Skip to main content
Top
Published in: The Journal of Value Inquiry 1/2018

15-11-2017

Categorical Desires and the Badness of Animal Death

Authors: Matt Bower, Bob Fischer

Published in: The Journal of Value Inquiry | Issue 1/2018

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Excerpt

Here’s a common thought: as long as an animal has a good life, it isn’t wrong to kill it. One way to justify this view is to argue that death isn’t bad for animals. If that’s so, then although the animal may be deprived of future goods, it isn’t harmed as a result. And if killing doesn’t involve harm, then it’s hard to see how it could be intrinsically wrong.1 In a number of publications, Christopher Belshaw (2009, 2015, 2016) takes exactly this line. On his view, “[d]eath is bad for you (in the way that matters) only when it cuts off a good and unfolding life that, not unreasonably, you want now, or wanted earlier, to live,”2 and “[animals] don’t have desires for more life, or desires for that which gives them reason to want more life” (2015, pp. 13–14). Elsewhere, he fleshes out the latter idea:
[Animals] have no rounded conception of time, or of themselves as creatures who persist through time, and take no stance regarding their own futures… And even if they can have some rudimentary future-directed desires—a dog wants its master to come home and take it for a walk—they can’t derive from these desires any reasons to go on living. They neither want to live for its own sake, nor do they want things, in the future, for which continuing to live is necessary and which provide reasons for their living on. In brief, they lack what have been called categorical desires (2016, 36).
Bradley and McDaniel (2013) and Bradley (2016) are critical of the view that categorical desires are relevant to the badness of death, and we share their skepticism. However, their arguments invite familiar philosophical moves: Belshaw will add some epicycles or bite some bullets, and the standoff will continue.3

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
Granted, there might be other reasons not to slaughter animals—e.g., environmental considerations for domestic animals, and worries about animal families for wild ones—but such concerns won’t occupy us here.
 
2
The parenthetical qualification is designed to distinguish those cases that do and do not give us reason to prevent death. So, for example it might well be the case that death is bad for plants, but presumably it isn’t bad in the way that matters, which is to say that we have no intrinsic reason to prevent the deaths of plants. Should they serve some agricultural, aesthetic, or similarly important end, then saving plants might make perfect sense. The point is just that, apart from such reasons, their deaths may well be bad for them, but not in a way that provides us with reason to act.
 
3
For instance, it’s no good to criticize Belshaw, as Bradley (2016) does, based on the odd consequences of a categorical desire account of the badness of death. Belshaw has received this criticism before, and now accepts the consequences that Bradley regards as counterexamples to the view—e.g., that it isn’t bad for babies to die. “I claim it is not bad, in the way that matters, for babies to die. Even when, predictably, their future life will be good and, again predictably, they will let some time want very much to continue with it, this life isn’t something in which they have any interest now” (2015, p. 14).
 
4
See Varner (2012) for discussion. Note, however, that in his treatment of animal cognition, Varner makes a significant leap in ascending from more to less basic forms of animal cognition, skipping from sentience right over to autonoetic mental states, and not placing much emphasis on desires.
 
5
See note 3.
 
6
Belshaw borrows the example from Bradley (2016), who thinks we ought to say the cow’s desire is about its future, but doesn’t explain why.
 
7
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for helping us see the connection between these desires and what makes a chicken’s life worth living.
 
8
Even though we’ve labeled this sort of semantic theory “forward-looking,” it’s not true that all content posited by this theory or other forward-looking semantic theories is future directed. That would no doubt count against any such theory, as it would then have difficulty accounting for the content of memory at all and face severe restrictions in its ability to explain the content of a variety of other mental states as well that aren’t necessarily future directed. But when it comes to desires, quite unlike memories, it is natural to suppose the functional role they play is largely if not wholly future-directed, and that its content will reflect this.
 
9
Note that teleosemantics is not the only forward-looking or benefit-based theory of mental content. The pragmatist approach to semantics championed by C.S. Peirce and William James is another version of the idea. Very roughly, and borrowing James’ words, the pragmatist position is that “to develop a thought’s meaning, we need only determine what conduct it is fitted to produce” (James [1907] 2000, p. 25). There is also the success semantics of Whyte, according to which “[t]he truth of beliefs explains the success of the actions they cause” (Whyte 1990, p. 149). You can take these views either as competing with (Blackburn 2005) or complementing (Papineau 1993) Millikan-style teleosemantics. You might prefer those approaches, depending on your philosophical sensibilities. If the appeal to biological function in teleosemantics seems dubious to you, or if you’re skeptical of its reductionist aspirations, you might opt for a version of our story retold in terms of these theories. We see no reason why they would fail to apply just as well to the cases of animal behavior we’ve discussed. Bermudez (2003), to cite a prominent example, accounts for mental content in non-human animals with a version of success semantics. We should also note that if you are skeptical about attributing mental content to non-human animals because you think content only comes packaged together with language, our story can be re-fashioned to accommodate this. Intentional states like belief can be decoupled from propositional (or conceptual) content and still plausibly be attributed to animals (Glock 2013). Moreover, Daniel Hutto (2007) and Erik Myin (Hutto and Myin 2013) defend a Millikan-esque “teleosemiotics” that could easily fill the role that teleosemantics plays in our story. It would explain the intentionality of mental states, but without construing them as having content (i.e., accuracy conditions) of any kind.
 
10
To take this line is to endorse a version of the precautionary principle. Some versions of the precautionary principle can get us into serious trouble: if we start attributing categorical desires to insects, for example, we will probably need to radically revise our ideas about what we ought to do—see Fischer (2016) and Sebo (ms). However, since we rely on precautionary reasoning in so many contexts, we think that it’s safe to appeal to it here, and we’ll have to bank on their being some way of drawing a line between reasonable and excessive levels of moral caution. Moreover, note that our argument here only commits us to saying the deaths of animals can be bad for them—not that any particular practical conclusion follows. As an instance of precautionary reasoning, ours is a fairly modest one.
 
Literature
go back to reference Allen, Collin (2000). “Animal concepts revisited: The use of self-monitoring as an empirical approach.” Erkenntnis 51, pp. 33–40. Allen, Collin (2000). “Animal concepts revisited: The use of self-monitoring as an empirical approach.” Erkenntnis 51, pp. 33–40.
go back to reference Andrews, Kristin (2015). Animal Minds: an Introduction to the Philosophy of Animal Cognition. London: Routledge. Andrews, Kristin (2015). Animal Minds: an Introduction to the Philosophy of Animal Cognition. London: Routledge.
go back to reference Belshaw, Chris (2009). Annihilation: The Sense and Significance of Death. New York: Acumen. Belshaw, Chris (2009). Annihilation: The Sense and Significance of Death. New York: Acumen.
go back to reference Belshaw, Chris (2013). “Death, value, and desire.” In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death. B. Bradley, F. Feldman, and J. Johansson (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Belshaw, Chris (2013). “Death, value, and desire.” In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death. B. Bradley, F. Feldman, and J. Johansson (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Belshaw, Chris (2015). “Victims.” In Immortality and the Philosophy of Death (pp. 3–20). M. Cholbi (ed.). New York: Rowman and Littlefield. Belshaw, Chris (2015). “Victims.” In Immortality and the Philosophy of Death (pp. 3–20). M. Cholbi (ed.). New York: Rowman and Littlefield.
go back to reference Belshaw, Chris (2016). “Death, pain, and animal life.” In The Ethics of Killing Animals (pp. 32–50). Visak and R. Garner (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Belshaw, Chris (2016). “Death, pain, and animal life.” In The Ethics of Killing Animals (pp. 32–50). Visak and R. Garner (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Bermudez, Jose Luis (2003). Thinking Without Words. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bermudez, Jose Luis (2003). Thinking Without Words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Blackburn, Simon (2005). “Success semantics.” In Ramsey’s Legacy (pp. 22–36). H. Lillehammer and H.D. Mellor (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Blackburn, Simon (2005). “Success semantics.” In Ramsey’s Legacy (pp. 22–36). H. Lillehammer and H.D. Mellor (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Bradley, Ben (2016). “Is death bad for a cow?” In The Ethics of Killing Animals (pp. 51–64). Visak and R. Garner (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bradley, Ben (2016). “Is death bad for a cow?” In The Ethics of Killing Animals (pp. 51–64). Visak and R. Garner (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Bradley, B. and K. McDaniel (2013). “Death and desires.” In The Metaphysics and Ethics of Death (pp. 118–133). J.S. Taylor (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bradley, B. and K. McDaniel (2013). “Death and desires.” In The Metaphysics and Ethics of Death (pp. 118–133). J.S. Taylor (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Brown, Culum (2015). “Fish intelligence, sentience and ethics.” Animal Cognition 18(1), pp. 1–17. Brown, Culum (2015). “Fish intelligence, sentience and ethics.” Animal Cognition 18(1), pp. 1–17.
go back to reference Carbonaro, D.A., T.H. Friend, G.R. Dellmeier, and L.C. Nuti (1992). “Behavioral and physiological responses of dairy goats to food thwarting.” Physiology and Behavior 51(2), pp. 303–308. Carbonaro, D.A., T.H. Friend, G.R. Dellmeier, and L.C. Nuti (1992). “Behavioral and physiological responses of dairy goats to food thwarting.” Physiology and Behavior 51(2), pp. 303–308.
go back to reference Costa, J.H.C., M.A.G. von Keyserlingk, and D.M. Weary (2016). “Effects of group housing of dairy calves on behavior, cognition, performance, and health.” Journal of Dairy Science 99(4), pp. 2453–2467. Costa, J.H.C., M.A.G. von Keyserlingk, and D.M. Weary (2016). “Effects of group housing of dairy calves on behavior, cognition, performance, and health.” Journal of Dairy Science 99(4), pp. 2453–2467.
go back to reference Daros, R.R., J.H.C. Costa, M.A.G. von Keyserlingk, M.J. Hötzel, and D.M. Weary (2014). “Separation from the dam causes negative judgement bias in dairy calves.” PLoS ONE 9(5), p. e98429. Daros, R.R., J.H.C. Costa, M.A.G. von Keyserlingk, M.J. Hötzel, and D.M. Weary (2014). “Separation from the dam causes negative judgement bias in dairy calves.” PLoS ONE 9(5), p. e98429.
go back to reference Gaillard, Charlotte, Rebecca K. Meagher, Marina A.G. von Keyserlingk, and Daniel M. Weary (2014). “Social Housing Improves Dairy Calves’ Performance in Two Cognitive Tests.” PLoS ONE 9(2), p. e90205. Gaillard, Charlotte, Rebecca K. Meagher, Marina A.G. von Keyserlingk, and Daniel M. Weary (2014). “Social Housing Improves Dairy Calves’ Performance in Two Cognitive Tests.” PLoS ONE 9(2), p. e90205.
go back to reference Dretske, Fred (1986). “Misrepresentation.” In Belief: Form, Content, and Function (pp. 17–36). R. Bogdan (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dretske, Fred (1986). “Misrepresentation.” In Belief: Form, Content, and Function (pp. 17–36). R. Bogdan (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Glock, Hans-Johann (2010). “Animal agency.” In A Companion to the Philosophy of Action. T. O’Connor and C. Sandis (eds.). Oxford: Blackwell. Glock, Hans-Johann (2010). “Animal agency.” In A Companion to the Philosophy of Action. T. O’Connor and C. Sandis (eds.). Oxford: Blackwell.
go back to reference Glock, Hans-Johann (2013). “Animal minds: A non-representationalist approach.” American Philosophical Quarterly 50(3), pp. 213–232. Glock, Hans-Johann (2013). “Animal minds: A non-representationalist approach.” American Philosophical Quarterly 50(3), pp. 213–232.
go back to reference Hagen, Kristin and Donald M. Broom (2004). “Emotional reactions to learning in cattle.” Applied Animal Behaviour Science 85(3), pp. 203–213. Hagen, Kristin and Donald M. Broom (2004). “Emotional reactions to learning in cattle.” Applied Animal Behaviour Science 85(3), pp. 203–213.
go back to reference Hutto, Daniel (2007). Folk Psychological Narratives: The Sociocultural Basis of Understanding Reasons. Cambridge: MIT Press. Hutto, Daniel (2007). Folk Psychological Narratives: The Sociocultural Basis of Understanding Reasons. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Hutto, Daniel and Erik Myin (2013). Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds Without Content. Cambridge: MIT Press. Hutto, Daniel and Erik Myin (2013). Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds Without Content. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference James, Williams (2000). Pragmatism and Other Writings. In G. Gunn (ed.). New York: Penguin Books. James, Williams (2000). Pragmatism and Other Writings. In G. Gunn (ed.). New York: Penguin Books.
go back to reference Mendl, Michael, Suzanne Held, and Richard W. Byrne (2010). “Pig cognition.” Current Biology 20(18), pp. R796–R798. Mendl, Michael, Suzanne Held, and Richard W. Byrne (2010). “Pig cognition.” Current Biology 20(18), pp. R796–R798.
go back to reference Mendl, Michael and C.J. Nicol (2009). “Learning and cognition.” In The Ethology of Domestic Animals, 2nd Ed. (pp. 57–72). P. Jensen (ed.). Wallingford: CABI. Mendl, Michael and C.J. Nicol (2009). “Learning and cognition.” In The Ethology of Domestic Animals, 2nd Ed. (pp. 57–72). P. Jensen (ed.). Wallingford: CABI.
go back to reference Mendl, Michael and Elizabeth S. Paul (2008). “Do animals live in the present? Current evidence and implications for welfare.” Applied Animal Behaviour Science 113(4), pp. 357–382. Mendl, Michael and Elizabeth S. Paul (2008). “Do animals live in the present? Current evidence and implications for welfare.” Applied Animal Behaviour Science 113(4), pp. 357–382.
go back to reference Millikan, Ruth (1984). Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge: MIT Press. Millikan, Ruth (1984). Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Millikan, Ruth (1986). “Thoughts without laws: Cognitive science with content.” The Philosophical Review 45(1), pp. 47–80. Millikan, Ruth (1986). “Thoughts without laws: Cognitive science with content.” The Philosophical Review 45(1), pp. 47–80.
go back to reference Papineau, David (1993). Philosophical Naturalism. Oxford: Blackwell. Papineau, David (1993). Philosophical Naturalism. Oxford: Blackwell.
go back to reference Papineau, David (2003). “Is representation rife?” Ratio 16(2), pp. 107–123. Papineau, David (2003). “Is representation rife?” Ratio 16(2), pp. 107–123.
go back to reference Rachels, S. (2011). “Vegetarianism.” In The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics. Tom Beauchamp and R.G. Frey (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 877–905. Rachels, S. (2011). “Vegetarianism.” In The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics. Tom Beauchamp and R.G. Frey (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 877–905.
go back to reference Roper, T.J. (1984). “Response of thirsty rats to absence of water: Frustration, disinhibition, or compensation?” Animal Behavior 32(4), pp. 1225–1235. Roper, T.J. (1984). “Response of thirsty rats to absence of water: Frustration, disinhibition, or compensation?” Animal Behavior 32(4), pp. 1225–1235.
go back to reference Rowlands, Mark (1994). “The mental life of some animals.” Between The Species 10(3), pp. 87–97. Rowlands, Mark (1994). “The mental life of some animals.” Between The Species 10(3), pp. 87–97.
go back to reference Sebo, Jeff. ms. “Reconsider the Lobster.” (Unpublished manuscript.). Sebo, Jeff. ms. “Reconsider the Lobster.” (Unpublished manuscript.).
go back to reference Steward, Helen (2009). “Animal agency.” Inquiry 52(3), pp. 217–231. Steward, Helen (2009). “Animal agency.” Inquiry 52(3), pp. 217–231.
go back to reference Suddendorf, T. and M.C. Corballis (2007). “The evolution of foresight: What is mental time-travel, and is it unique to humans?” Brain and Behavioral Science 30(3), pp. 313–351. Suddendorf, T. and M.C. Corballis (2007). “The evolution of foresight: What is mental time-travel, and is it unique to humans?” Brain and Behavioral Science 30(3), pp. 313–351.
go back to reference Varner, G. (2012). Personhood, Ethics, and Animal Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Varner, G. (2012). Personhood, Ethics, and Animal Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Weatherson, Brian (2014). “Running Risks Morally.” Philosophical Studies 167(1), pp. 141–163. Weatherson, Brian (2014). “Running Risks Morally.” Philosophical Studies 167(1), pp. 141–163.
go back to reference Whyte, J.T (1990). “Success semantics.” Analysis 50(3), pp. 149–157. Whyte, J.T (1990). “Success semantics.” Analysis 50(3), pp. 149–157.
go back to reference Williams, Bernard (1973). “The Makropulos case: Reflections on the tedium of immortality.” In Problems of the Self: Philosophical Papers 1956–1972 (pp. 82–100). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Williams, Bernard (1973). “The Makropulos case: Reflections on the tedium of immortality.” In Problems of the Self: Philosophical Papers 1956–1972 (pp. 82–100). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Metadata
Title
Categorical Desires and the Badness of Animal Death
Authors
Matt Bower
Bob Fischer
Publication date
15-11-2017
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
The Journal of Value Inquiry / Issue 1/2018
Print ISSN: 0022-5363
Electronic ISSN: 1573-0492
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-017-9604-y

Other articles of this Issue 1/2018

The Journal of Value Inquiry 1/2018 Go to the issue

OriginalPaper

Small-Scale Evil