Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Theory and Decision 4/2017

17-11-2016

Estimating cumulative prospect theory parameters from an international survey

Authors: Marc Oliver Rieger, Mei Wang, Thorsten Hens

Published in: Theory and Decision | Issue 4/2017

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

We conduct a standardized survey on risk preferences in 53 countries worldwide and estimate cumulative prospect theory parameters from the data. The parameter estimates show that significant differences on the cross-country level are to some extent robust and related to economic and cultural differences. In particular, a closer look on probability weighting underlines gender differences, economic effects, and cultural impact on probability weighting. The data set is a useful starting point for future research that investigates the impact of risk preferences on the market level.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Appendix
Available only for authorised users
Footnotes
1
These survey results have also been used to shed light on the selection between culture and general risk attitudes in gains and losses (Rieger et al. 2015) and on loss aversion (Wang et al. 2016). An earlier version of the data has also been used to study the prediction quality of various CPT variants (Rieger and Bui 2011).
 
2
For more detailed description of the survey, we refer to Rieger et al. (2015).
 
3
We tried different specifications of \(w_\pm \) and v and also alternative PT models, but we do not focus on this in the current article, see Rieger and Bui (2011) for details.
 
4
To guarantee a monotone probability weighting function, the value of \(\gamma \) has to be larger than 0.279, see Rieger and Wang (2006), Ingersoll (2008) and Giorgi and Legg (2012).
 
5
There is vast empirical evidence for this behavior in gains and at least for small losses Bosch-Doménech and Silvestre (2006).
 
6
The lowest measured value was 0.30 which is still in the parameter range where the probability weighting function is monotone (Ingersoll 2008; Giorgi and Legg 2012).
 
7
The first and fourth lotteries (the lotteries with two positive outcomes and large stakes, respectively) were omitted, since it has been found that such lotteries are difficult to estimate in the standard form of CPT (Rieger and Bui 2011). Moreover, we found that the first lottery question suffered from a relatively large amount of answers that violated first-order stochastic dominance (20%), pointing to mistakes when filling in the questionnaire. In contrast to that, answers to the other lotteries violated first-order stochastic dominance on average only in less than 2% of the cases.
 
8
In the last subsection, we have noticed the lack of robustness for these two countries, Portugal and Romania.
 
9
A model-independent definition of loss aversion has already been suggested by Schmidt and Zank (2005) and an in-depth analysis of loss aversion in CPT has been given by Zank (2010).
 
10
In this study, the subjects were asked two questions related to risk attitudes. The first one was “Suppose you are the only income earner in the family, and you have a good job guaranteed to give you and your current family income every year for life. Now, you are given an opportunity to take a new and equally good job. The new job has a 50/50 chance to increase by 50% your standard of living each year during your lifetime. However, the new job also has a 50/50 chance to reduce by X percent your standard of living each year during your lifetime. Circle the maximum X percent reduction in standard of living that you are willing to accept.” The second question was similarly stated, but it was in terms of a portfolio decision rather than an income decision.
 
11
We notice that \(\alpha \) and \(\beta \) are positively correlated (\(r=0.64\), \(p<0.01\)), implying that stronger risk aversion in gains is correlated with stronger risk seeking in losses. This can probably be explained by between-person differences in sensitivity to the relative wealth change: when a person is more sensitive to wealth changes with respect to a reference point, then his value function tends to be more concave in gains and more convex in losses, thus leading to lower \(\alpha \) and \(\beta \) values.
 
12
This “linear” loss aversion \(\theta \) has been introduced by Tversky and Kahneman (1992) and has been shown for the INTRA data to depend on cultural differences between countries (Wang et al. 2016).
 
13
We used the classical four dimensions: PDI (power distance index), IDV (individualism), MAS (masculinity), and UAI (uncertainty avoidance index), but omitted the newer and less common dimensions.
 
14
Without normalization, the size of the standard deviation depends on the size of the lottery values.
 
15
We excluded the five countries with non-robust CPT measurements as defined in Table 5 from this analysis.
 
16
Age effects cannot be studied from our data, since our sample was inherently biased towards a young age group.
 
Literature
go back to reference Bosch-Doménech, A., & Silvestre, J. (2006). Reflections on gains and losses: A 2\(\times \)2\(\times \)7 experiment. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 33(3), 217–235.CrossRef Bosch-Doménech, A., & Silvestre, J. (2006). Reflections on gains and losses: A 2\(\times \)2\(\times \)7 experiment. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 33(3), 217–235.CrossRef
go back to reference Breuer, W., Rieger, M. O., & Soypak, C. (2014). The behavioral foundations of corporate dividend policy - a cross-country empirical analysis. Journal of Banking and Finance, 42, 247–265.CrossRef Breuer, W., Rieger, M. O., & Soypak, C. (2014). The behavioral foundations of corporate dividend policy - a cross-country empirical analysis. Journal of Banking and Finance, 42, 247–265.CrossRef
go back to reference De Giorgi, E. G., & Legg, S. (2012). Dynamic portfolio choice and asset pricing with narrow framing and probability weighting. Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 36(7), 951–972.CrossRef De Giorgi, E. G., & Legg, S. (2012). Dynamic portfolio choice and asset pricing with narrow framing and probability weighting. Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 36(7), 951–972.CrossRef
go back to reference Fan, J. X., & Xiao, J. J. (2006). Cross-cultural differences in risk tolerance: A comparison between Chinese and Americans. Journal of Personal Finance, 5(54–75) Fan, J. X., & Xiao, J. J. (2006). Cross-cultural differences in risk tolerance: A comparison between Chinese and Americans. Journal of Personal Finance, 5(54–75)
go back to reference Fehr-Duda, H., De Gennaro, M., & Schubert, R. (2006). Gender, financial risk, and probability weights. Theory and Decision, 60, 283–313.CrossRef Fehr-Duda, H., De Gennaro, M., & Schubert, R. (2006). Gender, financial risk, and probability weights. Theory and Decision, 60, 283–313.CrossRef
go back to reference Gneezy, U., List, J. A., & Wu, G. (2006). The uncertainty effect: When a risky prospect is valued less than its worst possible outcome. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 121, 1283–1309.CrossRef Gneezy, U., List, J. A., & Wu, G. (2006). The uncertainty effect: When a risky prospect is valued less than its worst possible outcome. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 121, 1283–1309.CrossRef
go back to reference Harrison, G. W., Humphrey, S. J., & Verschoor, A. (2010). Choice under uncertainty: Evidence from Ethiopia, India and Uganda. Economic Journal, 120(543), 80–104. Harrison, G. W., Humphrey, S. J., & Verschoor, A. (2010). Choice under uncertainty: Evidence from Ethiopia, India and Uganda. Economic Journal, 120(543), 80–104.
go back to reference Harrison, G. W., & Rutström, E. E. (2009). Expected utility theory and prospect theory: one wedding and a decent funeral. Experimental Economics, 12(2), 133–158.CrossRef Harrison, G. W., & Rutström, E. E. (2009). Expected utility theory and prospect theory: one wedding and a decent funeral. Experimental Economics, 12(2), 133–158.CrossRef
go back to reference Hofstede, G. (2001). Culture’s Consequences, Comparing Values, Behaviors, Institutions, and Organizations Across Nations. Thousand Oaks CA: Sage Publications. Hofstede, G. (2001). Culture’s Consequences, Comparing Values, Behaviors, Institutions, and Organizations Across Nations. Thousand Oaks CA: Sage Publications.
go back to reference Hsee, C. K. H. K., & Weber, E. U. (1999). Cross-national differences in risk preference and lay predictions. Journal of Behavioral Deicision Making, 12, 165–179.CrossRef Hsee, C. K. H. K., & Weber, E. U. (1999). Cross-national differences in risk preference and lay predictions. Journal of Behavioral Deicision Making, 12, 165–179.CrossRef
go back to reference Ingersoll, J. (2008). Non-monotonicity of the tversky-kahneman probability-weighting function: A cautionary note. European Financial Management, 14(3), 385–390.CrossRef Ingersoll, J. (2008). Non-monotonicity of the tversky-kahneman probability-weighting function: A cautionary note. European Financial Management, 14(3), 385–390.CrossRef
go back to reference Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect Theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.CrossRef Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect Theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.CrossRef
go back to reference Rabin, M. (2000). Risk aversion and expected-utility theory: A calibration theorem. Econometrica, 68(5), 1281–1292.CrossRef Rabin, M. (2000). Risk aversion and expected-utility theory: A calibration theorem. Econometrica, 68(5), 1281–1292.CrossRef
go back to reference Rieger, M. O. (2014). Evolutionary stability of prospect theory preferences. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 50, 1–11.CrossRef Rieger, M. O. (2014). Evolutionary stability of prospect theory preferences. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 50, 1–11.CrossRef
go back to reference Rieger, M. O., & Bui, T. (2011). Too risk-averse for prospect theory? Modern Economy, 2(4), 691–700.CrossRef Rieger, M. O., & Bui, T. (2011). Too risk-averse for prospect theory? Modern Economy, 2(4), 691–700.CrossRef
go back to reference Rieger, M. O., & Wang, M. (2006). Cumulative prospect theory and the St. Petersburg paradox. Economic Theory, 28(3), 665–679.CrossRef Rieger, M. O., & Wang, M. (2006). Cumulative prospect theory and the St. Petersburg paradox. Economic Theory, 28(3), 665–679.CrossRef
go back to reference Rieger, M. O., Wang, M., & Hens, T. (2013). International evidence on the equity premium puzzle and time discounting. Multinational Finance Journal, 17(3/4), 1–15.CrossRef Rieger, M. O., Wang, M., & Hens, T. (2013). International evidence on the equity premium puzzle and time discounting. Multinational Finance Journal, 17(3/4), 1–15.CrossRef
go back to reference Rieger, M. O., Wang, M., & Hens, T. (2015). Risk preferences around the world. Management Science, 61(3), 637–648.CrossRef Rieger, M. O., Wang, M., & Hens, T. (2015). Risk preferences around the world. Management Science, 61(3), 637–648.CrossRef
go back to reference Schmidt, U., & Zank, H. (2005). What is loss aversion? Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 30(2), 157–167.CrossRef Schmidt, U., & Zank, H. (2005). What is loss aversion? Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 30(2), 157–167.CrossRef
go back to reference Starmer, C. (2000). Developments in non-expected utility theory: The hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk. Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 332–382.CrossRef Starmer, C. (2000). Developments in non-expected utility theory: The hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk. Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 332–382.CrossRef
go back to reference Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.CrossRef Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.CrossRef
go back to reference Vieider, F. M., Chmura, T., Fisher, T., Kusakawa, T., Martinsson, P., Sunday, A., et al. (2015). Within versus between country differences in risk attitudes: Implications for cultural comparisons. Theory and Decision, 78(2), 209–218.CrossRef Vieider, F. M., Chmura, T., Fisher, T., Kusakawa, T., Martinsson, P., Sunday, A., et al. (2015). Within versus between country differences in risk attitudes: Implications for cultural comparisons. Theory and Decision, 78(2), 209–218.CrossRef
go back to reference Vieider, F. M., Lefebvre, M., Bouchouicha, R., Chmura, T., Hakimov, R., Krawczyk, M., et al. (2015). Common components of risk and uncertainty attitudes across contexts and domains: Evidence from 30 countries. Journal of European Economic Association, 13(3), 421–452.CrossRef Vieider, F. M., Lefebvre, M., Bouchouicha, R., Chmura, T., Hakimov, R., Krawczyk, M., et al. (2015). Common components of risk and uncertainty attitudes across contexts and domains: Evidence from 30 countries. Journal of European Economic Association, 13(3), 421–452.CrossRef
go back to reference von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1944). Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1944). Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
go back to reference Wakker, P. P. (2010). Prospect Theory: For Risk and Ambiguity. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Wakker, P. P. (2010). Prospect Theory: For Risk and Ambiguity. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Wang, M., & Fischbeck, P. (2004a). Similar in how to frame, but different in what to choose. Marketing Bulletin, 15, 17–28. Wang, M., & Fischbeck, P. (2004a). Similar in how to frame, but different in what to choose. Marketing Bulletin, 15, 17–28.
go back to reference Wang, M., & Fischbeck, P. S. (2004b). Incorporating framing into prospect theory modeling: A mixture-model approach. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 29(2), 181–197.CrossRef Wang, M., & Fischbeck, P. S. (2004b). Incorporating framing into prospect theory modeling: A mixture-model approach. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 29(2), 181–197.CrossRef
go back to reference Wang, M., Rieger, M. O. Hens, T. (2016), ‘The impact of culture on loss aversion’, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making in press. Wang, M., Rieger, M. O. Hens, T. (2016), ‘The impact of culture on loss aversion’, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making in press.
go back to reference Weber, E. U., & Hsee, C. (1998). Cross-cultural differences in risk perception, but cross-cultural similiarities in attitudes towards perceived risk. Management Science, 44(9), 1205–1217.CrossRef Weber, E. U., & Hsee, C. (1998). Cross-cultural differences in risk perception, but cross-cultural similiarities in attitudes towards perceived risk. Management Science, 44(9), 1205–1217.CrossRef
go back to reference Zank, H. (2010). On probabilities and loss aversion. Theory and Decision, 68(3), 243–261.CrossRef Zank, H. (2010). On probabilities and loss aversion. Theory and Decision, 68(3), 243–261.CrossRef
Metadata
Title
Estimating cumulative prospect theory parameters from an international survey
Authors
Marc Oliver Rieger
Mei Wang
Thorsten Hens
Publication date
17-11-2016
Publisher
Springer US
Published in
Theory and Decision / Issue 4/2017
Print ISSN: 0040-5833
Electronic ISSN: 1573-7187
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-016-9582-8

Other articles of this Issue 4/2017

Theory and Decision 4/2017 Go to the issue

Premium Partner