Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Applied Categorical Structures 1/2021

Open Access 20-08-2020

Crossed Modules of Monoids III. Simplicial Monoids of Moore Length 1

Author: Gabriella Böhm

Published in: Applied Categorical Structures | Issue 1/2021

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

This is the last part of a series of three strongly related papers in which three equivalent structures are studied:
  • Internal categories in categories of monoids; defined in terms of pullbacks relative to a chosen class of spans
  • Crossed modules of monoids relative to this class of spans
  • Simplicial monoids of so-called Moore length 1 relative to this class of spans.
The most important examples of monoids that are covered are small categories (treated as monoids in categories of spans) and bimonoids in symmetric monoidal categories (regarded as monoids in categories of comonoids). In this third part relative simplicial monoids are analyzed. Their Moore length is introduced and the equivalence is proven between relative simplicial monoids of Moore length 1, and relative categories of monoids in Part I. This equivalence is obtained in one direction by truncating a simplicial monoid at the first two degrees; and in the other direction by taking the simplicial nerve of a relative category.
Notes
Communicated by George Janelidze.

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

1 Introduction

Whitehead’s crossed modules of groups [22] received a lot of attention because of their appearance in many different contexts; see the review articles [1719] and the references in them. In many of the applications they did not appear in their original form; but in the disguise of the equivalent notion of internal groupoid in the category of groups—also called a strict 2-group—(see [6, 7, 13] for proofs of the equivalence).
Groups can be regarded as (distinguished) monoids in the cartesian monoidal category of sets. In our antecedent papers [3] and [4] we worked out the notion of crossed module of monoids in more general, not necessarily cartesian monoidal categories, relative to a chosen suitable class of spans. The main examples described by the theory are crossed modules of monoids in [16], groupoids in [5] and crossed modules of Hopf monoids in [1, 1012, 15].
The aim of this article is to extend to this level of generality a third equivalent description of crossed modules of groups: as simplicial groups whose Moore complex has length 1. Recall that for any simplicial group, the Moore complex is the associated chain complex, which is given at each degree by the joint kernel of the face maps of positive label, and the restriction of the zero’th face map as the differential (this is part of the Dold-Kan correspondence). A chain complex—so in particular the Moore complex—is said to have length \(\ell \) if it is trivial for all degrees greater than \(\ell \).
We consider simplicial monoids; that is, functors from the opposite of the simplicial category \(\Delta \) to the category of monoids in some monoidal category \({\mathsf {C}}\). Assuming the existence of certain relative pullbacks (cf. [3]), in Sect. 2 we associate to a simplicial monoid a sequence of morphisms which yields a chain complex whenever the monoidal unit of \({\mathsf {C}}\) is a terminal (hence zero) object in the category of monoids in \({\mathsf {C}}\). It can be seen as a generalization of the Moore complex of a simplicial group. We also give a meaning to its length, and study the consequences of its having some finite length n.
Section 3 contains some technical material about the invertibility of a certain canonical morphism playing an essential role in the theory.
The main result can be found in Sect. 4 where we prove an equivalence between the category of relative categories in the category of monoids in \({\mathsf {C}}\) (cf. [3]) and the category of relative simplicial monoids in \({\mathsf {C}}\) whose Moore length is 1. The functors establishing the equivalence carry transparent meanings. For obtaining a relative category from a simplicial monoid we truncate it at the first two degrees. In the opposite direction, a simplicial monoid is obtained from a relative category of monoids as the (relative) simplicial nerve.
In the particular monoidal category of spans over a given set, we obtain an equivalence between the categories of certain double categories, and of certain simplicial categories. These equivalent categories contain, as equivalent full subcategories, the category of 2-groupoids on one hand, and the category of crossed modules of groupoids on the other hand.
In the particular monoidal category of comonoids in some symmetric monoidal category \({\mathsf {M}}\), we obtain an equivalence between the categories of certain category objects in the category of bimonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\), and of certain simplicial bimonoids. These equivalent categories contain, as equivalent full subcategories, the category of internal categories in the category of cocommutative Hopf monoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\) on one hand, and the category of simplicial cocommutative Hopf monoids of Moore length 1 on the other hand. This includes, in particular, the equivalence in [8] between the category objects in the category of cocommutative Hopf algebras over a field, and the category of simplicial cocommutative Hopf algebras whose Moore complex has length 1.
Throughout, we freely use definitions, notation and results from [3, 4]. The composition of some morphisms https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq12_HTML.gif and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq13_HTML.gif in an arbitrary category will be denoted by https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq14_HTML.gif . Identity morphisms will be denoted by 1 (without any reference to the (co)domain object if it causes no confusion). In any monoidal category \({\mathsf {C}}\) the monoidal product will be denoted by juxtaposition and the monoidal unit will be I. For the monoidal product of n copies of the same object A also the power notation \(A^n\) will be used. For any monoid A in \({\mathsf {C}}\), the multiplication and the unit morphisms will be denoted by https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq18_HTML.gif and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq19_HTML.gif , respectively. If \({\mathsf {C}}\) is also braided, then for the braiding the symbol c will be used.

2 The Moore Length

Recall that a simplicial object in an arbitrary category \({\mathsf {C}}\) is a functor S from the opposite of the simplicial indexing category to \({\mathsf {C}}\). Explicitly, this means objects and morphisms of \({\mathsf {C}}\) in
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ1_HTML.png
(1)
subject to the following simplicial relations.
$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{ll} \partial _i \cdot \partial _j = \partial _{j-1}\cdot \partial _i &{} \text { if } i<j\\ {}&{} {}\\ \sigma _j\cdot \sigma _i =\sigma _i \cdot \sigma _{j-1} &{} \text { if } i<j \end{array} \qquad \partial _i \cdot \sigma _j = \left\{ \begin{array}{cl} \sigma _{j-1} \cdot \partial _i &{} \text { if } i<j\\ 1 &{} \text { if } i\in \{j,j+1\} \\ \sigma _{j} \cdot \partial _{i-1} &{} \text { if } i>j+1 \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$
In the category of groups (and in more general semi-abelian categories [14]), a chain complex—the so called Moore complex—can be associated to any simplicial object. The full subcategory of those simplicial objects whose Moore complex has length 1, turns out to be equivalent to the category of crossed modules and to the category of internal categories in the semi-abelian category in question, see e.g. [19] (in the case of the category of groups) and [9, 21] (more generally).
However, as in [3] and [4], here we work in categories (of monoids in some monoidal category \({\mathsf {C}}\)) where the existence of zero objects is not assumed. So the notion of chain complex is not available. We shall see below, however, that when certain relative pullbacks exist, we can still associate to a simplicial object S a sequence of composable morphisms (reproducing the Moore complex whenever the monoidal unit of \({\mathsf {C}}\) is terminal in the category of monoids in \({\mathsf {C}}\)). Although the chain condition can not be formulated at this level of generality, there is a natural way to define the length of this sequence that we call the Moore length of the simplicial monoid S.
The construction of this sequence of composable morphisms is based on Assumption 2.1 below.
Recall that a class \({\mathcal {S}}\) of spans in an arbitrary category is said to be admissible if it satisfies the following two properties in ([3], Definition 2.1).
(POST)
If https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq28_HTML.gif then https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq29_HTML.gif too, for any morphisms https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq30_HTML.gif and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq31_HTML.gif .
 
(PRE)
If https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq32_HTML.gif then https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq33_HTML.gif , for any morphism https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq34_HTML.gif .
 
The relative pullback of a cospan https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq35_HTML.gif with respect to such a class \({\mathcal {S}}\) was introduced in ([3], Definition 3.1) as a span https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq37_HTML.gif in \({\mathcal {S}}\) satisfying the following properties.
  • Commutativity of the diagram
    https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ28_HTML.png
  • Universality. For any https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq39_HTML.gif such that \(f\cdot f'=g\cdot g'\), there is a unique morphism https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq41_HTML.gif which satisfies \(p_A \cdot h =f'\) and \(p_C \cdot h =g'\).
  • Reflection. If both
    https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ29_HTML.png
    belong to \({\mathcal {S}}\) then also https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq45_HTML.gif belongs to \({\mathcal {S}}\); and symmetrically, if
    https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ30_HTML.png
    belong to \({\mathcal {S}}\) then also https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq48_HTML.gif belongs to \({\mathcal {S}}\).
A class \({{\mathcal {S}}}\) of spans in a monoidal category is said to be monoidal if it satisfies the following two conditions in ([3], Definition 2.5).
(UNITAL)
For any morphisms f and g whose domain is the monoidal unit I, https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq51_HTML.gif .
 
(MULTIPLICATIVE)
If both https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq52_HTML.gif and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq53_HTML.gif then also https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq54_HTML.gif .
 
Assumption 2.1
Let \({\mathcal {S}}\) be a monoidal admissible class of spans—in the sense of ([3], Definitions 2.1 and 2.5)—in some monoidal category \({\mathsf {C}}\). For any simplicial object S in the category of monoids in \({\mathsf {C}}\) let us use the notation of (1) and consider the following successive assumptions.
(1)
Assume that for any positive integer n there exists the \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative pullback—in the sense of ([3], Definition 3.1)—\(S_n^{(1)}\) in
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ31_HTML.png
Since \(\partial _k\) is compatible with the units of the monoids \(S_n\) and \(S_{n-1}\); and by the simplicial relation \(\partial _n\,\cdot \,\partial _k=\partial _k\,\cdot \,\partial _{n+1}\) for any \(0\le k \le n\), we may apply ([3], Proposition 3.5 (1)) to conclude on the existence of the unique morphism https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq65_HTML.gif rendering commutative the above diagram.
 
(2)
In addition to the assumption in item (1) above, assume that for all \(n\ge 2\) there exists the \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative pullback \(S_{n}^{(2)}\) in
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ32_HTML.png
Since \(\partial _k^{(1)}\) is compatible with the units of the monoids \(S_n^{(1)}\) and \(S_{n-1}^{(1)}\), and by the simplicial relation \(\partial _{n-1}\,\cdot \,\partial _k=\partial _k\,\cdot \,\partial _n\) for any \(0\le k \le n-1\), we may apply ([3], Proposition 3.5 (1)) to conclude on the existence of the unique morphism https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq74_HTML.gif rendering commutative the above diagram.
\(\vdots \)
 
(l)
In addition to the assumptions in all items (1)\(\cdots \) (l-1) above, assume that for all \(n\ge l\) there exists the \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative pullback \(S_n^{(l)}\) in
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ33_HTML.png
Since \(\partial _k^{(l-1)}\) is compatible with the units of the monoids \(S_n^{(l-1)}\) and \(S_{n-1}^{(l-1)}\); and by the simplicial relation \(\partial _{n-(l-1)}\,\cdot \,\partial _k=\partial _k\,\cdot \,\partial _{n+1-(l-1)}\) for any \(0\le k \le n-(l-1)\), we may apply ([3], Proposition 3.5 (1)) to conclude on the existence of the unique morphism https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq85_HTML.gif rendering commutative the above diagram.
\(\vdots \)
 
Example 2.2
For this example note that in any monoidal category \({\mathsf {M}}\) the monoidal unit I carries a trivial monoid structure which is initial in the category of monoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\). Symmetrically, I carries a trivial comonoid structure which is terminal in the category of comonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\). Whenever \({\mathsf {M}}\) is braided, the trivial monoid and comonoid structures of I combine to a bimonoid which is thus the zero object in the category of bimonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\).
If moreover \({\mathsf {M}}\) has equalizers which are preserved by taking the monoidal product with any object, then the category of bimonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\) has equalizers—see ([3], Example 3.3)—and thus kernels. The kernel of any bimonoid morphism https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq94_HTML.gif is computed as the equalizer in \({\mathsf {M}}\) of
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ2_HTML.png
(2)
and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq96_HTML.gif , see [2].
So let \({\mathsf {M}}\) be a symmetric monoidal category in which equalizers exist and are preserved by taking the monoidal product with any object. Let \({\mathsf {C}}\) be the monoidal category of comonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\) and consider the monoidal admissible class \({\mathcal {S}}\) of spans in \({\mathsf {C}}\) from ([3], Example 2.3). Since \(\varepsilon \) is the counit, the diagram
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ34_HTML.png
commutes for any bimonoid morphism g proving that
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ3_HTML.png
(3)
From Example 3.3 and Proposition 3.7 in [3] we know that all \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative pullbacks exist in the category of bimonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\); hence any simplicial bimonoid in \({\mathsf {M}}\)—that is, any functor from \(\Delta ^{\mathsf {op}}\) to the category of monoids in \({\mathsf {C}}\)—satisfies the successive assumptions of Assumption 2.1 for any positive integer. Still—say, for an easier comparison with [8]—below we present a more explicit description of the objects \(S_n^{(k)}\).
For any positive integer n and any \(0< k \le n\) the desired objects \(S_n^{(k)}\) are constructed as the joint kernels of the morphisms \(\{\partial _n,\partial _{n-1},\cdots , \partial _{n-k+1}\}\) in the category of bimonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\); that is, as the joint equalizers
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ35_HTML.png
in \({\mathsf {M}}\) (where the “hat notation” of (2) is used). By construction they are bimonoids. Using the universality of the equalizer (in \({\mathsf {M}}\)) in the bottom rows, for \(k>1\) we construct bimonoid morphisms in
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ36_HTML.png
(note the serial commutativity of the right-hand diagram thanks to the simplicial identities) and show that they give rise to the \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative pullback
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ4_HTML.png
(4)
From (3) we infer https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq117_HTML.gif . The square of (4) commutes since \(j_{n-1}^{(k-1)}\) in the right vertical side of the commutative diagram
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ37_HTML.png
is a monomorphism. In order to check the universality of (4), take a bimonoid morphism https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq119_HTML.gif such that the exterior of the left-hand diagram of
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ5_HTML.png
(5)
commutes (we know that https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq120_HTML.gif by (3)). Then a filler \(\widetilde{g}\) of the left-hand diagram of (5) is constructed using the universality of the equalizer in the bottom row of the right-hand diagram of (5). The occurring morphism \(j_n^{(k-1)}\,\cdot \,g\) renders commutative the diagrams
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ38_HTML.png
for \(n-k+1<i\le n\). Thus since it is a comonoid morphism, it equalizes the parallel morphisms of the right-hand diagram of (5). The so constructed morphism \(\widetilde{g}\) renders commutative the left-hand diagram of (5) since the right column and the bottom row of the left-hand commutative diagram in
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ6_HTML.png
(6)
are equal monomorphisms. Finally \(\tilde{g}\) is the unique filler of the left-hand diagram of (5); as if also h makes the left-hand diagram of (5) commute then also the right-hand diagram of (6) commutes. Since \(j_n^{(k)}\) is a monomorphism, this proves \(h=\widetilde{g}\). In order to see that the span (4) satisfies the reflection property of ([3], Definition 3.1) on the right, take bimonoid morphisms https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq128_HTML.gif such that https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq129_HTML.gif ; equivalently, the large square on the left of the diagram
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ39_HTML.png
commutes. Since https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq130_HTML.gif is a monomorphism, this is equivalent to the commutativity of the exterior diagram. Since also https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq131_HTML.gif is a monomorphism, this is further equivalent to \(hg\,\cdot \,c\,\cdot \,\delta =hg\,\cdot \,\delta \); that is, to https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq133_HTML.gif . Reflectivity on the left follows symmetrically.
Proposition 2.3
Let \({\mathcal {S}}\) be a monoidal admissible class of spans in some monoidal category \({\mathsf {C}}\) and let S be a simplicial monoid in \({\mathsf {C}}\) which satisfies the successive conditions in Assumption 2.1 for any positive integer. For any positive integer n, the morphisms https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq137_HTML.gif (where \(S_n^{(0)}:=S_n\) and \(\partial _0^{(0)}:=\partial _0\)) render commutative the diagram
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ40_HTML.png
In particular, whenever the monoidal unit I is a zero object in the category of monoids in \({\mathsf {C}}\), there is a chain complex
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ7_HTML.png
(7)
Proof
The morphisms \(D_n\) are clearly well-defined and they render commutative
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ41_HTML.png
\(\square \)
Example 2.4
The definition of cartesian monoidal category includes the fact that the monoidal unit is a terminal object, which is therefore a zero object in the category of monoids. Thus Proposition 2.3 implies the well-known fact that any simplicial monoid in a cartesian monoidal category admits a Moore complex (7).
Example 2.5
If \({\mathsf {M}}\) is a symmetric monoidal category in which equalizers exist and are preserved by taking the monoidal product with any object, then we know from Example 2.2 that Assumption 2.1 holds for any simplicial bimonoid in \({\mathsf {M}}\) (that is, for any functor from \(\Delta ^{\mathsf {op}}\) to the category of monoids in the category of comonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\)). Since in the category of bimonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\) the monoidal unit is the zero object, we conclude by Proposition 2.3 that any simplicial bimonoid in \({\mathsf {M}}\) admits a Moore complex (7).
Definition 2.6
Let \({\mathcal {S}}\) be a monoidal admissible class of spans in some monoidal category \({\mathsf {C}}\). We say that a simplicial monoid S in \({\mathsf {C}}\) has Moore length l if the successive conditions in Assumption 2.1 hold for any positive integer and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq152_HTML.gif and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq153_HTML.gif are mutually inverse isomorphisms for all \(n>l\).
Lemma 2.7
Let \({\mathcal {S}}\) be a monoidal admissible class of spans in some monoidal category \({\mathsf {C}}\). For a simplicial monoid S in \({\mathsf {C}}\) of Moore length l, there are mutually inverse isomorphisms https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq158_HTML.gif and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq159_HTML.gif for any non-negative integer i and any \(n>i+l\).
Proof
We proceed by induction on i.
For \(i=0\) and \(n>l\) the claim holds by definition.
Assume that it holds for some fixed value of i and all \(n>l+i\).
If \(n>l+i+1\) then in the \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative pullback in the inner square of
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ8_HTML.png
(8)
the right column is an isomorphism by the induction hypothesis. We claim that so is then the left vertical of the inner square. By the monoidality of \({\mathcal {S}}\), https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq167_HTML.gif , hence by ([3], Lemma 3.4 (2)) also https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq168_HTML.gif . The exterior of (8) commutes by the commutativity of
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ42_HTML.png
where the bottom triangle commutes by the induction hypothesis. Then by the universality of the \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative pullback in (8) there is a unique morphism \(p_{S_n^{(n-i-1)}}^{-1}\) in (8). It is the right inverse of \(p_{S_n^{(n-i-1)}}\) by construction and also the left inverse since https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq172_HTML.gif are jointly monic and the following diagrams commute
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ43_HTML.png
Using that also https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq173_HTML.gif is an isomorphism by the induction hypothesis, so is the composite morphism https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq174_HTML.gif , and this completes the proof. \(\square \)
Lemma 2.8
Let \({\mathcal {S}}\) be a monoidal admissible class of spans in some monoidal category \({\mathsf {C}}\) and let S be a simplicial monoid in \({\mathsf {C}}\) for which the successive conditions of Assumption 2.1 hold for any positive integer. If there is some non-negative integer k for which https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq179_HTML.gif and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq180_HTML.gif are mutually inverse isomorphisms for all \(n \ge k\), then also https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq182_HTML.gif and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq183_HTML.gif are mutually inverse isomorphisms for all \(n > k\).
Proof
We need to show that under the standing assumptions the inner square of
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ44_HTML.png
is an \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative pullback for all \(n > k\). Commutativity of this square is immediate by the unitality of the morphism in the bottom row and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq187_HTML.gif by the unitality of \({\mathcal {S}}\). For the universality observe that since the verticals are isomorphisms by assumption, the exterior of our diagram commutes if and only if g is equal to https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq189_HTML.gif ; if and only if f is equal to https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq190_HTML.gif . Hence the (obviously unique) filler is g. The top row of the inner square is the identity morphism. Therefore the reflection property in ([3], Definition 3.1) of relative pullback trivially holds. \(\square \)
Corollary 2.9
Let \({\mathcal {S}}\) be a monoidal admissible class of spans in some monoidal category \({\mathsf {C}}\). For a simplicial monoid S in \({\mathsf {C}}\) which satisfies the successive conditions of Assumption 2.1 for any positive integer, the following assertions are equivalent.
(i)
S has Moore length l.
 
(ii)
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq195_HTML.gif and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq196_HTML.gif are mutually inverse isomorphisms for all \(n >l\).
 
Proof
Statement (i) implies (ii) by Lemma 2.7, and (ii) implies (i) by Lemma 2.8. \(\square \)

3 Invertibility of Some Canonical Morphisms

As in [([4], Theorems 1.1, 2.1 and 3.10), also in the forthcoming equivalence between relative categories and certain simplicial monoids a crucial role is played by the invertibility of some canonical morphisms discussed in this section.
Consider a monoidal admissible class of spans in an arbitrary monoidal category \({\mathsf {C}}\). Take a simplicial monoid S as in (1) in \({\mathsf {C}}\) for which the successive conditions in Assumption 2.1 hold for any positive integer. For any non-negative integer n, for \(0\le i \le n\) and for \(0\le k \le n-i\), we define a morphism https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq203_HTML.gif iteratively as follows.
  • \(\sigma _i^{(0)}:=\sigma _i\).
  • For \(0<k \le n-i\) we define \(\sigma _i^{(k)}\) as the unique filler in
    https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ45_HTML.png
    It is well-defined by the simplicial identity \(\partial _{(n+1)-(k-1)}\,\cdot \,\sigma _i=\sigma _i\,\cdot \,\partial _{n-(k-1)}\) and the unitality of \(\sigma _i^{(k-1)}\), see ([3], Proposition 3.5).
With these morphisms \(\sigma _i^{(k)}\) at hand, we introduce for any positive integer n and \(0\le k < n\) the morphisms
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ9_HTML.png
(9)
Note that they are natural in the following sense. For a simplicial monoid morphism https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq211_HTML.gif , let us define inductively the morphisms \(f_n^{(0)}:=f_n\) and for \(0<k \le n\) the unique morphism \(f_n^{(k)}\) which renders commutative
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ46_HTML.png
(This definition makes sense—see ([3], Proposition 3.5)—since \(\{f_n\}_{n\ge 0}\) is a morphism of simplicial monoids by assumption, hence so is \(\{f_n^{(k-1)}\}_{n\ge 0}\) and therefore
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ47_HTML.png
commutes.) These morphisms and \(y_{(n,k)}\) fit into the commutative diagram
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ10_HTML.png
(10)
Lemma 3.1
Consider a monoidal admissible class of spans in an arbitrary monoidal category \({\mathsf {C}}\). Take a simplicial monoid S as in (1) in \({\mathsf {C}}\) for which the successive conditions in Assumption 2.1 hold for any positive integer. If for some positive integer n and some \(0\le k < n-1\) the morphism \(y_{(n,k)}\) of (9) is invertible then also \(y_{(n-1,k)}\) is invertible.
Proof
It follows by the commutativity of both diagrams
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ11_HTML.png
(11)
for any \(0\le i < n-k-1\) together with the simplicial identity \(\partial _i\,\cdot \,\sigma _i=1\) that \(y_{(n-1,k)}\) has the inverse
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ48_HTML.png
\(\square \)
Note that in addition to the diagrams of (11), \(y_{(n,k)}\) renders commutative also
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ12_HTML.png
(12)
Proposition 3.2
Let \({\mathcal {S}}\) be a monoidal admissible class of spans in some monoidal category \({\mathsf {C}}\). For a simplicial monoid S in \({\mathsf {C}}\) of Moore length l, the following assertions hold.
(1)
The morphism \(y_{(n,k)}\) of (9) is invertible for all \(l<k<n\).
(2)
For any \(n>l\) the following are equivalent.
(i)
\(y_{(n,l)}\) of (9) is invertible.
(ii)
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq235_HTML.gif is invertible.
(iii)
The morphisms https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq236_HTML.gif are equal isomorphisms. Their inverse is equal to \(\partial _{0}^{(l)}=\partial _{1}^{(l)}=\cdots =\partial _{n-l}^{(l)}\).
Proof
(1)
In the unitality diagram
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ49_HTML.png
the vertical arrows are isomorphisms by Lemma 2.7. Then the bottom row is an isomorphism too.
 
(2)
The equivalence of (i) and (ii) follows by the commutativity of the diagram
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ50_HTML.png
whose left vertical arrow is an isomorphism by Lemma 2.7.
 
Assertion (iii) trivially implies (ii). Conversely, if \(\sigma _{n-1-l}^{(l)}\) is invertible then by the simplicial relations its inverse is \(\partial _{n-1-l}^{(l)}=\partial _{n-l}^{(l)}\) which is then invertible too. Again by the simplicial relations the inverse of \(\partial _{n-1-l}^{(l)}=\partial _{n-l}^{(l)}\) is \(\sigma _{n-1-l}^{(l)}=\sigma _{n-2-l}^{(l)}\). Iterating this reasoning we conclude that (iii) holds. \(\square \)
Example 3.3
For a simplicial category S (that is, a functor S from \(\Delta ^{\mathsf {op}}\) to the category of monoids in the category of spans over a fixed set in [4], Example 1.2]), \(S_n^{(k+1)}\) is the subcategory of those morphisms in \(S_n^{(k)}\) which are taken by the functor \(\partial _{n-k}^{(k)}\) to an identity morphism. Hence for a simplicial groupoid S, the category \(S_n^{(k)}\) is a groupoid for all \(0\le k \le n\). In this case all morphisms \(\{y_{(n,k)}\}_{0\le k<n}\) of (9) are invertible by the same argument applied to the morphism (1.3) in ([4], Example 1.2).
Example 3.4
Let \({\mathsf {M}}\) be a symmetric monoidal category in which equalizers exist and are preserved by taking the monoidal product with any object. Let \({\mathsf {C}}\) be the monoidal category of comonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\) and let \({\mathcal {S}}\) be the monoidal admissible class of spans in \({\mathsf {C}}\) from ([3], Example 2.3). Take a simplicial monoid S in \({\mathsf {C}}\) (that is, a simplicial bimonoid in \({\mathsf {M}}\)) such that for all non-negative integers n, \(S_n\) is a cocommutative Hopf monoid in \({\mathsf {M}}\). Then \(y_{(n,k)}\) of (9) is invertible for all \(0\le k <n\). This can be seen as follows.
Recall from Example 2.2 that \(S_n^{(k)}\) is now a joint kernel in the category of bimonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\), hence it is a sub bimonoid of the cocommutative bimonoid \(S_n\). Thus \(S_n^{(k)}\) is a cocommutative bimonoid. Moreover, by the cocommutativity of \(S_n\), its antipode is a comonoid morphism https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq266_HTML.gif for all \(n\ge 0\). So we can use the universality of the equalizer in \({\mathsf {C}}\) in the bottom row of
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ13_HTML.png
(13)
to define the antipode \(z_n^{(k)}\) for all \(n>0\) and \(0\le k\le n\) as the restriction of \(z_n\). The diagram of (13) is serially commutative since any bimonoid morphism between Hopf monoids is compatible with the antipodes, thus so are in particular the parallel morphisms of the rows. This makes \(S_n^{(k)}\) a cocommutative Hopf monoid for all \(0\le k \le n\). By construction the morphisms https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq275_HTML.gif and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq276_HTML.gif are morphisms of bimonoids and therefore of Hopf monoids.
Summarizing, https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq277_HTML.gif is a split epimorphism of bimonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\) for which conditions (1.a) and (1.b) of ([4], Proposition 1.5) hold; hence by ([4], Proposition 1.5) (see also [20]) the corresponding morphism \(y_{(n,k)}\) in ([4], Theorem 1.1 (1.b)) is invertible.
The above assumption about the cocommutativity of each \(S_n\) may look quite strong. Note however, that for the application of ([4], Proposition 1.5) we need the assumption that https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq281_HTML.gif belongs to the class \({\mathcal {S}}\). By ([3], Lemma 2.4)1 this is equivalent to the cocommutativity of \(S_{n-1}^{(k)}\). This should hold for all \(n>0\) and \(0\le k <n\); so in particular for \(k=0\).

4 Equivalence of Relative Categories and Simplicial Monoids of Moore Length 1

Theorem 4.1
Consider a monoidal admissible class \({\mathcal {S}}\) of spans in a monoidal category \({\mathsf {C}}\) such that there exist the \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative pullbacks of those cospans in \({\mathsf {C}}\) whose legs are in \({\mathcal {S}}\) (cf. ([3], Assumption 4.1])). The equivalent categories \(\mathsf {CatMon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) and \(\mathsf {Xmod}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) of ([4], Theorem 3.10) are equivalent also to the category \(\mathsf {Simp}^{1}\mathsf {Mon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) whose objects are simplicial monoids in \({\mathsf {C}}\) (that, is functors S from \(\Delta ^{\mathsf {op}}\) to the category of monoids in \({\mathsf {C}}\)) such that the following conditions hold.
(a)
S has Moore length 1.
(b)
Using the notation from (1), https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq298_HTML.gif and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq299_HTML.gif belong to \({\mathcal {S}}\).
(c)
The morphisms \(y_{(n,k)}\) of (9) and the morphisms
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ51_HTML.png
are invertible for all \(n> 0\) and \(0\le k < n\).
morphisms are simplicial monoid morphisms (that is, natural transformations between the functors from \(\Delta ^{\mathsf {op}}\) to the category of monoids in \({\mathsf {C}}\)).
Proof
The proof consists of the construction of mutually inverse equivalence functors between \(\mathsf {Simp}^1\mathsf {Mon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) and \(\mathsf {CatMon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\).
The functor \(\mathsf {Simp}^1\mathsf {Mon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}}) \rightarrow \mathsf {CatMon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) sends an object S in (1) to the \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative category whose underlying reflexive graph is https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq310_HTML.gif . By construction this is an object of the category \(\mathsf {ReflGraphMon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) in ([4], Theorem 2.1) for which the morphisms \(q_n\) of ([4], (3.3)) are invertible. By ([4], Proposition 3.8) it extends uniquely to an object of \(\mathsf {CatMon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) since the following diagram commutes.
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ52_HTML.png
Recall from Proposition 3.2 that https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq314_HTML.gif and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq315_HTML.gif are mutually inverse isomorphisms. Hence the regions of the above diagram sharing the dashed arrow commute because both \(q_2\,\cdot \,\partial _0^{(1)}1\) and \(y_{(2,0)}\) are multiplicative by [3], Lemma 1.5], with respect to the multiplications induced by the respective distributive laws
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ53_HTML.png
whose equality follows by the commutativity of the diagrams
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ54_HTML.png
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ55_HTML.png
A morphism https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq318_HTML.gif in \(\mathsf {Simp}^1\mathsf {Mon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) is sent to the morphism of reflexive graphs https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq320_HTML.gif ; it is an \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative functor by ([4], Proposition 3.9).
In the opposite direction \(\mathsf {CatMon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}}) \rightarrow \mathsf {Simp}^1\mathsf {Mon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\), we send an \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative category https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq324_HTML.gif to its ‘\({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative nerve’
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ56_HTML.png
where for any positive integer n we put
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ57_HTML.png
By the functoriality of https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq326_HTML.gif —cf. ([3], Proposition 3.5)—they constitute a simplicial monoid which obeys property (b) by construction and for which the morphisms \(q_n\) of part (c) are invertible. In order to see that it has Moore length 1, note first that https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq328_HTML.gif exists; see ([4], Theorem 1.1). We claim that also for any \(n>0\) there is an \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative pullback
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ58_HTML.png
determining https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq331_HTML.gif . By construction https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq332_HTML.gif hence by (POST) also https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq333_HTML.gif . If some morphisms f and g render commutative the left-hand diagram of
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ59_HTML.png
then they make commute the right-hand diagram as well by the commutativity of
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ60_HTML.png
Whenever https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq334_HTML.gif also https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq335_HTML.gif by (POST). Hence by the universality of the \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative pullback in the right-hand diagram, it has a unique filler h. But the same morphism h is a filler also for the left-hand diagram by the commutativity of both diagrams
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ61_HTML.png
The unique filler of the right-hand diagram is the unique filler for the left-hand diagram since any filler h of the left-hand diagram is clearly a filler for the right-hand diagram as well. For the reflection property let us use again that https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq337_HTML.gif is a monomorphism split by \(p_1\). Then if https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq339_HTML.gif then by (POST) also https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq340_HTML.gif . So, whenever also https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq341_HTML.gif , it follows from the reflection property of the relative pullback span https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq342_HTML.gif (in the sense of ([3], Definition 3.1)) that https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq343_HTML.gif . The reflection property on the left is proven symmetrically.
With this we proved that https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq344_HTML.gif exists for any \(n>0\) and it is isomorphic to https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq346_HTML.gif . The morphism \(\partial _{n-1}^{(1)}\) is the identity morphism, being defined as the unique morphism fitting the left-hand commutative diagram of
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ62_HTML.png
Since https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq348_HTML.gif by the unitality of \({\mathcal {S}}\), the right-hand diagram is obviously an \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative pullback. This proves that for any \(n>1\)
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ63_HTML.png
exists and it is isomorphic to I. Then by Corollary 2.9S has Moore length 1. Above we proved that https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq352_HTML.gif is invertible; then so is its inverse \(\sigma _{n-2}^{(1)}\). Therefore by Proposition 3.2 the morphism \(y_{(n,k)}\) of (9) is invertible for all \(0<k<n\). For any \(n>0\) the morphism \(y_{(n,0)}\) takes now the form
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ64_HTML.png
in which we recognize the invertible morphism \(q_n\). This proves that the nerve of an object of \(\mathsf {CatMon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) is indeed an object of \(\mathsf {Simp}^1\mathsf {Mon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\). A morphism
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ65_HTML.png
is sent to the family https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq361_HTML.gif which is clearly a morphism of simplicial monoids.
It remains to see that the above constructed functors are mutually inverse equivalences. Sending an \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative category (and \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative functor, respectively) to its nerve and then truncating it as above, we clearly re-obtain the \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative category (and \({\mathcal {S}}\)-relative functor, respectively) that we started with. Composing the functors in the opposite order, an object S of \(\mathsf {Simp}^1\mathsf {Mon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) is sent to
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ14_HTML.png
(14)
where https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq367_HTML.gif (see ([4], Proposition 3.8)) and for any positive integer n,
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ66_HTML.png
Note that together with the family of morphisms \(\{q_n\}_{n> 0}\) they render commutative the following diagrams. For all \(0\le i <n\),
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ15_HTML.png
(15)
For \(1< i <n\),
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ16_HTML.png
(16)
and for \(0\le i \le 1<n\) the analogous one
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ17_HTML.png
(17)
We claim that a natural isomorphism from S to its image in (14) can be constructed iteratively for all \(n\ge 0\) as
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ18_HTML.png
(18)
Note that it gives \(w_1=1\), but non-trivial higher components. Let us prove by induction on n the equality
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ19_HTML.png
(19)
For \(n=1\) both sides yield the identity morphism thus the equality holds. If it holds for some \(n>0\) then the following diagram commutes
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ67_HTML.png
proving (19) for all positive n. (The region marked by (IH) commutes by the induction hypothesis.)
The morphisms \(w_n\) of (18) are composites of isomorphisms (see Proposition 3.2) hence they are invertible. They are compatible with the units of the domain and codomain monoids by the unitality of the constituent monoid morphisms. Multiplicativity is checked by induction on n again. Trivially, \(w_0=1\) is multiplicative. If \(w_{n-1}\) is multiplicative for some \(n>0\) then by ([3], Corollary 1.7) so are both isomorphisms
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ20_HTML.png
(20)
with respect to the multiplications induced by the respective distributive laws
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ68_HTML.png
Their equality follows by the commutativity of the diagrams of Fig. 1, whose right vertical arrows are jointly monomorphic.
Since \(w_n\) is the composite of the right-hand morphism of (20) with the inverse of the left-hand one, we conclude that it is multiplicative too.
Next we check by induction on n that \(\{w_n \}_{n\ge 0}\) is a simplicial morphism; that is,
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ21_HTML.png
(21)
commute for all \(n\ge 0\) and \(0\le i \le n\) and \(0\le j \le n+1\). Note that the induction must be started with \(n=1\) because the left-hand diagram of (24) below only makes sense for \(n>0\). For \(n=0\) the diagrams of (21) commute because \(w_0\) and \(w_1\) are the identity morphisms and the equalities https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq391_HTML.gif and https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq392_HTML.gif hold for \(i=0,1\) by construction. For \(n=1\) commutativity of the diagrams of (21) is checked as follows.
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ69_HTML.png
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ70_HTML.png
Now assume that the left-hand diagram of (21) commutes for some \(n>0\) and all \(0\le i \le n\). By the commutativity of the diagrams
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ71_HTML.png
(where the region marked by (IH) commutes by the induction hypothesis) we conclude that the left-hand diagram of (21) commutes for all \(n>0\) and all \(0\le i \le n\).
Assume next that the right-hand diagram of (21) commutes for some \(n>0\) and all \(0\le j \le n+1\). Then the following diagrams commute for all \(0\le j \le n\).
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ22_HTML.png
(22)
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ23_HTML.png
(23)
The missing case \(j=n+1\) follows by the commutativity of the following diagrams whose vertical arrows are jointly monomorphic.
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ24_HTML.png
(24)
This proves that the right-hand diagram of (21) commutes for all stated values of n and j and thus w is a simplicial morphism.
Finally, naturality of w is proven by induction on n. For any simplicial monoid morphism https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq403_HTML.gif and \(n=1\) the left-hand diagram of
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ72_HTML.png
evidently commutes. If the left-hand diagram commutes for some non-negative integer n then so does the right-hand one too. \(\square \)
The functor \(\mathsf {Simp}^1\mathsf {Mon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}}) \rightarrow \mathsf {CatMon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) in the above proof can be composed with the functor \(\mathsf {CatMon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}}) \rightarrow \mathsf {Xmod}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) in the proof of ([4], Theorem 3.10). The resulting equivalence functor sends an object S to
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ73_HTML.png
where \(D_0\) is the same morphism in Proposition 2.3.
Example 4.2
As in [4], Example 1.2, take the (evidently admissible and monoidal) class of all spans in the category \({\mathsf {C}}\) of spans over a given set X. The equivalent categories of [4], Example 3.11 are equivalent also to the following category.
\(\mathsf {Simp}^{1}\mathsf {Mon}({\mathsf {C}})\) whose
objects are simplicial categories S such that the object set of \(S_n\) for each \(n\ge 0\) is the given set X and the following conditions hold.
(a)
The Moore complex of S has length 1.
 
(c)
The morphisms \(q_n\) and \(y_{(n,k)}\) of Theorem 4.1 are invertible for all \(0\le k<n\) (equivalently, \(q_1\), \(y_{(n,0)}\) and \(y_{(n,1)}\) are invertible for all \(0<n\)).
 
(There is no condition (b) because we are working with the class of all spans.) morphisms are the simplicial functors.
This category contains as a full subcategory the category of simplicial groupoids of Moore length 1; which is therefore equivalent to the category of internal categories in the category of groupoids; and also to the category of crossed modules of groupoids, see [4], Example 3.11].
Example 4.3
Let \({\mathsf {M}}\) be a symmetric monoidal category in which equalizers exist and are preserved by taking the monoidal product with any object. Take \({\mathsf {C}}\) to be the category of comonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\) with the monoidal admissible class \({\mathcal {S}}\) in ([3], Example 2.3) of spans in \({\mathsf {C}}\). The equivalent categories of ([4], Example 3.12) are also equivalent to the category
\(\mathsf {Simp}^{1}\mathsf {Mon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) whose
objects are simplicial bimonoids S in \({\mathsf {M}}\) such that
(a)
For all \(n>0\) and for https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq428_HTML.gif for \(0<i\le n\),
https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ25_HTML.png
(25)
is a joint equalizer in \({\mathsf {M}}\) (that is; the Moore complex of S has length 1, see Examples 2.2 and 2.5).
 
(b)
\(\partial _0 1\,\cdot \,\delta =\partial _0 1\,\cdot \,c\,\cdot \,\delta \) and \(\partial _1 1\,\cdot \,\delta =\partial _1 1\,\cdot \,c\,\cdot \,\delta \).
 
(c)
The morphisms \(q_n\) and \(y_{(n,k)}\) of Theorem 4.1 are invertible for \(0\le k<n\) (equivalently, \(q_1\), \(y_{(n,0)}\) and \(y_{(n,1)}\) are invertible for all \(0<n\)).
 
morphisms are the simplicial bimonoid morphisms.
As a simple consequence we obtain the following result in [8].
Proposition 4.4
Let \({\mathsf {M}}\) be a symmetric monoidal category in which equalizers exist and are preserved by taking the monoidal product with any object. Take \({\mathsf {C}}\) to be the category of comonoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\) with the monoidal admissible class \({\mathcal {S}}\) in ([3], Example 2.3) of spans in \({\mathsf {C}}\). The equivalent categories in ([4], Example 3.12) and in Example 4.3 have equivalent full subcategories as follows.
  • The full subcategory of \(\mathsf {CatMon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) for whose objects https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq446_HTML.gif both A and B are cocommutative Hopf monoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\).
  • The full subcategory of \(\mathsf {Xmod}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) for whose objects https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq449_HTML.gif both Y and B are cocommutative Hopf monoids in \({\mathsf {M}}\).
  • The full subcategory of \(\mathsf {ReflGraphMon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) for whose objects https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_IEq452_HTML.gif the following conditions hold.
    • A and B are cocommutative Hopf monoids (with antipodes z)
    • for the morphisms
      https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ74_HTML.png
      the following diagram commutes.
      https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10485-020-09603-z/MediaObjects/10485_2020_9603_Equ26_HTML.png
      (26)
  • The full subcategory of \(\mathsf {Simp}^1\mathsf {Mon}_{{\mathcal {S}}}({\mathsf {C}})\) for whose objects S the following conditions hold.
    • \(S_n\) is a cocommutative Hopf monoid in \({\mathsf {M}}\) for all \(n\ge 0\).
    • The Moore complex of S has length 1; that is, (25) is a joint equalizer in \({\mathsf {M}}\) for all \(n>1\).
Proof
We need to show that the category listed last is a subcategory of the category in Example 4.3. Condition (b) of Example 4.3 becomes trivial thanks to the cocommutativity assumption. Concerning condition (c), the morphisms \(q_n\) are invertible by ([4], Proposition 3.13) and the morphisms \(y_{(n,k)}\) are invertible by Example 3.4. \(\square \)

Acknowledgements

Open access funding provided by ELKH Wigner Research Centre for Physics. Open access funding provided by ELKH Wigner Research Centre for Physics. The author’s interest in the subject was triggered by the excellent workshop ‘Modelling Topological Phases of Matter—TQFT, HQFT, premodular and higher categories, Yetter-Drinfeld and crossed modules in disguise’ in Leeds UK, 5–8 July 2016. It is a pleasure to thank the organizers, Zoltán Kádár, João Faria Martins, Marcos Calçada and Paul Martin for the experience and a generous invitation. Financial support by the Hungarian National Research, Development and Innovation Office—NKFIH (grant K124138) is gratefully acknowledged.
Open AccessThis article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Footnotes
1
Apologies about a regrettable typo in the first line of ([3], Lemma 2.4), interchanging the symbols A and B.
 
Literature
1.
go back to reference Aguiar, Marcelo: Internal Categories and Quantum Groups. Ph.D. thesis, Cornell University 1997 Aguiar, Marcelo: Internal Categories and Quantum Groups. Ph.D. thesis, Cornell University 1997
2.
go back to reference Andruskiewitsch, Nicolás, Devoto, Jorge Andrés: Extensions of Hopf algebras, Algebra i Analiz 7 no. 1, 22–61. English version: St. Petersburg Mathematical Journal 7 no. 1, 17–52 (1995) Andruskiewitsch, Nicolás, Devoto, Jorge Andrés: Extensions of Hopf algebras, Algebra i Analiz 7 no. 1, 22–61. English version: St. Petersburg Mathematical Journal 7 no. 1, 17–52 (1995)
3.
4.
go back to reference Böhm, Gabriella: Crossed modules of monoids II. Relative crossed modules. Appl. Categ. Struct. 28(4), 601–653 (2020)CrossRef Böhm, Gabriella: Crossed modules of monoids II. Relative crossed modules. Appl. Categ. Struct. 28(4), 601–653 (2020)CrossRef
5.
go back to reference Brown, Ronald, İçen, İhan: Homotopies and automorphisms of crossed modules of groupoids. Appl. Categ. Struct. 11(2), 185–206 (2003) Brown, Ronald, İçen, İhan: Homotopies and automorphisms of crossed modules of groupoids. Appl. Categ. Struct. 11(2), 185–206 (2003)
6.
go back to reference Brown, Ronald, Spencer, Christopher B.: G-groupoids, crossed modules and the fundamental groupoid of a topological group. Indagationes Math. Proc. 79(4), 296–302 (1976)MathSciNetCrossRef Brown, Ronald, Spencer, Christopher B.: G-groupoids, crossed modules and the fundamental groupoid of a topological group. Indagationes Math. Proc. 79(4), 296–302 (1976)MathSciNetCrossRef
7.
go back to reference Duskin, John Williford: Preliminary Remarks on Groups, as quoted in [6]: Unpublished notes, Tulane University, (1969) Duskin, John Williford: Preliminary Remarks on Groups, as quoted in [6]: Unpublished notes, Tulane University, (1969)
9.
go back to reference Everaert, Tomas: Van der Linden, Tim: Baer invariants in semi-abelian categories II: Homology. Theory Appl. Categories 12(4), 195–224 (2004)MathSciNetMATH Everaert, Tomas: Van der Linden, Tim: Baer invariants in semi-abelian categories II: Homology. Theory Appl. Categories 12(4), 195–224 (2004)MathSciNetMATH
10.
go back to reference Faria Martins, João: Crossed modules of Hopf algebras and of associative algebras and two-dimensional holonomy. J. Geom. Phys. 99, 68–110 (2016) Faria Martins, João: Crossed modules of Hopf algebras and of associative algebras and two-dimensional holonomy. J. Geom. Phys. 99, 68–110 (2016)
11.
go back to reference Fernández Vilaboa, José Manuel, López López, María Purification, Villanueva Novoa, Emilio: Cat1 -Hopf algebras and crossed modules Commun. Algebra 35(1), 181–191 (2006) Fernández Vilaboa, José Manuel, López López, María Purification, Villanueva Novoa, Emilio: Cat1 -Hopf algebras and crossed modules Commun. Algebra 35(1), 181–191 (2006)
12.
go back to reference Gran, Marino: Sterck, Florence, Vercruysse, Joost: A semi-abelian extension of a theorem by Takeuchi. J. Pure Appl. Algebra 223, 4171–4190 (2019)MathSciNetCrossRef Gran, Marino: Sterck, Florence, Vercruysse, Joost: A semi-abelian extension of a theorem by Takeuchi. J. Pure Appl. Algebra 223, 4171–4190 (2019)MathSciNetCrossRef
14.
go back to reference Janelidze, George, Márki, László, Tholen, Walter: Semi-abelian categories. J. Pure Appl. Algebra 168(2–3), 367–386 (2002)MathSciNetCrossRef Janelidze, George, Márki, László, Tholen, Walter: Semi-abelian categories. J. Pure Appl. Algebra 168(2–3), 367–386 (2002)MathSciNetCrossRef
16.
go back to reference Patchkoria, Alex: Crossed semimodules and Schreier internal categories in the category of monoids. Georgian Math. J. 5(6), 575–581 (1998)MathSciNetCrossRef Patchkoria, Alex: Crossed semimodules and Schreier internal categories in the category of monoids. Georgian Math. J. 5(6), 575–581 (1998)MathSciNetCrossRef
17.
go back to reference Paoli, Simona: Internal categorical structures in homotopical algebra. In: Baez, J.C., May, J.P. (eds.) Towards Higher Categories IMA volumes inMathematics and its applications, pp. 85–103. Springer, Berlin (2009) Paoli, Simona: Internal categorical structures in homotopical algebra. In: Baez, J.C., May, J.P. (eds.) Towards Higher Categories IMA volumes inMathematics and its applications, pp. 85–103. Springer, Berlin (2009)
19.
go back to reference Porter, Timothy: The Crossed Menagerie: an introduction to crossed gadgetry and cohomology in algebra and topology, Notes initially prepared for the XVI Encuentro Rioplatense de Álgebra y Geometría Algebraica, in Buenos Aires, 12–15 December 2006, extended for an MSc course (Summer 2007) at Ottawa. available at https://ncatlab.org/timporter/show/crossed+menagerie Porter, Timothy: The Crossed Menagerie: an introduction to crossed gadgetry and cohomology in algebra and topology, Notes initially prepared for the XVI Encuentro Rioplatense de Álgebra y Geometría Algebraica, in Buenos Aires, 12–15 December 2006, extended for an MSc course (Summer 2007) at Ottawa. available at https://​ncatlab.​org/​timporter/​show/​crossed+menageri​e
20.
go back to reference Radford, David E: The structure of Hopf algebras with a projection. J. Algebra 92(2), 322–347 (1985) Radford, David E: The structure of Hopf algebras with a projection. J. Algebra 92(2), 322–347 (1985)
21.
go back to reference Van der Linden, Tim: Homology and Homotopy in Semi-Abelian Categories. Ph.D. Thesis, Vrije Universiteit Brussel, (2006) Van der Linden, Tim: Homology and Homotopy in Semi-Abelian Categories. Ph.D. Thesis, Vrije Universiteit Brussel, (2006)
22.
go back to reference Whitehead, John Henry Constantine: Combinatorial homotopy II. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 55, 453–496 (1949) Whitehead, John Henry Constantine: Combinatorial homotopy II. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 55, 453–496 (1949)
Metadata
Title
Crossed Modules of Monoids III. Simplicial Monoids of Moore Length 1
Author
Gabriella Böhm
Publication date
20-08-2020
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Applied Categorical Structures / Issue 1/2021
Print ISSN: 0927-2852
Electronic ISSN: 1572-9095
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10485-020-09603-z

Other articles of this Issue 1/2021

Applied Categorical Structures 1/2021 Go to the issue

Premium Partner