Skip to main content

2016 | OriginalPaper | Buchkapitel

2. Rule-of-Law and Judicial Federalism: The Role of Ordinary Courts in the Enforcement of Fundamental Rights

verfasst von : Alfredo Narváez Medécigo

Erschienen in: Rule of Law and Fundamental Rights

Verlag: Springer International Publishing

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

In order to find out whether the law of a given country has any say in Rule-of-Law achievement—or failure—it is first necessary to establish on a theoretical level what Rule-of-Law means. Indeed, only a critical legal approach (i.e., not merely descriptive) can shed light on whether the law per se is a determinant of Rule-of-Law realization and, therefore, on whether cultural components have been thus far overrated as the explanation for Rule-of-Law failure in certain contexts. On the other hand, critique of a specific legal system can only be meaningful if it is based on an objective standard, that is, on legal norms that objectively correspond to the Rule-of-Law ideal. The first evident problem is that even though the concept Rule-of-Law has consolidated as the overarching objective guiding almost every reform effort all over the world, there is hardly any consensus on what it concretely stands for. Despite the overwhelming agreement worldwide on the Rule-of-Law as a desirable goal and as a good idea for every society, the debate concerning the concept’s scope and meaning is far from over, particularly when taking into account the usual tensions—when not contradictions—faced by practitioners with diverging views on the topic. The classic theoretical inquiries on whether the Rule-of-Law represents merely the establishment of law and order in a given territory or rather includes democratic procedures that legitimize government decisions are by no means resolved. Quite the opposite: there is still much disagreement on whether Rule-of-Law denotes merely the predictability provided by limited government or instead comprises also a substantive character which involves the effectiveness of certain rights and/or the existence of some sort of social justice. These theoretical discussions intensified with the growing inclusion of the term Rule-of-Law in the political agenda and its indiscriminate use to justify any transformation of a legal or judicial institution worldwide. If there is not a fairly clear Rule-of-Law concept at hand, however, any value judgment issued with regard to a specific legal system’s suitability to achieve the Rule-of-Law will be arbitrary and, consequently, any conclusion based on that critique will be meaningless.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
See Carothers (2006a, b), pp. 3–4.
 
2
See Stromseth et al. (2006a, b), p. 56; and Kleinfeld (2006), p. 32.
 
3
See Carothers (2008), p. 52.
 
4
See Kleinfeld (2006), pp. 33–35. She claims that the Rule-of-Law as a concept includes different ends and not infrequently those ends are incompatible with each other. This happens, for instance, with the implementation of law and order and human rights in some contexts. Similarly Carothers (2008), p. 50, points out: “… when diverse national and international actors gather and agree that they are all committed to helping build the rule of law in a particular country or context, they usually agree on much less than it initially appears. They may all proceed with a putatively common rule-of-law agenda but in practice pursue quite different preoccupations, either in relative isolation from one another or sometimes at cross purposes.”
 
5
See Raz (2009b), p. 211, who considers Rule-of-Law and democracy as two very different things.
 
6
See Dworkin (1985), pp. 11–12, who argues against the “Rule book conceptions” of the Rule-of-Law. These are not sufficient for a just society, he claims, when one considers the different theories of adjudication they recommend.
 
7
See Carothers (2008), p. 50. On the negative impact of poor Rule-of-Law definitions see Kleinfeld (2006), p. 50.
 
8
See, for instance, Bumke and Voßkuhle (2008), pp. 294–312. Referring to the German context, they point out that some other key elements include the principle of separation of powers, the lawfulness of the administration, the principle of proportionality, the binding effect of law and justice on the judiciary, the principle of legal certainty, legal protection against violation of the law by public authorities, and due process principles in criminal and criminal procedural law. Curiously enough, however, many of these elements can also be seen as basic rights for individuals provided they are considered as such by a constitution (or by a constitutional court) and there is the mechanism to enforce them judicially. One good example of this is how the German Federal Constitutional Court (BVerfG) has considered that every statute contrary to the constitution violates the general freedom of action (allgemeine Handlungsfreiheit) granted by German Basic Law (Ger. GG) (1949), art. 2, cl. 1, published in Bundesgesetzblatt Teil I 1 1949:1–19, and entitles the individual to challenge the measure through a constitutional complaint. See Elfes, BVerfGE 6, 32 (1957), p. 41, and its implications in infra Chap. 4.
 
9
By ordinary it is meant that these courts are not specialized in constitutional matters.
 
10
For a brief yet clear account of these meanings and their origin see Kleinfeld (2006), pp. 36–46. She notes that whereas the government bound by the law conception can be traced back to Aristotle and a desire to prevent arbitrariness, the law and order meaning is rather strongly connected with the Hobbesian notion of the State as a provider of security. Kleinfeld tracks the idea of equality before the law also to ancient Greece, yet points out that its connection to the Rule-of-Law concept is mainly due to Albert Venn Dicey, who elaborated the first modern definition of the term. A similar phenomenon occurred with the longstanding ideas of efficient and predictable justice and enforced human rights. While the former was retaken in part by Friedrich August von Hayek in his efforts to foster the market economy, the latter was recaptured by Dicey from the Enlightenment’s idea of individual rights. See also Shklar (1998), pp. 21–37. She claims there are two very different archetypes of the concept: one elitist and based on reason which can be attributed to Aristotle; the other one egalitarian and grounded on ‘freedom from fear’, which she associates with Montesquieu.
 
11
See Bumke and Voßkuhle (2008), pp. 294–312. For a distinction between the uses of Rechtsstaat and the Rule-of-Law see Rivers (2007), pp. 891–904.
 
12
See Secretary General of the United Nations (2004), p. 4.
 
13
See Stromseth et al. (2006a, b), p. 69.
 
14
In a now classic essay first published in 1977 by Raz (2009b), pp. 210–211, it was described as one of the “main fallacies on the treatment of the doctrine of the Rule-of-law” the assumption that the concept stands for democracy, justice, equality (before the law or otherwise), human rights of any kind, or respect for persons or for the dignity of man. Shklar (1998), p. 21, pointed out already in the 1980s that “it would not be very difficult to show that the phrase ‘the Rule of Law’ has become meaningless thanks to ideological abuse and general over-use”.
 
15
For example, the controversial definition provided by Dicey (1982), p. 120, was included in an account of the British legal system. That of Hayek (2001), pp. 75–76, represents an attempt to justify a political economy idea: one against planned economy and in favor of the free market. The notions Rule-of-Law developed by Fuller (1969), pp. 33–94; Raz (2009b), p. 212 and Dworkin (1985), pp. 11–12, are all rather connected to their discussions in philosophy of law and, as such, to their analysis on the relationship between law and morality.
 
16
See Shklar (1998), p. 21. Her main thesis is that the new conceptions of the Rule-of-Law did not consider the objectives the original versions where supposed to serve and this impasse has turned the concept into a vacuum. See also Radin (1989), p. 784, who tries to redefine the concept based on a “Wittgensteinian” notion of rules, that is, one which considers consensus as an inherent feature of any rule; and Fallon (1997), pp. 1–56, where he systematically analyses diverging conclusions reached by the United States Supreme Court with the Rule-of-Law concept.
 
17
To such efforts belong the ‘multiple-end’ notion of Rule-of-Law developed by Kleinfeld (2006), pp. 34–47, and the ‘pragmatic definition’ established by Stromseth et al. (2006a, b), p. 78.
 
18
Not without some semantic distinctions and mild variations in content, such classification is followed by Radin (1989), p. 784; and by Stromseth et al. (2006a, b), pp. 69–70. The innovative distinction between ‘ends-based’ and ‘institutional’ definitions held by Kleinfeld (2006), p. 36, is rather used in the context of Rule-of-Law implementation. It aims for practitioners to “consider their reforms aim by aim, rather than institution by institution, so that they can actually gauge the likelihood of their success”.
 
19
Some of the best-known supporters of this conception are Hayek (2001), pp. 75–76; Fuller (1969), p. 39; and Raz (2009b), pp. 212–213.
 
20
Raz (2009b), p. 214, resumes this position quite clearly: “This is the basic intuition from which the doctrine of the rule of law derives: the law must be capable of guiding the behavior of its subjects. It is evident that this position is a formal one. It says nothing on how the law is to be made: by tyrants, democratic majorities, or any other way. It says nothing about basic rights, about equality, or justice…”
 
21
The main supporters of such notion are said to be Dicey (1982), p. 107; Rawls (1999), p. 208; and Dworkin (1985), pp. 11–12.
 
22
See Dworkin (1985), p. 26.
 
23
For an explanation of the inclusion of democratic values in the Rule-of-Law agenda, see Carothers (2008), p. 54.
 
24
See Fallon (1997), pp. 32–33.
 
25
For Stromseth et al. (2006a, b), p. 78, for instance, Rule-of-Law “describes a state of affairs in which the state successfully monopolizes the means of violence, and in which most people, most of the time, choose to resolve disputes in a manner consistent with procedurally fair, neutral, and universally applicable rules, and in a manner that respects fundamental human rights norms (such as prohibitions on racial, ethnic, religious and gender discrimination, torture, slavery, prolonged arbitrary detentions, and extrajudicial killings).” She points out that some authors consider equality before the law and democratic procedures as elements of the instrumental conception.
 
26
See Stromseth et al. (2006a, b), p. 69.
 
27
According to Rawls (1999), p. 208, for instance, “…yet because these precepts guarantee only the impartial and regular administration of rules, whatever these are, they are compatible with injustice…”
 
28
See Carothers (2008), pp. 53–54.
 
29
See Dworkin (1985), p. 12.
 
30
See Kleinfeld (2006), p. 45.
 
31
See Radin (1989), p. 791.
 
32
See Shklar (1998), p. 21.
 
33
See Holmes (1997), pp. 991–1009; Radbruch (1946), pp. 105–108; and Hart (1977), pp. 17–37.
 
34
See Lovett (2002), p. 67. The same concern is reflected by Radin (1989), pp. 782–783.
 
35
For instance, both the position of Radbruch (1946), p. 105, to subject the validity of statutes to their compatibility with basic principles of morality, as well as the material notion of the German Rechtsstaat described by Böckenförde (2007), pp. 164–168, have the German Third Reich in mind.
 
36
For example, both Hart (1977), p. 37; and Raz (2009b), p. 224, deny that the moral character of a rule determines its legal validity.
 
37
This is why Raz and Dworkin end up with so different notions of the Rule-of-Law.
 
38
To be more precise, it is usually assumed that only a legal system can match the Rule-of-Law, but a system does not need the Rule-of-Law to be a legal system. Contrary to this trend, see Lovett (2002), p. 42. A rather important exception would be Kelsen (2008), pp. 125–137. In a theory of law in which law and State are one and the same thing—that needs to be able to rule to a certain extent in order to be considered law and that can have any moral content whatsoever—the concept Rule-of-Law would be redundant and not very useful.
 
39
See Raz (2009b), p. 212, who makes precisely this point.
 
40
The definition of Hayek (2001), pp. 75–76, emphasizes this very idea: “Stripped of all technicalities this means that government in all its actions is bound by rules fixed and announced beforehand—rules which make it possible to foresee with fair certainty how the authority will use its coercive powers in given circumstances, and to plan one’s individual affairs on the basis of this knowledge.”
 
41
See Rawls (1999), p. 210; and Hayek (2001), p. 76.
 
42
See Shklar (1998), p. 26.
 
43
For Rawls (1999), p. 207, “a legal system is a coercive order of public rules addressed to rational persons for the purpose of regulating their conduct and providing the framework for social cooperation. When these rules are just, they establish a basis for legitimate expectations. They constitute grounds upon which persons can rely on one another and rightly object when their expectations are not fulfilled.”
 
44
The easy path would be to analyze whether modern constitutions, the ultimate pillars of the Rule-of-Law doctrine, contain more than the formal elements. Just by looking at the catalogues of basic rights that are regularly included it could be easily confirmed they do. This would be, however, a question of fact, and probably fallacious if used in an ‘ought to’ context as when debating the Rule-of-Law ideal. The more interesting question is if there could be a necessary relationship before the inclusion of these elements in positive law that could theoretically explain them as an essential element.
 
45
Raz (2009b), p. 214.
 
46
See Fuller (1969), p. 53.
 
47
See Rawls (1999), p. 209; and Fuller (1969), pp. 63–64.
 
48
See Fuller (1969), pp. 79–81.
 
49
This principle is also named “Ought to implies can” by Rawls (1999), p. 210.
 
50
See Hart (1997), pp. 100–110.
 
51
See Kelsen (2008), p. 77.
 
52
The wording used by Raz (2009b), p. 213, is “the lay sense of law” in contrast to the professional sense of the term.
 
53
See Hart (1997), pp. 127–128.
 
54
See Raz (2009b), pp. 215–216.
 
55
Fuller (1969), p. 81, points out somewhat eloquently: “We arrive finally at the most complex of all desiderata that make up the internal morality of the law: congruence between official action and the law. This congruence may be destroyed or impaired in a great variety of ways: mistaken interpretation, inaccessibility of the law, lack of insight into what is required to maintain the integrity of a legal system, bribery, prejudice, indifference, stupidity, and the drive toward personal power [....] Just as the threats to this congruence are manifold, so the procedural devices designed to maintain it take, of necessity, a variety of forms…”
 
56
See Rawls (1999), pp. 50–51; and Raz (2009b), pp. 216–217.
 
57
See Hart (1997), p. 160; and Fuller (1969), p. 81.
 
58
Rawls (1999), p. 210.
 
59
See Rawls (1999), p. 210; and Raz (2009b), pp. 216–217.
 
60
The issue of the indeterminacy of the law should be left aside here. While one should be aware of the existence of the hard cases, of the “problems of the penumbra” identified by Hart (1977), p. 23, the Rule-of-Law ideal is mostly not about the penumbral cases. It rather assumes that the law has the potential ability to guide people’s conduct.
 
61
Whereas Raz (2009b), pp. 217–218, includes the accessibility to courts as well as the prohibition of crime-preventing agencies to pervert the law through discretion, authors like Fuller (1969), p. 81, consider also the right to appeal an adverse decision to a higher tribunal.
 
62
The highly criticized association made by Dicey (1982), pp. 107–108, between the Rule-of-Law and constitutional rights would not sound that distant anymore.
 
63
See Fallon (1997), p. 8.
 
64
See Raz (2009b), p. 217.
 
65
Fuller (1969), p. 81.
 
66
As Raz (2009b), p. 210, has pointed out, the Rule-of-Law competes with other values which are probably more important for some people. These values are frequently constitutionalized.
 
67
See Raz (2009b), p. 217; Fuller (1969), p. 81; Dicey (1982), p. 108; and Dworkin (1985), p. 27.
 
68
See Dicey (1982), pp. 110–111.
 
69
For Raz (2009b), p. 217, “…it is in connection with political freedom in this sense that constitutional guaranteed rights are of great importance.” Nevertheless, in his view the Rule-of-Law is compatible with gross violations of human rights and it has no bearing on the existence of spheres of activity free from governmental interference.
 
70
See Fuller (1969), p. 81.
 
71
As it will be shown, certainty in the legal system could be reinforced that way. Dworkin (1985), p. 32, summarizes this advantage: “Society makes an important promise to each individual, and the value of the promise seems to me worth the cost. It encourages each individual to suppose that his relations with other citizens and with his government are matters of justice, and it encourages him and his fellow citizens to discuss as a community what justice requires these relationships to be. It promises a forum in which his claims about what he is entitled to have will be steadily and seriously considered at his demand.” See also Fallon (1997), p. 53.
 
72
This means, in short, that one cannot exist without the other. For Kelsen (2008), p. 51, however, whereas the right always needs an obligation, the right is only a possibility and not a necessity.
 
73
Compare, for instance, Lüth, BVerfGE 7, 198 (1958), p. 205, with Dicey (1982), pp. 115–120.
 
74
For instance, it is clear that in principle it makes no difference in regards to predictability whether a published statute was democratically voted or enacted by the executive power.
 
75
See Raz (2009b), pp. 210–211.
 
76
See Hume (2000), p. 302, after whom this logical rule is named: “I cannot forbear adding to these reasonings an observation, which may, perhaps, be found of some importance. In every system of morality, which I have hitherto met with, I have always remarked, that the author proceeds for some time in the ordinary way of reasoning, and establishes the being of a God, or makes observations concerning human affairs; when of a sudden I am surprised to find, that instead of the usual copulations of propositions, is, and is not, I meet with no proposition that is not connected with an ought, or an ought not. This change is imperceptible; but is, however, of the last consequence. For as this ought, or ought not, expresses some new relation or affirmation, it is necessary that it should be observed and explained; and at the same time that a reason should be given, for what seems altogether inconceivable, how this new relation can be a deduction from others, which are entirely different from it. But as authors do not commonly use this precaution, I shall presume to recommend it to the readers; and am persuaded, that this small attention would subvert all the vulgar systems of morality, and let us see, that the distinction of vice and virtue is not founded merely on the relations of objects, nor is perceived by reason.”
 
77
See Michelman (2003), pp. 13–34.
 
78
See, for instance, Elfes, BVerfGE 6, 32 (1957), p. 41.
 
79
See Dworkin (1985), p. 16, who points out that “though the rights model concedes that the rule book is in this way a source of moral rights in court, it denies that the rule book is the exclusive source of such rights.”
 
80
See Alexy (1986), pp. 53–54.
 
81
See Raz (2009b), p. 210.
 
82
Provided it is not only political demagogy and the constitution enjoys a reasonable degree of entrenchment.
 
83
Raz (2009b), p. 229.
 
84
See Dworkin (1985), p. 12.
 
85
See Raz (2009b), p. 222.
 
86
See Rawls (1999), p. 210.
 
87
See Kelsen (1929), p. 52.
 
88
See Raz (2009b), p. 225.
 
89
See Fuller (1969), pp. 81–82; and Dworkin (1985), p. 16.
 
90
See Dicey (1982), pp. 115–116; and Dworkin (1985), pp. 11–12.
 
91
See Carothers (2008), pp. 59–60; and Kleinfeld (2006), p. 47.
 
92
The subjective and objective dimensions of constitutional scrutiny are explained in the last section of this chapter. See infra Sect. 2.4.1.
 
93
See Schlaich and Korioth (2010), pp. 6–7.
 
94
As it will be thoroughly discussed, in some legal systems ordinary courts are not allowed to control acts of Parliament directly. Yet as it is argued by Kelsen (1929), p. 52, “…in the referred legal conditions it cannot be said that the constitution is guaranteed. This is only the case when there is the possibility to nullify unconstitutional acts.” (Author’s translation). Thus, empowerment in those systems is achieved insofar as the ordinary court, to which the powers of judicial review—in the particular sense of being able to declare the unconstitutionality of acts of authority regardless of the State power from which they derive, what is also known as richterliches Prüfungsrecht—are limited, enjoys instead the ability to detonate the mechanism through which the constitutional review of the act of Parliament will be performed by a specialized organ.
 
95
As it will be further explained in this chapter (infra Sect. 2.4.4), there has to be of course a limit on the acts of the State that can be subject to review. Otherwise the system would have no end. While the limit usually rests in the activity of the constitutional jurisdiction, this does not mean that their decisions cannot be unconstitutional in the dogmatic sense, but rather that there is no further entity entitled to judge that and remedy it. American Supreme Court Justice Robert Houghout Jackson made this point eloquently in a concurring opinion on Brown v. Allen, 344 U.S. 443 (1953), p. 540: “…There is no doubt that if there were a super-Supreme Court, a substantial proportion of our reversals of state courts would also be reversed. We are not final because we are infallible, but we are infallible only because we are final”.
 
96
See Fuller (1969), p. 81.
 
97
See Kelsen (2008), pp. 94–95.
 
98
See Kelsen (2008), pp. 95–97.
 
99
It represents the activity of “saying the law” in a legal controversy. See Kelsen (2008), p. 89.
 
100
See Kelsen (1929), p. 65.
 
101
In the words of Raz (2009b), pp. 225–226, “it is of the essence of the law to guide behavior through rules and courts in charge of their application. Therefore, the rule of law is the specific excellence of the law. Since conformity to the rule of law is the virtue of law in itself, law as law regardless of the purposes it serves, it is understandable and right that the rule of law is thought of as among the few virtues of law which are the special responsibility of the courts and the legal profession.”
 
102
See Shapiro (1981), pp. 154–155.
 
103
See Raz (2009b), p. 216, and more critical, Shapiro (1981), pp. 1–5. The main argument for this conclusion is that independent courts are impartial to the dispute and follow certain standard procedures to reach their conclusions. Thus, certainty in the application of the law would be assured through a contradictory procedure (the trial) carried out by impartial experts in the law (the judges). However, this is a conclusion that has been highly contested, at least in two fronts: The first and best known argument comes from Kelsen (1929), p. 44, who rejects a substantial difference between what the administration and the judiciary do in regards to application of the law. More recently however, the critique falls especially in regards to rights which imply a high degree of technical expertise in their realization or implementation by administrative agencies. As an introduction to this problem, see Shapiro (2002), pp. 173–199. Compare also Hesse (1991), pp. 221–230.
 
104
See Raz (2009b), p. 225.
 
105
See Raz (2009b), p. 220.
 
106
See Posner (1985), pp. 69–71.
 
107
The distinction between constitutional right and constitutional procedural right will be of the utmost importance when analyzing the subjective and objective dimensions of constitutional judgments. See infra Sect. 2.4.1 in this chapter.
 
108
See Kelsen (2008), p. 60; and Alexy (1986), p. 472.
 
109
See, for instance, Ger. GG (1949), art. 93, cl. 1, No. 2, and Political Constitution of the United Mexican States (Mex. Const.) (1917), art. 105, para. II, published in Diario Oficial V(30) 1917:1–13.
 
110
See Fiss (1996), pp. 23–24.
 
111
The Rule-of-Law conception of Dworkin (1985), p. 27 praises this individual empowerment before the courts: “For individuals have powers under the rights conception that they do not have under the rule book conception. They have the power to demand, as individuals, a fresh adjudication of their rights. If their rights are recognized by a court, these rights will be enforced in spite of the fact that no parliament had the time or the will to enforce them.”
 
112
See Raz (2009b), pp. 225–226.
 
113
See Dworkin (1985), p. 27.
 
114
See Dworkin (1985), p. 16.
 
115
See Kommers (1997), pp. 59–62.
 
116
See, for instance, Ger. GG (1949), art. 20, cl. I.
 
117
See Schuppert (1999a, b), p. 299.
 
118
See Schmitt (1993), p. 125.
 
119
See Trenor (2005), p. 457, and compare with Germany, where according to Kommers (1997), p. 36, before the Basic Law “there was no place for judicial review.”
 
120
See, for instance, Stone Sweet (1992), p. 219.
 
121
This was the case, for instance, in the United Kingdom, where the House of Lords was, until 2009, the Highest Court of the Land. See Le Sueur (2004), pp. 3–7.
 
122
See Schwartz (2006), pp. 19–48.
 
123
See Fallon (1997), p. 53.
 
124
The traditional sense of the term is defining concretely and individually a right or an obligation.
 
125
See Schlaich and Korioth (2010), pp. 244–246.
 
126
See Hervey (2003), pp. 194–195.
 
127
It could also be discussed whether a right without the procedural entitlement to enforce it is actually a right. The assumption here is that it is as long as the implementation of such right is not discretional to the reviewing authority, that is, as long as someone can challenge for the individual and the review is obligatory for the court (e.g. abstract control of norms or collective action).
 
128
See Dicey (1982), pp. 3–5.
 
129
See, among many, Freund (1954), pp. 106–162.
 
130
See Stone Sweet (1992), p. 132.
 
131
See Constitution of the French Republic (Fr. Const.) (1958), arts. 61.1 and 62, published in Journal Officiel de la République Française 0238 1958:9151–9172, as amended by Constitutional Law to modernize the Institutions of the 5th French Republic (Fr. L. Const. Inst. 5° Rep.) (2008), arts. 29–30, published in Journal Officiel de la République Française 0171(2) 2008:11890–11896.
 
132
This misunderstanding is one of the reasons why Mexico has developed a parallel constitutional jurisdiction which has become the last word in almost every ordinary trial. See infra Chap. 5.
 
133
See Kenntner (2005a), p. 786.
 
134
This is the unintended consequence of the recent decision of the Mexican Supreme Court in October 25, 2011 that authorizes every court in the country the disapplication of “unconstitutional” or “unconventional” statutory law. See infra Chap. 5.
 
135
If, for instance, a criminal code would be declared unconstitutional, an elemental sense of justice would demand to set free all of those convicted for the unconstitutional crime description. See infra Chap. 5.
 
136
See Montesquieu (1989), p. 163.
 
137
For instance, it is an essential element of the German Rechtsstaat. See Bumke and Voßkuhle (2008), pp. 295–297.
 
138
The classic examples are the extraordinary powers of legislation given to the executive and the submission of the executive to the legislative in parliamentary systems.
 
139
See Kau (2007), p. 83. The principle of Parliamentary Sovereignty, however, is present in the common law tradition of England. See Dicey (1982), pp. 3–5.
 
140
Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. 137 (1803).
 
141
In England, for instance, as there is no written constitution, Rule-of-Law is rather related to the ability of the courts to apply ordinary law, but this is always subject to retaliation from the Parliament. See Fallon (1997), p. 9.
 
142
See Trenor (2005), p. 457.
 
143
See Pushaw (1996), pp. 413–425.
 
144
Whereas the German notion of richterliches Prüfungsrecht involves the review of the law (mostly of administrative action but also of statutes) through statutory and constitutional standards by a judicial-type organ, Verfassungskontrolle represents the resolution of disputes between the political organs acknowledged by the constitution. See Kommers (1997), p. 4. Contrary to his distinction, however, it is the latter concept that is wider. While Verfassungskontrolle implies the powers to determine the constitutionality of a legal measure enacted by a public organ (statutory, administrative, or judicial), richterliches Prüfungsrecht does not necessarily imply the settlement of a constitutional political dispute.
 
145
Whereas in the European tradition the duties of judicial review in regards to acts of the executive or administrative agencies can be done by the ordinary courts (usually administrative courts, but also courts of general jurisdiction), the task of constitutional control has been just a capacity of a specialized organ with jurisdiction on State matters. For the transition of jurisdiction on State matters (Staatsgerichtsbarkeit) to jurisdiction on constitutional matters (Verfassungsgerichtsbarkeit) see Schlaich and Korioth (2010), pp. 6–8; and Kommers (1997), p. 5.
 
146
Whereas European scholarship uses the ‘separation’ and ‘unity’ semantics; American scholars refer to this dichotomy as ‘decentralized’ or ‘centralized’ models. See Kau (2007), p. 79.
 
147
See Stone Sweet (2008), p. 223; and Jackson and Tushnet (1999), p. 465.
 
148
See Stone Sweet (2008), p. 224. See also infra Chap. 3.
 
149
See Trenor (2005), p. 357.
 
150
Kau (2007), p. 368, is mistaken when he implies that this kind of control is only given to federal courts.
 
151
This is known as the ‘case or controversy’ requirement and implies that abstract constitutional control is not part of the American Einheitsmodell.
 
152
See Jackson and Tushnet (1999), p. 458.
 
153
See Fuller (1969), p. 81.
 
154
The constitutional review of judicial decisions in this decentralized model is channeled usually only through the ordinary mechanisms of appeal, that is, it is—albeit with important exceptions—regularly represented by the control of the judgment which is exercised by the courts of appeal enjoying a higher position in the judicial hierarchy.
 
155
See U.S. Code Title 28 (28 U.S.C.) (2006), § 1257.
 
156
This is the principle that binds courts to the authority of superior courts as it forces them to solve a case in the same way it has been previously decided by a higher tribunal in the judicial hierarchy. See Jackson and Tushnet (1999), p. 468.
 
157
See Stone Sweet (2008), p. 222; and Jackson and Tushnet (1999), p. 467.
 
158
There are usually courts specialized in administrative matters, but it is not excluded that courts of general jurisdiction review administrative action as well. Constitutional review of judicial action is shared both by the ordinary courts and the constitutional court.
 
159
By jurisdictional here it is meant that the organ follows a judicial contradictory procedure to reach a decision and is integrated by professional judges at least in some part. The French Constitutional Council would in a way correspond to this model, but neither are its members necessarily related to the judicial realm nor is its procedure completely contradictory. See Stone Sweet (1992), p. 219.
 
160
For an updated regional distribution of this model worldwide, see the several tables available at http://​www.​concourts.​net/​tab/​tab1.​php?​lng=​en&​stat=​1&​prt=​0&​srt=​0.
 
161
See Fleury (2008), p. 63.
 
162
See Dicey (1982), pp. 3–5.
 
163
See Kommers (1997), p. 36.
 
164
See Schlaich and Korioth (2010), pp. 244–246.
 
165
See, for instance, the ‘force of statute’ effects of some of the judgments in German Federal Constitutional Court Act (Ger. BVerfGG) (1951), § 31, No. 2, published in Bundesgesetzblatt Teil I 45 1993:1473–1487.
 
166
There is normally an exception towards the review of pre-constitutional legislation, but this is usually not considered constitutional review in the strict sense of the term. In reference to this exception in Germany, see Kau (2007), p. 300; and Fleury (2008), p. 63. The constitutional review of preconstitutional legislation, however, should be considered constitutional review insofar as it enforces the primacy of constitutional rules. See infra Chap. 4.
 
167
See Hesse (1991), pp. 29–32.
 
168
See, for instance, the Vorlageverfahren in Ger. GG (1949), art. 100, the cuestión de inconstitucionalidad in Spanish Constitution (Spa. Const.) (1978), art. 163, published in Boletín Oficial del Estado CCCXVIII(311.1) 1978:29313–29339, and the recently introduced question constitutionnelle in Fr. Const. (1958), art. 61.1.
 
169
See Schlaich and Korioth (2010), pp. 7–8; and Kau (2007), p. 75. As a matter of fact the original creator of this model of constitutional review did not consider challenges of individual acts (i.e. administrative resolutions or judgments) as an essential element of the attributions of a constitutional court. Since the unconstitutionality of the individual act—insofar the constitutionality of a statute is not questioned—could only be indirect, he rather considered that the resolution of these challenges should be a task for ordinary administrative courts. See Kelsen (1929), pp. 62–63.
 
170
See, in this sense, Kommers (1997), pp. 3 and 42.
 
171
See Shapiro (2002), pp. 174–175.
 
172
For a distinction between two and three-tier federalisms, see Kommers (1997), pp. 68–69.
 
173
See Saunders (1995), p. 61.
 
174
See Cameron and Falleti (2005), p. 260.
 
175
See Fuller (1969), p. 81.
 
176
If there was a centralized system of constitutional control of statutes (Verwerfungsmonopol), one would have to include in this ordinary mechanisms of congruence the possibility of federal and local courts to refer the case to the constitutional organ. Still, that would be an interaction strictly in regards to competencies and not hierarchical one. It would be a similar situation to that one between the European Court of Justice (ECJ) and the national courts of the European Union’s (EU) member states. See Cohen (1996), pp. 421–461.
 
177
See Winkle (1974), p. 68. Whether this relationship by many courts is usually not regarded as “hierarchical” but rather as the exercise of different competencies, they are no doubt hierarchical insofar as a judgment can be overturned.
 
178
Here ‘state’ is used in the sense of ‘Bundesland’. When ‘State’ is capitalized, it is used in the sense of ‘Staat’.
 
179
For the use of federal common law as a way to review decisions from state courts, see Winkle (1974), pp. 71–72.
 
180
See Constitution of the United States of America (U.S. Const.) (1789), amend. X, available at http://​www.​usconstitution.​cc/​, as well as Kau (2007), p. 53.
 
181
See Burnham (2006), pp. 189–191.
 
182
See Kau (2007), p. 54.
 
183
See Holt (1985), pp. 169–189. For the evolution of federal question jurisdiction see infra Chap. 3.
 
184
In other words, to bring a federal question before federal courts is facultative. See Winkle (1974), p. 72; and Burnham (2006), p. 185. For a more detailed analysis of the distribution of jurisdiction between federal and state courts in the United States see infra Chap. 3.
 
185
See 28 U.S.C. (2006), § 1257. There is, as it will be mentioned, a possibility for lower federal courts to review state court decisions via habeas corpus. This writ, however, is limited to violations of liberty and thus basically restricted to criminal cases.
 
186
This presupposes that the case, given its “objective importance” in the eyes of the U.S. Supreme Court, is relevant enough to be considered for discussion. See Graf Vitzthum (2005), p. 322, and U.S. Sup. Ct. Rules (2013), rule 10, available at http://​www.​supremecourt.​gov/​ctrules/​2013RulesoftheCo​urt.​pdf.
 
187
Diversity jurisdiction cases are not included here as they are more about which law to apply than a question of which jurisdiction. See Winkle (1974), p. 72. For the evolution of habeas corpus in the United States see infra Chap. 3.
 
188
See, among many decisions of the so-called “Warren Court”, Brown v. Allen, 344 U.S. 443 (1953), and Fay v. Noia, 372 U.S. 391 (1963).
 
189
See Winkle (1974), p. 73. This problems ended up eventually in a severe restriction of the federal writ as of the 1980s. See infra Chap. 3.
 
190
See Kau (2007), p. 60.
 
191
See Monaghan (1975), pp. 10–14.
 
192
See Graf Vitzthum (2005), p. 322.
 
193
It is meant here the relationship between judicial authorities within the National State. Germany, Italy, and Spain are the usual referents for this kind of judicial federalism. What has been traditionally understood as European judicial federalism has more to do with the relationship between the supra-national judicial authorities of the EU, that is, between the ECJ and the judiciaries of the member states. For this kind of analysis see Cohen (1996), pp. 421–461.
 
194
See Heyde (1999), pp. 17 and 46.
 
195
This court is not to be confused with the constitutional court which is also a federal judicial organ. Given its relevance for judicial federalism, the revision of judgments by the federal constitutional court is subject of analysis in the following section.
 
196
There are some exceptions to this rule. For instance, whereas the German Federal Administrative Court is first instance court against some administrative resolutions of the Federal Ministry of Interior, the Spanish Supreme Court is trial court in cases concerning civil liability of members of the Federal Government and Terrorism. See, respectively, German Administrative Judiciary Act (Ger. VwGO) (1960), § 50, published in Bundesgesetzblatt Teil I 18 1991:686–711, and Spanish Organic Law for the Judicial Power (Spa. LOPJ) (1985), art. 56.2, published in Boletín Oficial del Estado(157) 1985:20632–20678.
 
197
See Jolowicz (2000), pp. 299–327; and Shapiro (1981), pp. 37–39 and 149.
 
198
See Heyde (1999), p. 46.
 
199
See Kau (2007), p. 59.
 
200
See, for instance, Ger. GG (1949), art. 95.
 
201
See, for instance, Spa. Const. (1978), art. 123, cl. I, in connection with Spa. LOPJ (1985), art. 55.
 
202
France is not, however, a federal country.
 
203
That is why these courts are usually known as ‘cassation’ or ‘revision’ courts. See Shapiro (1981), p. 149.
 
204
To foster this unifying role of the federal court, the procedural rules usually contain a mechanism of leave or ‘explicit admission’ in which, provided the relevance requirements are fulfilled, the local court that issued the final judgment has to explicitly grant the right to file the federal appeal. See, for instance, Ger. VwGO (1960), §§ 132–133.
 
205
Indeed, in the American model the higher status of federal courts before local judiciaries has never been as marked as in Europe. Even with the American original procedural configuration, if one chose the local judiciary to solve a federal question case, the federal appeal would have reached the U.S. Supreme Court only if the supreme court of a state held a statute as unconstitutional when deciding the federal question, when the constitutionality of a state statute was affirmed, or when the state court had decided against a federal interest. See U.S. Judiciary Act (1789), § 25, published in Stat. 1(21):73–93. This deference towards local courts is even stronger with the current procedural rules: ever since the “direct appeals” were eliminated in 1988—and the U.S. Supreme Court enjoys a completely discretional docket—the federal revision of state supreme courts’ decisions that hold (federal or state) statutes as unconstitutional will depend on the U.S. Supreme Court’s willingness to grant certiorari. See Graf Vitzthum (2005), p. 322.
 
206
See Fleury (2008), p. 39.
 
207
See Kommers (1997), p. 3.
 
208
The referral procedure is established by Ger. GG (1949), art. 100; Spa. Const. (1978), art. 163, and more recently Fr. Const. (1958), art. 61.1.
 
209
See Kommers (1997), p. 3; and Schlaich and Korioth (2010), pp. 303–304.
 
210
The usual criteria are: the case’s relevance for the legal order; that the local court does not share the criteria already established by the federal court; or a violation of due process by the local court. See, for instance, Ger. VwGO (1960), § 132.
 
211
While in Austria and in France this is not the case, in Spain and Germany the individual mechanisms of constitutional procedural law have consolidated as essential to the legal realm. See Kommers (1997), p. 14; and Kenntner (2005b), p. 270.
 
212
This limitation occurs, for instance, with the French Constitutional Council. See Stone Sweet (1992), p. 219. The inclusion of the referral procedure in Fr. Const. (1958), art. 61.1 in an amendment of July, 2008 has not changed this substantially. See L. Const. Inst. 5° Rep. (2008), art. 29. While in Austria the Verfassungsgerichtshof does not control judgments, it can certainly control administrative acts. See Austrian Federal Constitutional Laws (Aut. B-VG) (1930), art. 144, cl. I, published in Bundesgesetzblatt für die Republik Österreich 1(1) 1930:1–26.
 
213
Compare Hesse (1991), p. 226.
 
214
As a matter of fact one of the main procedural limitations to the exercise of these mechanisms is that the act which is challenged must specifically violate the constitutional rights of the complainant and not constitutional law in general. See, for instance, Ger. GG (1949), art. 93, cl. I, para. 4a, and Mex. Const. (1917), art. 103, para. I.
 
215
According to Kelsen (1929), p. 67, in order to avoid jurisdictional conflicts, the cases that are not based on unconstitutional statutes should have been left aside of the constitutional jurisdiction and remained a task for the ordinary administrative courts.
 
216
See Graf Vitzthum (2005), p. 322.
 
217
See 28 U.S.C. (2006), § 1257. For a detailed description of the evolution of the U.S. Supreme Court's certiorari jurisdiction see infra Chap. 3.
 
218
For instance, constitutional procedural mechanisms such as the German Verfassungsbeschwerde or the Spanish Recurso de amparo are mostly filed against judgments from ordinary courts. See, respectively, Ger. GG (1949), art. 93, cl. I, para. 4a, and Spa. Const. (1978), art. 53.2.
 
219
See Kenntner (2005b), p. 270.
 
220
This is not supposed to mean that the American model of judicial organization guaranties less effectively the Rule-of-Law than the European. As it will be seen, this depends mostly on the legal system’s ability to provide legal predictability. In the American model of diffused constitutional control and binding precedent, the ordinary mechanisms of appeal and the discretional review by the U.S. Supreme Court serve adequately such purposes. See infra Chap. 3.
 
221
See Kelsen (1929), p. 67.
 
222
See Fleury (2008), p. 64. This requirement, however, does not really solve the problem. It rather forwards the issue and makes it part of the already existing problem of determining the boundaries between ordinary and constitutional jurisdiction.
 
223
See Kenntner (2005b), p. 270. To sustain that constitutional courts apply only constitutional law and ordinary courts apply only ordinary law is to deny that constitutional rules are binding for every authority or, in other words, that there is a direct effect of the constitution. In a theory of the Rule-of-Law that fosters constitutional supremacy such conclusion is, therefore, absurd. See also Schlaich and Korioth (2010), p. 14.
 
224
See Schuppert (1978), p. 43.
 
225
This includes the uniformity role which the U.S. Supreme Court sporadically exercises through its discretional docket in certiorari.
 
226
See Hoffmann-Riem (2003), p. 189.
 
227
Inefficiency here is used in its most primary meaning describing a cost-benefit relationship. That is, if the same desired result could be achieved with the use of only one instead of two units, the model applying two units for such purpose is inefficient.
 
228
See Kenntner (2005b), p. 271.
 
229
See Schlaich and Korioth (2010), p. 11.
 
230
See Hoffmann-Riem (2003), pp. 181–182.
 
231
See, for instance, Elfes, BVerfGE 6, 32 (1957), p. 41. This judgment, however, speaks of a constitutional violation in regards to a statute (Normen) and not necessarily in regards to a judgment given its own vices. See infra Chap. 3. For other examples, see Schlaich and Korioth (2010), pp. 11–12.
 
232
See, for instance, Mex. Const. (1917), arts. 14 and 16. For a similar example in Germany see Hoffmann-Riem (2003), pp. 190–191, in regards to Lüth, BVerfGE 7, 198 (1958), and the establishment of basic rights as a control criterion in the application of ordinary law.
 
233
See Roth (1996), pp. 547–548.
 
234
See Kenntner (2005a), p. 786.
 
235
See Roth (1996), pp. 547–548.
 
236
It is not a surprise that the main argument against this conclusion comes from Kelsen (1929), p. 67.
 
237
According to Kenntner (2005b), pp. 270–271, in the German realm this cooperation relationship has not been harmonic at all given the insufficiency of the formulas used by the BVerfG.
 
238
See Hoffmann-Riem (2003), pp. 188–189.
 
239
See Hoffmann-Riem (2003), p. 175.
 
240
The American Habeas corpus, the German Verfassungsbeschwerde, and the Mexican Juicio de Amparo only proceed against constitutional violations that involve basic rights. However, the extensive dogmatic postures in basic rights protection which frequently turn any constitutional discrepancy indirectly a basic right issue send the problem back to the realization of constitutional law in general. See Schlaich and Korioth (2010), pp. 9–12; and Roth (1996), p. 547.
 
241
See Hoffmann-Riem (2003), p. 175.
 
242
Raz (2009a), p. 226.
 
243
Even though the subjective and objective dimensions are described here semantically mostly with regard to constitutional rights, it is important to remember that they presuppose, respectively, the subjective and objective dimensions of the correlative constitutional obligations. This clarification is omitted in the main text for clarity purposes, but will achieve special significance when discussing the objective-legal character of a constitutional judgment. See Kelsen (2008), p. 55, and infra Sect. 2.4.1.2.
 
244
See, for instance, U.S. Sup. Ct. Rules (2013), rule 10, and Fiss (1996), pp. 23–24.
 
245
See, among many, Hesse (1991), pp. 118–127.
 
246
See Kelsen (2008), pp. 56–58.
 
247
The act of authority subject to constitutional scrutiny can be of course an omission. See Alexy (1986), pp. 194–195.
 
248
There are, of course, many kinds of constitutional judgments. For a well-structured typology, see Schlaich and Korioth (2010), pp. 241–279.
 
249
In this case, it forces the activity of a court with powers to perform constitutional scrutiny. See supra Sect. 2.1.3 in this chapter.
 
250
One can think, for instance, in the abstract control of norms which is proper of centralized systems of constitutional review. The holder of the procedural right to constitutional review that challenges the constitutionality of a norm for violating a constitutional right is usually not the holder of the constitutional right at stake. Compare Hesse (1991), p. 144.
 
251
The delivery of a ‘constitutional judgment’ can only be considered a ‘right’ when such constitutional scrutiny represents a correlative ‘obligation’ for the reviewing organ. As it was mentioned already apropos of the judicial realization of constitutional rules, not everyone enjoys always and in every case the procedural capacity to initiate the mechanism of constitutional scrutiny. Therefore, if the obligation to perform constitutional (judicial) review is institutionalized only through the activity of selected bodies authorized to initiate such mechanism in a legal system, the individual dimension of a case can determine its constitutional relevance only when there is a general mechanism of constitutional review that empowers the individual as one of these selected bodies.
 
252
Dworkin (1985), p. 27.
 
253
See Kenntner (2005a), p. 786.
 
254
Whereas the objective-legal character of a basic right would describe a direct relationship between a constitutional rule (conferring a general right) and every recipient of such rule in general, the objective character of a constitutional judgment only has a bearing on that general relationship insofar these constitutional rules are object of interpretation by a judicial organ and, consequently, their meaning, scope, and/or validity are further developed by such court. Since not every constitutional judgment has erga omnes effects or, in other words, not every judgment concerning basic rights has the ‘force of a statute’, then strictly speaking these two notions cannot be identical. This might explain why the concept “objective-legal character of basic rights” is deeply rooted in systems with centralized constitutional control where judgments of the constitutional court can have the force of a statute. See Schlaich and Korioth (2010), pp. 301–304.
 
255
This dimension includes all the addressees of a constitutional rule in general, that is, both the hypothetical holders of a constitutional right as well as all the entities with a general duty to their realization. See, for instance, Ger. VwGO (1960), §§ 132–133, and Bumke and Voßkuhle (2008), pp. 8–9.
 
256
Certainly, the objective character also comprises the general duty of every organ of the State to pursue, in its own sphere of competencies, the general realization of the constitutional rule as interpreted by the constitutional judgment. See Bumke and Voßkuhle (2008), pp. 8–9.
 
257
Some legal systems give different effects to a constitutional judgment depending on this particular feature. This is problematic as it fosters inequality in the application of the law. With such a differentiation the system might foster, for instance, that in two different cases filed against the same act, for the exact same reasons and with exactly the same arguments, one is overruled and the other one confirmed by the constitutional court. See the several cases referred to in infra Chap. 5. There, the majorities required for a decision on unconstitutionality in cases filed through Amparo are different that those filed in abstract control.
 
258
See Steiner (2001), p. 2921.
 
259
The clearest example of this is the writ of certiorari in the Supreme Court of the United States. See Graf Vitzthum (2005), p. 322.
 
260
See Kelsen (2008), pp. 62–64.
 
261
See Dworkin (1985), p. 27.
 
262
The individual dimension of constitutional scrutiny as a source of obligation was explained previously in this chapter (Sect. 2.4.1.1).
 
263
Compare Hesse (1991), p. 32.
 
264
See Fuller (1969), p. 81.
 
265
Raz (2009b), p. 213.
 
266
See Dworkin (1985), p. 32.
 
267
See Schlaich and Korioth (2010), p. 6.
 
268
Hoffmann-Riem (2003), p. 176.
 
269
See Hesse (1991), pp. 202–203.
 
270
This implies the powers either of referral or of “disapplication”. See supra Sect. 2.2.3 in this chapter.
 
271
This implies the judgment’s status as binding precedent or as a decision with Gesetzkraft. See, for instance, Ger. BVerfGG (1951), § 31, No. 2.
 
272
See Hoffmann-Riem (2003), p. 206.
 
273
See Hoffmann-Riem (2003), pp. 201–202.
 
274
This is meant only in the sense that it is authorized by the constitutional court, not that it is correct or wrong. See Kelsen (2008), pp. 107–109.
 
275
To make it obligatory to non-judicial authorities is not necessary if judicial review is reasonably complete, for legislative and administrative powers will be subject to the courts.
 
276
See Hoffmann-Riem (2003), pp. 201–202.
 
277
Compare Hesse (1991), p. 32.
 
278
See, for instance, Solange II, BVerfGE 73, 339 (1986), p. 375.
 
279
See Hart (1997), pp. 124–125.
 
280
See Shapiro (2007), p. 17.
 
281
See Kelsen (2008), p. 99.
 
282
Constitutions cannot solve every contingency and therefore, should be only guiding rules.
 
283
See Kelsen (2008), p. 79, and Schlaich and Korioth (2010), pp. 270–277.
 
284
Compare Hesse (1991), pp. 29–32.
 
285
Hoffmann-Riem (2003), p. 188 (author’s translation).
 
286
See Schlaich and Korioth (2010), p. 7.
 
287
Dworkin (1985), p. 27.
 
288
According to Hoffmann-Riem (2003), p. 189, the constitutional court should have a prerogative to determine the standards of scrutiny in constitutional interpretation. This prerogative is particularly strong vis-à-vis ordinary courts when there are no established criteria set by the legislator.
 
289
In centralized systems these decisions are anyway monopolized by the constitutional court. See Stone Sweet (2008), p. 224.
 
290
See Hoffmann-Riem (2003), p. 191.
 
291
Compare Hesse (1991), p. 199.
 
292
Many authors are in love with the idea that they are only different competencies and no real hierarchical relationship. If one court can overrule the decisions of another one, one of them is exercising a superior role and thus has a higher position. Whether this relationship is considered “hierarchical” in the original meaning of the term is rather semantics.
 
293
See Schuppert (1978), p. 44.
 
294
See Kelsen (1929), pp. 62–63, and the notion of parity developed in infra Chap. 3.
 
295
See Kenntner (2005a), p. 786.
 
296
See Kelsen (2008), p. 77.
 
297
Kelsen (2008), p. 83 (author’s translation).
 
298
See Roth (1996), p. 561.
 
299
The constitutional courts usually do not act without being asked to. See Steiner (2001), pp. 2919–2920.
 
300
Both on the German Verfassungsbeschwerde and the Mexican Amparo the law assumes that the purpose of such mechanisms is to protect rights individually. Nevertheless, on the former there is sort of a discretional rule of rejection. See Ger. BVerfGG (1951), §§ 93 d, para. 3. On the latter, in contrast, there is no such rule and, therefore, there has to be a grounded judgment to reject the case.
 
301
At least this is the interpretation that is given to their label as mechanisms for the protection of constitutional rights.
 
302
See Ger. BVerfGG (1951), §§ 93 d, para. 3, and U.S. Sup. Ct. Rules (2013), rule 10.
 
303
See Kenntner (2005b), p. 270.
 
304
See Kommers (1997), pp. 112–113 and 551 (note 85).
 
305
See Hoffmann-Riem (2003), p. 181.
 
306
See Roth (1996), p. 547.
 
307
Hoffmann-Riem (2003), p. 176.
 
308
Compare Hesse (1991), pp. 29–32.
 
309
Raz (2009b), p. 215.
 
310
See Roth (1996), p. 574.
 
311
Hoffmann-Riem (2003), p. 182.
 
312
Compare Hoffmann-Riem (2003), p. 214.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Alexy R (1986) Theorie der Grundrechte. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main Alexy R (1986) Theorie der Grundrechte. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main
Zurück zum Zitat Böckenförde EW (2007) Recht, Staat, Freiheit: Studien zur Rechtsphilosophie, Staatstheorie und Verfassungsgeschichte, 2nd edn. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main Böckenförde EW (2007) Recht, Staat, Freiheit: Studien zur Rechtsphilosophie, Staatstheorie und Verfassungsgeschichte, 2nd edn. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main
Zurück zum Zitat Bumke C, Voßkuhle A (2008) Casebook Verfassungsrecht, 5th edn. Beck, München Bumke C, Voßkuhle A (2008) Casebook Verfassungsrecht, 5th edn. Beck, München
Zurück zum Zitat Burnham W (2006) Introduction to the law and legal system of the United States, 4th edn. Thomson/West, St. Paul Burnham W (2006) Introduction to the law and legal system of the United States, 4th edn. Thomson/West, St. Paul
Zurück zum Zitat Cameron MA, Falleti TG (2005) Federalism and the subnational separation of powers. Publius J Federalism 35(2):245–271CrossRef Cameron MA, Falleti TG (2005) Federalism and the subnational separation of powers. Publius J Federalism 35(2):245–271CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Carothers T (ed) (2006a) Promoting the rule of law abroad: in search of knowledge. Carnegie Endowment, Washington Carothers T (ed) (2006a) Promoting the rule of law abroad: in search of knowledge. Carnegie Endowment, Washington
Zurück zum Zitat Carothers T (2006b) The rule of law revival. In: Carothers T (ed) Promoting the rule of law abroad: in search of knowledge. Carnegie Endowment, Washington, pp 3–13 Carothers T (2006b) The rule of law revival. In: Carothers T (ed) Promoting the rule of law abroad: in search of knowledge. Carnegie Endowment, Washington, pp 3–13
Zurück zum Zitat Carothers T (2008) Rule of law temptations. Fletcher Forum World Aff 33(1):49–61 Carothers T (2008) Rule of law temptations. Fletcher Forum World Aff 33(1):49–61
Zurück zum Zitat Cohen JC (1996) The European preliminary reference and US Supreme Court review of State Court Judgments: a study in comparative judicial federalism. Am J Comp Law 44(3):421–461CrossRef Cohen JC (1996) The European preliminary reference and US Supreme Court review of State Court Judgments: a study in comparative judicial federalism. Am J Comp Law 44(3):421–461CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Dicey AV (1982) Introduction to the study of the law of the constitution. Liberty/Classics, Indianapolis Dicey AV (1982) Introduction to the study of the law of the constitution. Liberty/Classics, Indianapolis
Zurück zum Zitat Dworkin RM (1985) A matter of principle. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Dworkin RM (1985) A matter of principle. Harvard University Press, Cambridge
Zurück zum Zitat Fallon RH (1997) The rule of law as a concept in the constitutional discourse. Colum L Rev 97(1):1–56CrossRef Fallon RH (1997) The rule of law as a concept in the constitutional discourse. Colum L Rev 97(1):1–56CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fiss OM (1996) The political theory of the class action. Wash & Lee L Rev 53(1):21–31 Fiss OM (1996) The political theory of the class action. Wash & Lee L Rev 53(1):21–31
Zurück zum Zitat Fleury R (2008) Verfassungsprozessrecht, 7th edn, Academia iuris: Basisstudium. Heymanns, Köln Fleury R (2008) Verfassungsprozessrecht, 7th edn, Academia iuris: Basisstudium. Heymanns, Köln
Zurück zum Zitat Freund PA (1954) The federal judiciary. In: Bowie RR, Friedrich CJ (eds) Studies in federalism. Little, Brown & Co., Boston, pp 106–162 Freund PA (1954) The federal judiciary. In: Bowie RR, Friedrich CJ (eds) Studies in federalism. Little, Brown & Co., Boston, pp 106–162
Zurück zum Zitat Fuller LL (1969) The morality of law. Yale University Press, New Haven, 2nd revised edition Fuller LL (1969) The morality of law. Yale University Press, New Haven, 2nd revised edition
Zurück zum Zitat Graf Vitzthum W (2005) Annahme nach Ermessen bei Verfassungsbeschwerden?: Das writ of certiorari-Verfahren des US Supreme Court als ein systemfremdes Entlastungsmodell. JöR 53:319–343 Graf Vitzthum W (2005) Annahme nach Ermessen bei Verfassungsbeschwerden?: Das writ of certiorari-Verfahren des US Supreme Court als ein systemfremdes Entlastungsmodell. JöR 53:319–343
Zurück zum Zitat Hart HLA (1977) Positivism and the separation of law and morals. In: Dworkin RM (ed) The philosophy of law. Oxford University Press, London, pp 17–37 Hart HLA (1977) Positivism and the separation of law and morals. In: Dworkin RM (ed) The philosophy of law. Oxford University Press, London, pp 17–37
Zurück zum Zitat Hart HLA (1997) The concept of law, vol 17, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford Hart HLA (1997) The concept of law, vol 17, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Zurück zum Zitat Hayek FA (2001) The road to Serfdom. Routledge, London Hayek FA (2001) The road to Serfdom. Routledge, London
Zurück zum Zitat Hervey TK (2003) The right to health in European Union law. In: Hervey TK, Kenner J (eds) Economic and social rights under the EU charter of fundamental rights: a legal perspective. Hart, Oxford, pp 193–222 Hervey TK (2003) The right to health in European Union law. In: Hervey TK, Kenner J (eds) Economic and social rights under the EU charter of fundamental rights: a legal perspective. Hart, Oxford, pp 193–222
Zurück zum Zitat Hesse K (1991) Grundzüge des Verfassungsrechts der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, 18th edn. C.F. Müller, Heidelberg Hesse K (1991) Grundzüge des Verfassungsrechts der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, 18th edn. C.F. Müller, Heidelberg
Zurück zum Zitat Heyde W (1999) Justiz in Deutschland: Ein Überblick über Recht und Gerichte der BRD. Press and Information Office of the Federal Government, Bonn (6th improved and revised edition) Heyde W (1999) Justiz in Deutschland: Ein Überblick über Recht und Gerichte der BRD. Press and Information Office of the Federal Government, Bonn (6th improved and revised edition)
Zurück zum Zitat Hoffmann-Riem W (2003) Nachvollziehende Grundrechtskontrolle: Zur Verhältnis von Fach- und Verfassungsgerichtsbarkeit am Beispiel von Konflikten zwischen Medienfreiheit und Persönlichkeitsrecht. AöR 128(1):173–225 Hoffmann-Riem W (2003) Nachvollziehende Grundrechtskontrolle: Zur Verhältnis von Fach- und Verfassungsgerichtsbarkeit am Beispiel von Konflikten zwischen Medienfreiheit und Persönlichkeitsrecht. AöR 128(1):173–225
Zurück zum Zitat Holt W (1985) The first federal question case. Law & Hist Rev 3(1):169–189CrossRef Holt W (1985) The first federal question case. Law & Hist Rev 3(1):169–189CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hume D (2000) A treatise of human nature. Oxford University Press, Oxford Hume D (2000) A treatise of human nature. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Zurück zum Zitat Jackson VC, Tushnet MV (1999) Comparative constitutional law. University casebook series. Foundation Press, New York Jackson VC, Tushnet MV (1999) Comparative constitutional law. University casebook series. Foundation Press, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Jolowicz JA (2000) On civil procedure. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRef Jolowicz JA (2000) On civil procedure. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kau M (2007) United States Supreme Court und Bundesverfassungsgericht: Die Bedeutung des United States Supreme Court für die Errichtung und Fortentwicklung des Bundesverfassungsgerichts. Springer, BerlinCrossRef Kau M (2007) United States Supreme Court und Bundesverfassungsgericht: Die Bedeutung des United States Supreme Court für die Errichtung und Fortentwicklung des Bundesverfassungsgerichts. Springer, BerlinCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kelsen H (1929) Wesen und Entwicklung der Staatsgerichtsbarkeit: Mitbericht von Prof. Hans Kelsen in Wien. In: von Hippel E, Kelsen H, Layer M, Triepel H (eds) Wesen und Entwicklung der Staatsgerichtsbarkeit: Berichte [der] Verhandlungen der Tagung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer zu Wien am 23. und 24. April 1928; mit einem Auszug aus der Aussprache. Walter de Gruyter & Co., Berlin, pp 30–84 Kelsen H (1929) Wesen und Entwicklung der Staatsgerichtsbarkeit: Mitbericht von Prof. Hans Kelsen in Wien. In: von Hippel E, Kelsen H, Layer M, Triepel H (eds) Wesen und Entwicklung der Staatsgerichtsbarkeit: Berichte [der] Verhandlungen der Tagung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer zu Wien am 23. und 24. April 1928; mit einem Auszug aus der Aussprache. Walter de Gruyter & Co., Berlin, pp 30–84
Zurück zum Zitat Kelsen H (2008) Reine Rechtslehre: Einleitung in die rechtswissenschaftliche Problematik, Student version from, 1st edn. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen Kelsen H (2008) Reine Rechtslehre: Einleitung in die rechtswissenschaftliche Problematik, Student version from, 1st edn. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen
Zurück zum Zitat Kenntner M (2005a) Das BVerfG als subsidiärer Superrevisor? NJW 58(12):785–788 Kenntner M (2005a) Das BVerfG als subsidiärer Superrevisor? NJW 58(12):785–788
Zurück zum Zitat Kenntner M (2005b) Vom “Hüter der Verfassung” zum “Pannenhelfer der Nation”?: Zur Kontrolldichte im Verfahren der Urteilsverfassungsbeschwerde. DÖV 58(7):269–279 Kenntner M (2005b) Vom “Hüter der Verfassung” zum “Pannenhelfer der Nation”?: Zur Kontrolldichte im Verfahren der Urteilsverfassungsbeschwerde. DÖV 58(7):269–279
Zurück zum Zitat Kleinfeld R (2006) Competing definitions of the rule of law. In: Carothers T (ed) Promoting the rule of law abroad: in search of knowledge. Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, Washington, pp 31–74 Kleinfeld R (2006) Competing definitions of the rule of law. In: Carothers T (ed) Promoting the rule of law abroad: in search of knowledge. Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, Washington, pp 31–74
Zurück zum Zitat Kommers DP (1997) The constitutional jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany. Duke University Press, Durham, 2nd revised and expanded edition Kommers DP (1997) The constitutional jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany. Duke University Press, Durham, 2nd revised and expanded edition
Zurück zum Zitat Le Sueur AP (ed) (2004) Building the UK's new Supreme Court: national and comparative perspectives. Oxford University Press, Oxford Le Sueur AP (ed) (2004) Building the UK's new Supreme Court: national and comparative perspectives. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Zurück zum Zitat Lovett F (2002) A positivist account of the rule of law. Law & Soc Inquiry 27(1):41–78CrossRef Lovett F (2002) A positivist account of the rule of law. Law & Soc Inquiry 27(1):41–78CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Monaghan HP (1975) The Supreme Court, 1974 term. Harv L Rev 89(1):1–281CrossRef Monaghan HP (1975) The Supreme Court, 1974 term. Harv L Rev 89(1):1–281CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Montesquieu C (1989) The spirit of the laws. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (revised edition) Montesquieu C (1989) The spirit of the laws. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (revised edition)
Zurück zum Zitat Posner RA (1985) Wealth maximization revisited. Notre Dame JL Ethics & Pub Pol’y 2(1):85–106 Posner RA (1985) Wealth maximization revisited. Notre Dame JL Ethics & Pub Pol’y 2(1):85–106
Zurück zum Zitat Pushaw RJ (1996) Justiciability and separation of powers: a neo-federalist approach. Cornell L Rev 81(2):393–512 Pushaw RJ (1996) Justiciability and separation of powers: a neo-federalist approach. Cornell L Rev 81(2):393–512
Zurück zum Zitat Radbruch G (1946) Gesetzliches Unrecht und übergesetzliches Recht. Süddeutsche Juristenzeitung 1(5):105–108 Radbruch G (1946) Gesetzliches Unrecht und übergesetzliches Recht. Süddeutsche Juristenzeitung 1(5):105–108
Zurück zum Zitat Radin MJ (1989) Reconsidering the rule of law. BU L Rev 69(4):781–819 Radin MJ (1989) Reconsidering the rule of law. BU L Rev 69(4):781–819
Zurück zum Zitat Rawls J (1999) A theory of justice. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 2nd revised edition Rawls J (1999) A theory of justice. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 2nd revised edition
Zurück zum Zitat Raz J (2009a) The authority of law: essays on law and morality, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford Raz J (2009a) The authority of law: essays on law and morality, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Zurück zum Zitat Raz J (2009b) The rule of law and its virtue. In: The authority of law: essays on law and morality, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 210–229 Raz J (2009b) The rule of law and its virtue. In: The authority of law: essays on law and morality, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 210–229
Zurück zum Zitat Rivers J (2007) Rechtsstaatsprinzip and rule of law revisited. In: Starck C, Grote R (eds) Die Ordnung der Freiheit: Festschrift für Christian Starck zum siebzigsten Geburtstag. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, pp 891–904 Rivers J (2007) Rechtsstaatsprinzip and rule of law revisited. In: Starck C, Grote R (eds) Die Ordnung der Freiheit: Festschrift für Christian Starck zum siebzigsten Geburtstag. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, pp 891–904
Zurück zum Zitat Roth W (1996) Die Überprüfung fachgerichtlicher Urteile durch das Bundesverfassungsgericht und die Entscheidung über die Annahme einer Verfassungsbeschwerde. AöR 121(4):544–577 Roth W (1996) Die Überprüfung fachgerichtlicher Urteile durch das Bundesverfassungsgericht und die Entscheidung über die Annahme einer Verfassungsbeschwerde. AöR 121(4):544–577
Zurück zum Zitat Saunders C (1995) Constitutional arrangements of federal systems. Publius J Federalism 25(2):61–79 Saunders C (1995) Constitutional arrangements of federal systems. Publius J Federalism 25(2):61–79
Zurück zum Zitat Schlaich K, Korioth S (2010) Das Bundesverfassungsgericht: Stellung, Verfahren, Entscheidungen, 8th edn. Beck, München Schlaich K, Korioth S (2010) Das Bundesverfassungsgericht: Stellung, Verfahren, Entscheidungen, 8th edn. Beck, München
Zurück zum Zitat Schmitt C (1993) Verfassungslehre, 8th edn. Duncker & Humblot, Berlin Schmitt C (1993) Verfassungslehre, 8th edn. Duncker & Humblot, Berlin
Zurück zum Zitat Schuppert GF (1978) Zur Nachprüfung gerichtlicher Entscheidungen durch das Bundesverfassungsgericht. AöR 103(1):43–69 Schuppert GF (1978) Zur Nachprüfung gerichtlicher Entscheidungen durch das Bundesverfassungsgericht. AöR 103(1):43–69
Zurück zum Zitat Schuppert GF (ed) (1999a) Jenseits von Privatisierung und “schlankem” Staat: Verantwortungsteilung als Schlüsselbegriff eines sich verändernden Verhältnisses von öffentlichem und privatem Sektor. Nomos, Baden-Baden Schuppert GF (ed) (1999a) Jenseits von Privatisierung und “schlankem” Staat: Verantwortungsteilung als Schlüsselbegriff eines sich verändernden Verhältnisses von öffentlichem und privatem Sektor. Nomos, Baden-Baden
Zurück zum Zitat Schuppert GF (1999b) Zur notwendigen Neubestimmung der Staatsaufsicht im verantwortungsteilenden Verwaltungsstaat. In: Schuppert GF (ed) Jenseits von Privatisierung und “schlankem” Staat: Verantwortungsteilung als Schlüsselbegriff eines sich verändernden Verhältnisses von öffentlichem und privatem Sektor. Nomos, Baden-Baden, pp 299–330 Schuppert GF (1999b) Zur notwendigen Neubestimmung der Staatsaufsicht im verantwortungsteilenden Verwaltungsstaat. In: Schuppert GF (ed) Jenseits von Privatisierung und “schlankem” Staat: Verantwortungsteilung als Schlüsselbegriff eines sich verändernden Verhältnisses von öffentlichem und privatem Sektor. Nomos, Baden-Baden, pp 299–330
Zurück zum Zitat Schwartz B (2006) French administrative law and the common-law world. Lawbook Exchange, Clark Schwartz B (2006) French administrative law and the common-law world. Lawbook Exchange, Clark
Zurück zum Zitat Secretary General of the United Nations (2004) The rule of law and transitional justice in conflict and post-conflict societies: report of the Secretary General to the Security Council, S/2004/616 Secretary General of the United Nations (2004) The rule of law and transitional justice in conflict and post-conflict societies: report of the Secretary General to the Security Council, S/2004/616
Zurück zum Zitat Shapiro M (1981) Courts: a comparative and political analysis. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago Shapiro M (1981) Courts: a comparative and political analysis. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Zurück zum Zitat Shapiro SJ (2007) The “Hart-Dworkin” debate: a short guide for the perplexed. Public Law and Legal Theory Working Paper Series Shapiro SJ (2007) The “Hart-Dworkin” debate: a short guide for the perplexed. Public Law and Legal Theory Working Paper Series
Zurück zum Zitat Shklar JN (1998) Political theory and the rule of law. In: Hoffmann S, Shklar JN (eds) Political thought and political thinkers. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 21–37 Shklar JN (1998) Political theory and the rule of law. In: Hoffmann S, Shklar JN (eds) Political thought and political thinkers. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 21–37
Zurück zum Zitat Steiner U (2001) Der Richter als Ersatzgesetzgeber: Richterliche Normenkontrolle – Erfahrungen und Erkenntnisse. NJW 54(40):2919–2923 Steiner U (2001) Der Richter als Ersatzgesetzgeber: Richterliche Normenkontrolle – Erfahrungen und Erkenntnisse. NJW 54(40):2919–2923
Zurück zum Zitat Stone Sweet A (1992) The birth of judicial politics in France: The Constitutional Council in comparative perspective. Oxford University Press, New York Stone Sweet A (1992) The birth of judicial politics in France: The Constitutional Council in comparative perspective. Oxford University Press, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Stone Sweet A (2008) Constitutions and judicial power. In: Caramani D (ed) Comparative politics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 217–239 Stone Sweet A (2008) Constitutions and judicial power. In: Caramani D (ed) Comparative politics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 217–239
Zurück zum Zitat Stromseth J, Brooks R, Wippman D (eds) (2006a) Can might make rights? Building the rule of law after military interventions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Stromseth J, Brooks R, Wippman D (eds) (2006a) Can might make rights? Building the rule of law after military interventions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Zurück zum Zitat Stromseth J, Brooks R, Wippman D (2006b) What is the rule of law? A pragmatic definition and a synergistic approach. In: Stromseth J, Brooks R, Wippman D (eds) Can might make rights? Building the rule of law after military interventions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 56–84CrossRef Stromseth J, Brooks R, Wippman D (2006b) What is the rule of law? A pragmatic definition and a synergistic approach. In: Stromseth J, Brooks R, Wippman D (eds) Can might make rights? Building the rule of law after military interventions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 56–84CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Trenor WM (2005) Judicial review before Marbury. Stan L Rev 58:455–562 Trenor WM (2005) Judicial review before Marbury. Stan L Rev 58:455–562
Zurück zum Zitat Winkle JW (1974) Dimensions of judicial federalism. Annals Am Ac Polit SS 416(1):67–76CrossRef Winkle JW (1974) Dimensions of judicial federalism. Annals Am Ac Polit SS 416(1):67–76CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
Rule-of-Law and Judicial Federalism: The Role of Ordinary Courts in the Enforcement of Fundamental Rights
verfasst von
Alfredo Narváez Medécigo
Copyright-Jahr
2016
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-24562-1_2