Ivan, Carvalho, Lucelia Nobre, Mendonca, Fernando Pereira, and Zuanon, Jansen. 2006. “Fallen Leaves on the Water-Bed: Diurnal Camouflage of Three Night Active Fish Species in an Amazonian Streamlet.” Neotropical Ichthyology 4 (1): 119–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schoener, Thomas W. 1986. “Mechanistic Approaches to Community Ecology: A New Reductionism.” American Zoologist 26:81106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwartz, James. 2002. “Population Genetics and Sociobiology.” Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 45 (2): 224–40.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stevens, Martin, and Merilaita, Sami. 2009. “Animal Camouflage: Current Issues and New Perspectives.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364:423–27.Google ScholarPubMed
Strevens, Michael. 2006. Bigger than Chaos: Understanding Complexity through Probability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
West, Geoffrey B., and Brown, James H.. 2005. “The Origin of Allometric Scaling Laws in Biology from Genomes to Ecosystems: Towards a Quantitative Unifying Theory of Biological Structure and Organization.” Journal of Experimental Biology 208 (9): 1575–92.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
White, Ethan P., Morgan Ernest, S. K., Kerkhoff, Andrew J., and Enquist, Brian J.. 2007. “Relationships between Body Size and Abundance in Ecology.” Trends in Ecology and Evolution 22:323–30.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wiens, John A. 1989. “Spatial Scaling in Ecology.” Functional Ecology 3:385–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiens, John A.. 1990. “Ecology 2000: An Essay on Future Directions in Ecology.” Revista Chilena de Historia Natural 65:309–15.Google Scholar
Wilson, Edward O., and Bossert, William H.. 1971. A Primer of Population Biology. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.Google Scholar
Wilson, Robert A. 2008. “The Biological Notion of Individual.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, Edward N.. Stanford, CA: Stanford University. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/biology-individual.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, William C. 2007. Re-engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zillio, Tommaso, and Condit, Richard. 2007. “The Impact of Neutrality, Niche Differentiation and Species Input on Diversity and Abundance Distributions.” Oikos 116:931–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar