Skip to main content

2019 | OriginalPaper | Buchkapitel

8. The Limits of Punishment: Of Angels and Bad Men

verfasst von : Thomas J. Miceli

Erschienen in: The Paradox of Punishment

Verlag: Springer International Publishing

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

The chapter explores the limits of criminal punishment as a means of regulating conduct by introducing the role of law in communicating unacceptable behaviors to members of society. This “expressive function” of law can expand the reach of law if least some members of the population are responsive to the idea that disobeying the law is itself wrong or immoral, regardless of the consequences. The chapter examines the implications of this moral dimension of law for the optimal scope of rulemaking and the structure of punishments. It turns out that an increase in the fraction of reflexive law-abiders may make it desirable to expand or contract the scope of law; that is, morality can either be a complement or substitute for the threat of punishment.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
Hart notes that the prototypes of the latter are Holmes’s bad men, who, as we noted, are the epitome of the rational economic agent (Holmes 1897).
 
2
In keeping with this view, Holmes, in his classic treatise on the common law (Holmes 1881), argued that the law had evolved away from ideas of moral culpability and instead operated “based on external standards of conduct that reflected social needs and norms of behavior” (Budiansky 2019, p. 170). That view, however, is not incompatible with the idea that some people are nevertheless impelled to obey the law out of considerations of morality.
 
3
Dharmapala and McAdams (2003) argue that the expressive function may work through the role of the legislature in providing information to citizens about the costs of certain behaviors, which induces them to change their behavior apart from the threat of any punishment.
 
4
The model is based on Coşgel and Miceli (2019).
 
5
Hayek (1960, 1973) invokes the same logic. For example, he argues that a “group may have persisted only because its members have developed and transmitted ways of doing things which made the group as a whole more effective than others” (1973, p. 80). Also, see Posner (1983, p. 205), who makes a similar argument about the survival value of efficiency in a primitive world, and Johnson (2005), who argues that belief in supernatural punishment is adaptive both at the individual and the group level.
 
6
Frank (1987) argues that if they could, people would in fact choose a utility function that embodies a conscience, by which he means an aversion to cheating.
 
7
On this point, see Frank (1990), who argues that if cooperators can detect cheaters by expending some cost, the population will eventually evolve to a stable equilibrium in which both cooperators and cheaters co-exist in some fixed proportions.
 
8
The idea is similar to that discussed by Nozick (1974) regarding the emergence of a state with a monopoly on law enforcement.
 
9
The assumption of certain detection is made merely for simplicity and does not affect the qualitative conclusions of the analysis. See Coşgel and Miceli (2019) for a more general model with a detection probability of p ≤ 1.
 
10
For example, it is a bounty paid to the police.
 
11
We will assume here that the start-up cost of a police force is solely incurred by the group of believers comprising the willing participants in such an enterprise, even though under law enforcement all citizens will end up being cooperators. The point here is to examine the conditions for the emergence of law.
 
12
This of course reflects the same logic as described by Weber with respect to certain Protestant sects (Weber 1930 [2003]).
 
13
The group is all but extinct today. Although there are a handful of Shakers left, they are no longer accepting converts.
 
14
Some other enforcement costs will be truly fixed in that they will also be independent of the crime rate, such as the cost of creating the infrastructure of law enforcement, like building police stations and courthouses. We ignore these costs.
 
15
If the sanction is costly to impose, then the optimal sanction will be less than the sum of the harm plus the cost of enforcement; that is, s  < h + k(s ) (see, e.g., Polinsky and Shavell 2007, p. 410). Thus, the offender incurs a punishment that is less than the total cost he imposes on society (including enforcement costs). In this sense, there is some underdeterrence relative to an ideal outcome. In other words, the marginal crime imposes a greater overall cost on society than the benefit received by the offender. This is a consequence of the fact that raising s is costly.
 
16
This conclusion would not be true if the sanction s were bounded; that is, if s ≤ A, where A is, for example, the maximum ability of the offender to pay a fine. When A < h + k, this constraint would be binding and thus some criminal acts would be inefficient.
 
17
Hart (1982, p. 7) makes a similar point.
 
18
In fact, all drivers know that police will not generally apprehend drivers who slightly exceed the posted speed limit, which means that the effective speed limit (i.e., the threshold that actually will result in a sanction) is somewhat higher than the actual posted number.
 
19
Analytically, the results would be the same if we continued to count the offender’s gains but simply assumed that the harm from the act exceeds the gains to the offender who values the activity most. The idea of not counting the gains at all, however, seems to be a qualitatively different situation and one more in line with crimes of the sort we are considering here.
 
20
This would not necessarily be the case if the cost of enforcement depends on s (as is true of punishment by imprisonment). In that case, the optimal sanction would balance the marginal deterrence benefits against the marginal cost of raising s.
 
21
There is some risk of tautology here since, as we have argued, some people’s moral code is in fact shaped by law, as Shavell (2002, p. 254) recognizes. We pursue this point below.
 
22
Note that this is the converse of civil disobedience, which occurs when a person violates a law precisely because he or she believes its content is not moral or righteous. See, for example, Rawls (1971, Chapter VI)
 
23
Holmes (1881, p. 118) makes a similar point when he asks, “If we accept the test of liability alone, how do we distinguish…between conduct that is prohibited, and that which is merely taxed?”
 
24
See Katz (1987, pp. 64–65), Shavell (2004, pp. 565–566), and White (2018, p. 319).
 
25
This standard for categorizing potentially harmful acts is reminiscent of the Supreme Court’s ruling on the question of what constitutes obscenity in Jacobellis v. Ohio (378 U.S. 184, 1964). In that case, Justice Potter Stewart famously said that, although he could not define what obscenity is, he knew it when he saw it.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Andrews, E., and F. Andrews. 1974. Work and Worship Among the Shakers: Their Craftsmanship and Economic Order. New York: Dover Publications. Andrews, E., and F. Andrews. 1974. Work and Worship Among the Shakers: Their Craftsmanship and Economic Order. New York: Dover Publications.
Zurück zum Zitat Becker, Gary. 1968. Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach. Journal of Political Economy 76: 169–217.CrossRef Becker, Gary. 1968. Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach. Journal of Political Economy 76: 169–217.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Buchanan, James. 1965. Ethical Values, Expected Values, and Large Numbers. Ethics 76: 1–13.CrossRef Buchanan, James. 1965. Ethical Values, Expected Values, and Large Numbers. Ethics 76: 1–13.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Budiansky, Stephen. 2019. Oliver Wendell Holmes: A Life in War, Law, and Ideas. New York: W. W. Norton & Co. Budiansky, Stephen. 2019. Oliver Wendell Holmes: A Life in War, Law, and Ideas. New York: W. W. Norton & Co.
Zurück zum Zitat Cooter, Robert. 1998. Expressive Law and Economics. The Journal of Legal Studies 27: 585–607.CrossRef Cooter, Robert. 1998. Expressive Law and Economics. The Journal of Legal Studies 27: 585–607.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2005. The Confluence of Justice and Efficiency in the Economic Analysis of Law. In The Origins of Law and Economics: Essays of the Founding Fathers, ed. F. Parisi and C. Rowley. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. ———. 2005. The Confluence of Justice and Efficiency in the Economic Analysis of Law. In The Origins of Law and Economics: Essays of the Founding Fathers, ed. F. Parisi and C. Rowley. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2006. The Intrinsic Value of Obeying a Law: Economic Analysis of the Internal Viewpoint. Fordham Law Review 75: 1275–1285. ———. 2006. The Intrinsic Value of Obeying a Law: Economic Analysis of the Internal Viewpoint. Fordham Law Review 75: 1275–1285.
Zurück zum Zitat Coşgel, Metin, and Thomas J. Miceli. 2009. State and Religion. Journal of Comparative Economics 37: 402–416.CrossRef Coşgel, Metin, and Thomas J. Miceli. 2009. State and Religion. Journal of Comparative Economics 37: 402–416.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2019. Toward a Theory of Religious Belief and the Emergence of Law. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics (forthcoming). ———. 2019. Toward a Theory of Religious Belief and the Emergence of Law. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics (forthcoming).
Zurück zum Zitat Dharmapala, Dhammika, and Richard McAdams. 2003. The Condorcet Jury Theorem and the Expressive Function of Law: A Theory of Informative Law. American Law and Economics Review 5: 1–31.CrossRef Dharmapala, Dhammika, and Richard McAdams. 2003. The Condorcet Jury Theorem and the Expressive Function of Law: A Theory of Informative Law. American Law and Economics Review 5: 1–31.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Etzioni, Amitai. 1999. Back to the Pillory? The American Scholar 68: 43–50. Etzioni, Amitai. 1999. Back to the Pillory? The American Scholar 68: 43–50.
Zurück zum Zitat Frank, Robert. 1987. If Homo Economicus Could Choose His Own Utility Function, Would He Want One with a Conscience? American Economic Review 77: 593–604. Frank, Robert. 1987. If Homo Economicus Could Choose His Own Utility Function, Would He Want One with a Conscience? American Economic Review 77: 593–604.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 1990. A Theory of Moral Sentiments. In Beyond Self-Interest, ed. J. Mansbridge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ———. 1990. A Theory of Moral Sentiments. In Beyond Self-Interest, ed. J. Mansbridge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Friedman, David. 2000. Law’s Order: What Economics Has to Do with the Law and Why It Matters. Princeton, N.J: Princeton University Press. Friedman, David. 2000. Law’s Order: What Economics Has to Do with the Law and Why It Matters. Princeton, N.J: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Hart, H.L.A. 1961. The Concept of Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hart, H.L.A. 1961. The Concept of Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 1982. Punishment and Responsibility: Essays in the Philosophy and Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ———. 1982. Punishment and Responsibility: Essays in the Philosophy and Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Hayek, F.A. 1960. The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hayek, F.A. 1960. The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 1973. Law and Legislation: A New Statement of the Liberal Principles of Justice and Political Economy, Volume I: Rules and Order. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ———. 1973. Law and Legislation: A New Statement of the Liberal Principles of Justice and Political Economy, Volume I: Rules and Order. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Holmes, Oliver Wendell. 1881 [1963]. The Common Law. Boston: Little Brown. Holmes, Oliver Wendell. 1881 [1963]. The Common Law. Boston: Little Brown.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 1897. The Path of the Law. Harvard Law Review 10: 457–478.CrossRef ———. 1897. The Path of the Law. Harvard Law Review 10: 457–478.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Iannaccone, L., R. Finke, and R. Stark. 1997. Deregulating Religion: The Economics of Church and State. Economic Inquiry 35: 350–364.CrossRef Iannaccone, L., R. Finke, and R. Stark. 1997. Deregulating Religion: The Economics of Church and State. Economic Inquiry 35: 350–364.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Johnson, Dominic. 2005. God’s Punishment and Public Goods: A Test of the Supernatural Punishment Hypothesis in 186 World Cultures. Human Nature 16: 410–446.CrossRef Johnson, Dominic. 2005. God’s Punishment and Public Goods: A Test of the Supernatural Punishment Hypothesis in 186 World Cultures. Human Nature 16: 410–446.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2016. God Is Watching You: How the Fear of God Makes Us Human. New York: Oxford University Press. ———. 2016. God Is Watching You: How the Fear of God Makes Us Human. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Kahan, Dan. 1998. Social Meaning and the Economic Analysis of Crime. The Journal of Legal Studies 27: 609–622.CrossRef Kahan, Dan. 1998. Social Meaning and the Economic Analysis of Crime. The Journal of Legal Studies 27: 609–622.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Katz, Leo. 1987. Bad Acts and Guilty Minds: Conundrums of the Criminal Law. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRef Katz, Leo. 1987. Bad Acts and Guilty Minds: Conundrums of the Criminal Law. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Lewin, Jeff, and William Trumbull. 1990. The Social Value of Crime? International Review of Law and Economics 10: 271–284.CrossRef Lewin, Jeff, and William Trumbull. 1990. The Social Value of Crime? International Review of Law and Economics 10: 271–284.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Madison, James. 2008. The Federalist, 51. In The Federalist Papers, ed. L. Goldman. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Madison, James. 2008. The Federalist, 51. In The Federalist Papers, ed. L. Goldman. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Mungan, Murat. 2012. The Scope of Criminal Law. In Research Handbook on the Economics of Criminal Law, ed. A. Harel and K. Hylton. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. Mungan, Murat. 2012. The Scope of Criminal Law. In Research Handbook on the Economics of Criminal Law, ed. A. Harel and K. Hylton. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Zurück zum Zitat Norenzayan, A. 2013. Big Gods: How Religion Transformed Cooperation and Conflict. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef Norenzayan, A. 2013. Big Gods: How Religion Transformed Cooperation and Conflict. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books. Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Parisi, Francesco, and Giuseppe Dari-Mattiacci. 2004. The Rise and Fall of Communal Liability in Ancient Law. International Review of Law and Economics 24: 489–505.CrossRef Parisi, Francesco, and Giuseppe Dari-Mattiacci. 2004. The Rise and Fall of Communal Liability in Ancient Law. International Review of Law and Economics 24: 489–505.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Polinsky, A. Mitchell, and Steven Shavell. 2007. The Theory of Public Law Enforcement. In Handbook of Law and Economics, ed. A.M. Polinsky and S. Shavell, vol. I. Amsterdam: Elsevier, North-Holland. Polinsky, A. Mitchell, and Steven Shavell. 2007. The Theory of Public Law Enforcement. In Handbook of Law and Economics, ed. A.M. Polinsky and S. Shavell, vol. I. Amsterdam: Elsevier, North-Holland.
Zurück zum Zitat Posner, Richard. 1983. The Economics of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Posner, Richard. 1983. The Economics of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Shavell, Steven. 2002. Law Versus Morality as Regulators of Conduct. American Law and Economics Review 4: 227–257.CrossRef Shavell, Steven. 2002. Law Versus Morality as Regulators of Conduct. American Law and Economics Review 4: 227–257.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2004. Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. ———. 2004. Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Smith, Adam. 1759 [1976]. A Theory of Moral Sentiments. New York: Liberty Press. Smith, Adam. 1759 [1976]. A Theory of Moral Sentiments. New York: Liberty Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Stark, Rodney. 2007. Discovering God: The Origins of the Great Religions and the Evolution of Belief. New York: Harper-Collins. Stark, Rodney. 2007. Discovering God: The Origins of the Great Religions and the Evolution of Belief. New York: Harper-Collins.
Zurück zum Zitat Sunstein, Cass. 1996. On the Expressive Function of Law. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 144: 2021–2053.CrossRef Sunstein, Cass. 1996. On the Expressive Function of Law. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 144: 2021–2053.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Wade, Nicholas. 2009. The Faith Instinct: How Religion Evolved and Why It Endures. New York: Penguin Books. Wade, Nicholas. 2009. The Faith Instinct: How Religion Evolved and Why It Endures. New York: Penguin Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Weber, Max. 1930 [2003]. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Mineola: Dover Publications. Weber, Max. 1930 [2003]. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Mineola: Dover Publications.
Zurück zum Zitat White, Mark. 2018. The Neglected Nuance of Beccaria’s Theory of Punishment. European Journal of Law and Economics 46: 315–329.CrossRef White, Mark. 2018. The Neglected Nuance of Beccaria’s Theory of Punishment. European Journal of Law and Economics 46: 315–329.CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
The Limits of Punishment: Of Angels and Bad Men
verfasst von
Thomas J. Miceli
Copyright-Jahr
2019
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-31695-2_8