Skip to main content
Erschienen in: The Journal of Value Inquiry 1/2020

29.01.2019

Metaethical Agnosticism: Practical Reasons for Acting When Agnostic About the Existence of Moral Reasons

verfasst von: Joseph Len Miller

Erschienen in: The Journal of Value Inquiry | Ausgabe 1/2020

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

There has been little discussion about how to act when uncertain about the existence of moral reasons in general. In this paper I will argue that despite being uncertain about the existence of moral reasons, someone can still have a practical reason to act in a particular way (under certain conditions). This practical reason is morally relevant because it will have an impact on whether we’re making the correct moral decision (if there is a correct moral decision). This practical reason will result from a principle of decision-making that can be used when someone is agnostic about the existence of moral reasons (‘metaethical agnosticism’). The aims of this paper include explicitly beginning the discussion about this topic and advocating for a principle of moral decision-making that can be used despite being metaethically agnostic.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
See Andrew Sepielli, “What to Do When You Don’t Know What to Do,” in Russ Shafer-Landau, ed., Oxford Studies in Metaethics: Volume 4 (New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2009), pp. 5–28.
 
2
Ibid., p. 5.
 
3
See Alexander A. Guerrero, “Don’t Know, Don’t Kill: Moral Ignorance, Culpability and Caution,” Philosophical Studies, Vol. 136 (2007); Dan Moller, “Abortion and Moral Risk,” Philosophy, Vol. 86, No. 3 (2011); Graham Oddie, “Moral Uncertainty and Human Embryo Experimentation,” in K. W. M. Fulford, Grant Gillett, and Janet Martin Soskice, eds., Medicine and Moral Reasoning (New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1994), pp. 144–161; and Nancy M. Williams, “Affected Ignorance and Animal Suffering: Why Our Failure to Debate Factory Farming Puts Us at Moral Risk,” Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, Vol. 21 (2008).
 
4
See Ted Lockhart, Moral Uncertainty and Its Consequences (New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2000); Jacob Ross, “Rejecting Ethical Deflationism,” Ethics, Vol. 116 (2006); Sepielli, op. cit.; and Andrew Sepielli, “Moral Uncertainty and the Principle of Equity among Moral Theories,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 86, No. 3 (2013).
 
5
One might ask how we could have applicatory knowledge despite being theoretically and/or metaethically uncertain. I do not intend to articulate or defend any kind of hierarchical ranking or ordering of the different levels at which normative uncertainty can occur. It will be enough for my purposes if I can show that it’s plausible to have knowledge at the applicatory level while at the same time being metaethically agnostic.
 
6
See William FitzPatrick, “Moral Responsibility and Normative Ignorance: Answer a New Skeptical Challenge,” Ethics, Vol. 118 (2008); Elizabeth Harman, “Does Moral Ignorance Exculpate?” Ratio, Vol. 24 (2011); Gideon Rosen, “Culpability and Ignorance,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (2003); Gideon Rosen, “Skepticism about Moral Responsibility,” Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. 18 (2004); Williams, op. cit.; and Michael J. Zimmerman, “Moral Responsibility and Ignorance,” Ethics, Vol. 107, No. 3 (1997).
 
7
I’m using this particular example because it is one of the two most popular examples in the literature on decision-making under theoretical uncertainty. The same things can be shown if the example involved getting an abortion instead of eating meat.
 
8
For an argument against the idea that being agnostic about the existence of moral reasons means either option is morally permissible, see Mark Schroeder, “Normative Ethics and Metaethics,” in Tristram McPherson and David Plunkett, eds., The Routledge Handbook to Metaethics (New York, NY: Routledge, 2017) pp. 674–686.
 
9
I would like to thank an anonymous referee for drawing my attention to this concern.
 
10
See Thomas Nagel, “War and Massacre,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 1, No. 2 (1972).
 
11
There are situations, for example, where deciding whether to get an abortion or whether to eat meat is purely the result of a person’s decisions, and what the person did to get themselves into that situation may have been morally wrong. However, this does not seem to entail that both options in the current decision are morally wrong. There are two different decision-making contexts: (1) the one that got the person into a situation where they have to make their current decision, and (2) their current decision. Even though the person may have made a morally wrong choice that put them in the current decision-making context, the moral status of the available choices may change given the circumstances. The person could have done something morally wrong to get themselves into a situation where they have to decide whether to get an abortion or whether to eat meat, but this is a different decision than the one that got them into this situation in the first place. I am assuming that while the two decisions are connected or related, the moral status of the available options in this new decision can change given the circumstances.
 
12
For a comparison of moral knowledge and mathematical knowledge, see Justin Clarke-Doane, “Moral Epistemology: The Mathematics Analogy,” Noûs, Vol. 48 (2014).
 
13
See Blaise Pascal, Pensées (1670), W. F. Trotter, trans. (London: Dent, 1910), §233.
 
14
This interpretation views Pascal’s Wager as a decision under uncertainty. See Edward F. McClennen, “Pascal’s Wager and Finite Decision Theory,” in Jeff Jordan, ed., Gambling on God: Essays on Pascal’s Wager (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1994) pp. 115–138.
 
15
I am not claiming this to be the correct interpretation of Pascal’s Wager. This is just one particular interpretation of Pascal’s Wager that is structurally similar to PAUMA. Even if this isn’t the correct way of understanding Pascal’s Wager, it’s a similar decision procedure to PAUMA.
 
16
Again, for an argument against the idea that being agnostic about the existence of moral reasons means either option is morally permissible, see Schroeder, op. cit.
 
17
See Elizabeth Harman, “The Irrelevance of Moral Uncertainty,” in Russ Shafer-Landau, ed., Oxford Studies in Metaethics: Volume 10 (New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2015), pp. 53–79.
 
18
See Lockhart, op. cit.
 
19
When I have been saying that someone is unsure of an action’s moral status, Lockhart, op. cit., refers to this as ‘might be morally wrong,’ and what I have been referring to as ‘morally permissible’ Lockhart refers to as ‘not morally wrong.’
 
20
Sepielli offers a similar argument that advocates maximizing expected moral value. Acting in ways that are known to be morally permissible maximizes expected moral value since the only other way of acting is believed to possibly be morally wrong. Thus, acting in a way that could be morally wrong, when an alternative that is known to be morally permissible is available, fails to maximize expected moral value.
 
21
See Guerrero, op. cit., and Moller, op. cit.
 
22
See Brian Weatherson, “Running Risks Morally,” Philosophical Studies, Vol. 167, No. 1 (2014). Weatherson refers to this principle as “ProbWrong.” ProbWrong and Uncertaintism are roughly equivalent (there are different variations of ProbWrong, but the general idea is the same). As such, in this paper I refer to ProbWrong as Uncertaintism.
 
23
Ibid., p. 146.
 
24
Ibid.
 
25
Weatherson, op. cit., acknowledges that his argument owes a lot to Michael Smith’s distinction between doing what is actually morally right and doing whatever turns out to be morally right. See Michael Smith, The Moral Problem (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, Ltd., 1994), p. 75.
 
Metadaten
Titel
Metaethical Agnosticism: Practical Reasons for Acting When Agnostic About the Existence of Moral Reasons
verfasst von
Joseph Len Miller
Publikationsdatum
29.01.2019
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Erschienen in
The Journal of Value Inquiry / Ausgabe 1/2020
Print ISSN: 0022-5363
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-0492
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-019-09682-9

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 1/2020

The Journal of Value Inquiry 1/2020 Zur Ausgabe