Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Theory and Decision 1/2019

05-03-2019

Individual vs. group decision-making: an experiment on dynamic choice under risk and ambiguity

Authors: Enrica Carbone, Konstantinos Georgalos, Gerardo Infante

Published in: Theory and Decision | Issue 1/2019

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

This paper focuses on the comparison of individual and group decision-making, in a stochastic inter-temporal problem in two decision environments, namely risk and ambiguity. Using a consumption/saving laboratory experiment, we investigate behaviour in four treatments: (1) individual choice under risk; (2) group choice under risk; (3) individual choice under ambiguity and (4) group choice under ambiguity. Comparing decisions within and between decision environments, we find an anti-symmetric pattern. While individuals are choosing on average closer to the theoretical optimal predictions, compared to groups in the risk treatments, groups tend to deviate less under ambiguity. Within decision environments, individuals deviate more when they choose under ambiguity, while groups are better planners under ambiguity rather than under risk. Our results extend the often observed pattern of individuals (groups) behaving more optimally under risk (ambiguity), to its dynamic dimension.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Appendix
Available only for authorised users
Footnotes
1
See Etner et al. (2012) for a review of the theoretical models and Trautmann and van de Kuilen (2015) for a review of the experimental evidence.
 
2
For an extensive review of life-cycle experiments, see Duffy (2014).
 
3
The income generation process is described shortly.
 
4
Setting the discount rate equal to zero is not expected to have an impact on our results (see Carbone and Hey 2004, footnote 1).
 
5
The Ellsberg-type urns have been introduced in the literature by Ellsberg (1961) seminal paper. In this paper, he proposed two thoughts experiment with the scope to challenge the ”sure thing principle” of the Subjective Expected Utility model (Savage 1954) and to introduce non-neutral attitudes towards ambiguity. A significant number of experimental studies are making use of either the two-colour or the three-colour urn to introduce ambiguity in the lab.
 
6
This information was only provided during the risk treatments. During the ambiguity treatments, subjects obtained no information regarding the composition of the urn and thus, they were facing ambiguity. During the session they had the chance to observe draws from the urn and obtain information regarding the actual distribution.
 
7
Caballero (1990) shows that under the assumption of a CARA utility function, a closed-form solution for the optimal consumption can be derived. Nevertheless, an additional assumption requires that the decision-maker is fully aware of the underlying income stochastic process, condition which is not satisfied in the ambiguity treatments.
 
8
We elaborate on this issue later.
 
9
We are grateful to a careful referee for drawing our attention to this literature.
 
10
The theoretical foundations of the model are presented in Appendix A.
 
11
We assume that subjects are risk and ambiguity neutral with regard to monetary payoffs. Controlling for averse or loving attitudes towards risk and ambiguity would add two additional layers of complexity to the function mapping from consumption to monetary payoffs (Carbone and Duffy 2014). If one wants to control for attitudes towards risk and ambiguity, she needs to appropriately extend the experimental design with tasks that will perplex an already complicated decision task (see for example Hey and Dardanoni 1988). As our main objective is to understand the effects of ambiguity to saving decisions, we leave this for future work.
 
12
Klibanoff et al. (2005) smooth-ambiguity model provides a flexible specification to capture both FOPs and SOPs and there is also experimental evidence in support of this model (Conte and Hey 2013; Attanasi et al. 2014). Nevertheless, one needs to assume non-neutral ambiguity attitudes and particular belief updating rules.
 
13
The optimal solution and the subsequent econometric analysis were conducted using the R programming language (R Core Team 2013). The programs and the data are available upon request.
 
14
As Ballinger et al. (2003) and Feltovich and Ejebu (2014) notice, the no-borrowing constraint along with a positive third derivative of the utility function, imply motives for precautionary saving. Both conditions are satisfied in our experimental design.
 
15
During the experiment expressions like “income”, “wealth”, “consumption” or “utility” were carefully avoided.
 
16
Again, there was no explicit reference to decreasing marginal utility but to “increments at a decreasing rate”.
 
17
The software recorded all proposals. When members did not confirm a decision within three minutes, the computer would pick the last proposal of each member and then randomly choose one of those as representative of the group. This did not happen very frequently. We recorded 54 cases of “disagreement” out of 900 decisions (6\(\%\)). Preliminary regressions suggested that disagreement was not a significant regressor.
 
18
From the sample we excluded the observations of 1 subject in sequence 1 and 2 subjects in sequence 2 in the I-R treatment, 3 subjects in sequence 1 and 1 subject in both sequences in I-A, 2 subjects in sequence 2 and 1 subject in both sequences in G-R and 1 subject in sequence 1 in G-A. We verified that including in our sample the observations of the participants who although failed the rationality test, they left in their saving accounts less than 9 units, does not change quantitatively the results that we report below.
 
19
Individuals (groups) exhibit positive deviation of 4.32 (2.62) consumption units under risk and deviation of 2.56 (3.17) units under ambiguity.
 
20
We also conducted the regressions using the mean squared deviation from the conditional optimal as dependent variable. Although the results are magnified compared to those where absolute deviation has been used as the dependent variable, the qualitative results regarding the treatment effects remain the same. We report the results of these regressions in the supplementary material.
 
21
In the case, the group consisted of one male and one female member, this dummy variable takes the value 1.
 
22
Note that, since during the experiment there were actual draws from the urn, there was no way to implement the same income streams to all treatments.
 
23
I-R vs. G-R: \(p=0.780\); I-R vs. I-A: \(p=0.550\); I-A vs. G-A: \(p=0.300\); G-R vs. G-A: \(p=0.900\). All reported p-values were generated using pairwise \(\chi ^2\) tests.
 
24
Carbone and Hey (2004).
 
25
In our experimental design, this \(\tau \) may range from 1 (extreme myopic behaviour) to 15 (optimal behaviour).
 
26
I-R vs. G-R: \(p=0.452\); I-R vs. I-A: \(p=0.269\); I-A vs. G-A: \(p=0.620\); G-R vs. G-A: \(p=0.432\). All p-values reported were generated using rank-sum MWW tests for independent samples.
 
27
I-R: \(p=0.008\); G-R: \(p=0.330\); I-A: \(p=0.178\); G-A: \(p=0.743\). All reported p values were generated using rank-sum MWW tests for independent samples for the group treatments and signed-rank MWW tests for the individual ones.
 
28
The probability of Low income P(L) is defined as the residual \(P(L)=1-P(H)\).
 
29
The material referred to in the “Appendix” is the same for all sets of instructions and can be consulted in subsection 1 (Individual Decision-Making).
 
Literature
go back to reference Ahn, D., Choi, S., Gale, D., & Kariv, S. (2014). Estimating ambiguity aversion in a portfolio choice experiment. Quantitative Economics, 5(2), 195–223.CrossRef Ahn, D., Choi, S., Gale, D., & Kariv, S. (2014). Estimating ambiguity aversion in a portfolio choice experiment. Quantitative Economics, 5(2), 195–223.CrossRef
go back to reference Attanasi, G., Gollier, C., Montesano, A., & Pace, N. (2014). Eliciting ambiguity aversion in unknown and in compound lotteries: A smooth ambiguity model experimental study. Theory and Decision, 77, 485–530.CrossRef Attanasi, G., Gollier, C., Montesano, A., & Pace, N. (2014). Eliciting ambiguity aversion in unknown and in compound lotteries: A smooth ambiguity model experimental study. Theory and Decision, 77, 485–530.CrossRef
go back to reference Baillon, A., Bleichrodt, H., Keskin, U., L’Haridon, O., & Li, C. (2018). Learning under ambiguity: An experiment using initial public offerings on a stock market. Management Science, 64(5), 2181–2198.CrossRef Baillon, A., Bleichrodt, H., Keskin, U., L’Haridon, O., & Li, C. (2018). Learning under ambiguity: An experiment using initial public offerings on a stock market. Management Science, 64(5), 2181–2198.CrossRef
go back to reference Baillon, A., Bleichrodt, H., Liu, N., & Wakker, P. (2016). Group decision rules and group rationality under risk. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 52(2), 99–116.CrossRef Baillon, A., Bleichrodt, H., Liu, N., & Wakker, P. (2016). Group decision rules and group rationality under risk. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 52(2), 99–116.CrossRef
go back to reference Baker, R., Laury, S., & Williams, A. (2008). Comparing small-group and individual behavior in lottery-choice experiments. Southern Economic Journal, 75(2), 367–382. Baker, R., Laury, S., & Williams, A. (2008). Comparing small-group and individual behavior in lottery-choice experiments. Southern Economic Journal, 75(2), 367–382.
go back to reference Ballinger, T., Hudson, E., Karkoviata, L., & Wilcox, N. (2011). Saving behavior and cognitive abilities. Experimental Economics, 14(3), 349–374.CrossRef Ballinger, T., Hudson, E., Karkoviata, L., & Wilcox, N. (2011). Saving behavior and cognitive abilities. Experimental Economics, 14(3), 349–374.CrossRef
go back to reference Ballinger, T. P., Palumbo, M. G., & Wilcox, N. T. (2003). Precautionary saving and social learning across generations: An experiment. The Economic Journal, 113(490), 920–947.CrossRef Ballinger, T. P., Palumbo, M. G., & Wilcox, N. T. (2003). Precautionary saving and social learning across generations: An experiment. The Economic Journal, 113(490), 920–947.CrossRef
go back to reference Berg, J., Daley, L., Dichaut, J., & O’Brien, J. (1986). Controlling preferences for lotteries on units of experimental exchange. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 101(2), 281–306.CrossRef Berg, J., Daley, L., Dichaut, J., & O’Brien, J. (1986). Controlling preferences for lotteries on units of experimental exchange. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 101(2), 281–306.CrossRef
go back to reference Bougheas, S., Nieboer, J., & Sefton, M. (2013). Risk-taking in social settings: Group and peer effects. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 92, 273–283.CrossRef Bougheas, S., Nieboer, J., & Sefton, M. (2013). Risk-taking in social settings: Group and peer effects. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 92, 273–283.CrossRef
go back to reference Brown, A. L., Chua, Z. E., & Camerer, C. F. (2009). Learning and visceral temptation in dynamic saving experiments. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 124(1), 197–231.CrossRef Brown, A. L., Chua, Z. E., & Camerer, C. F. (2009). Learning and visceral temptation in dynamic saving experiments. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 124(1), 197–231.CrossRef
go back to reference Brunette, M., Cabantous, L., & Couture, S. (2015). Are individuals more risk and ambiguity averse in a group environment or alone? Results from an experimental study. Theory and Decision, 78(3), 357–376.CrossRef Brunette, M., Cabantous, L., & Couture, S. (2015). Are individuals more risk and ambiguity averse in a group environment or alone? Results from an experimental study. Theory and Decision, 78(3), 357–376.CrossRef
go back to reference Caballero, R. (1990). Consumption puzzles and precautionary savings. Journal of Monetary Economics, 25, 113–136.CrossRef Caballero, R. (1990). Consumption puzzles and precautionary savings. Journal of Monetary Economics, 25, 113–136.CrossRef
go back to reference Camerer, C., & Weber, M. (1992). Recent developments in modeling preferences: Uncertainty and ambiguity. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5(4), 325–370.CrossRef Camerer, C., & Weber, M. (1992). Recent developments in modeling preferences: Uncertainty and ambiguity. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5(4), 325–370.CrossRef
go back to reference Campanale, C. (2011). Learning, ambiguity and life-cycle portfolio allocation. Review of Economic Dynamics, 14(2), 339–367.CrossRef Campanale, C. (2011). Learning, ambiguity and life-cycle portfolio allocation. Review of Economic Dynamics, 14(2), 339–367.CrossRef
go back to reference Carbone, E. (2005). Demographics and behaviour. Experimental Economics, 8, 217–232.CrossRef Carbone, E. (2005). Demographics and behaviour. Experimental Economics, 8, 217–232.CrossRef
go back to reference Carbone, E., & Duffy, J. (2014). Lifecycle consumption plans, social learning and external habits: Experimental evidence. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 106, 413–427.CrossRef Carbone, E., & Duffy, J. (2014). Lifecycle consumption plans, social learning and external habits: Experimental evidence. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 106, 413–427.CrossRef
go back to reference Carbone, E., & Hey, J. D. (2004). The effect of unemployment on consumption: An experimental analysis. The Economic Journal, 114(497), 660–683.CrossRef Carbone, E., & Hey, J. D. (2004). The effect of unemployment on consumption: An experimental analysis. The Economic Journal, 114(497), 660–683.CrossRef
go back to reference Carbone, E., & Infante, G. (2014). Comparing behavior under risk and under ambiguity in a lifecycle experiment. Theory and Decision, 57, 313–322.CrossRef Carbone, E., & Infante, G. (2014). Comparing behavior under risk and under ambiguity in a lifecycle experiment. Theory and Decision, 57, 313–322.CrossRef
go back to reference Carbone, E., & Infante, G. (2015). Are groups better planners than individuals? An experimental analysis. Journal of Behavioral and Experimental Economics, 57, 112–119.CrossRef Carbone, E., & Infante, G. (2015). Are groups better planners than individuals? An experimental analysis. Journal of Behavioral and Experimental Economics, 57, 112–119.CrossRef
go back to reference Carlsson, F., He, H., Martinsson, P., Qin, P., & Sutter, M. (2012). Household decision making in rural China: Using experiments to estimate the influences of spouses. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 84(2), 525–536.CrossRef Carlsson, F., He, H., Martinsson, P., Qin, P., & Sutter, M. (2012). Household decision making in rural China: Using experiments to estimate the influences of spouses. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 84(2), 525–536.CrossRef
go back to reference Charness, G., Karni, E., & Levin, D. (2007). Individual and group decision making under risk: An experimental study of Bayesian updating and violations of first-order stochastic dominance. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 35(2), 129–148.CrossRef Charness, G., Karni, E., & Levin, D. (2007). Individual and group decision making under risk: An experimental study of Bayesian updating and violations of first-order stochastic dominance. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 35(2), 129–148.CrossRef
go back to reference Charness, G., Karni, E., & Levin, D. (2010). On the conjunction fallacy in probability judgment: New experimental evidence regarding linda. Games and Economic Behavior, 68(2), 551–556.CrossRef Charness, G., Karni, E., & Levin, D. (2010). On the conjunction fallacy in probability judgment: New experimental evidence regarding linda. Games and Economic Behavior, 68(2), 551–556.CrossRef
go back to reference Charness, G., Karni, E., & Levin, D. (2013). Ambiguity attitudes and social interactions: An experimental investigation. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 46(1), 1–25.CrossRef Charness, G., Karni, E., & Levin, D. (2013). Ambiguity attitudes and social interactions: An experimental investigation. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 46(1), 1–25.CrossRef
go back to reference Charness, G., & Sutter, M. (2012). Groups make better self-interested decisions. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 26(3), 157–76.CrossRef Charness, G., & Sutter, M. (2012). Groups make better self-interested decisions. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 26(3), 157–76.CrossRef
go back to reference Cohen, M., Gilboa, I., & Schmeidler, D. (2000). An experimental study of updating ambiguous beliefs. Risk Decision and Policy, 5(2), 123–133.CrossRef Cohen, M., Gilboa, I., & Schmeidler, D. (2000). An experimental study of updating ambiguous beliefs. Risk Decision and Policy, 5(2), 123–133.CrossRef
go back to reference Conte, A., & Hey, J. (2013). Assessing multiple prior models of behaviour under ambiguity. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 46(2), 113–132.CrossRef Conte, A., & Hey, J. (2013). Assessing multiple prior models of behaviour under ambiguity. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 46(2), 113–132.CrossRef
go back to reference Cooper, D., & Kagel, J. (2005). Are two heads better than one? Team versus individual play in signaling games. American Economic Review, 95(3), 477–509.CrossRef Cooper, D., & Kagel, J. (2005). Are two heads better than one? Team versus individual play in signaling games. American Economic Review, 95(3), 477–509.CrossRef
go back to reference Curley, S., Yates, F., & Abrams, R. (1986). Psychological sources of ambiguity avoidance. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 38(2), 230–256.CrossRef Curley, S., Yates, F., & Abrams, R. (1986). Psychological sources of ambiguity avoidance. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 38(2), 230–256.CrossRef
go back to reference Denant-Boemont, L., Diecidue, E., & l’Haridon, O. (2016). Patience and time consistency in collective decisions. Experimental Economics (page forthcoming). Denant-Boemont, L., Diecidue, E., & l’Haridon, O. (2016). Patience and time consistency in collective decisions. Experimental Economics (page forthcoming).
go back to reference Dominiak, A., Dürsch, P., & Lefort, J. (2012). A dynamic ellsberg urn experiment. Games and Economic Behavior, 75, 625–638.CrossRef Dominiak, A., Dürsch, P., & Lefort, J. (2012). A dynamic ellsberg urn experiment. Games and Economic Behavior, 75, 625–638.CrossRef
go back to reference Duffy, J. (2014). Macroeconomics: A survey of laboratory research. Technical report, University of California. Duffy, J. (2014). Macroeconomics: A survey of laboratory research. Technical report, University of California.
go back to reference Dutt, V., Arló-Costa, H., Helzner, J., & Gonzalez, C. (2014). The description-experience gap in risky and ambiguous gambles. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 27, 316–327. Dutt, V., Arló-Costa, H., Helzner, J., & Gonzalez, C. (2014). The description-experience gap in risky and ambiguous gambles. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 27, 316–327.
go back to reference Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity and the savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75, 643–669.CrossRef Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity and the savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75, 643–669.CrossRef
go back to reference Epstein, L., Noor, J., & Sandroni, A. (2010). Non-bayesian learning. The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics, 10(1), 1–20. Epstein, L., Noor, J., & Sandroni, A. (2010). Non-bayesian learning. The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics, 10(1), 1–20.
go back to reference Epstein, L., & Schneider, M. (2007). Learning under ambiguity. Review of Economic Studies, 74(4), 1275–1303.CrossRef Epstein, L., & Schneider, M. (2007). Learning under ambiguity. Review of Economic Studies, 74(4), 1275–1303.CrossRef
go back to reference Etner, J., Jeleva, M., & Tallon, J. (2012). Decision theory under ambiguity. Journal of Economic Surveys, 26(2), 234–270.CrossRef Etner, J., Jeleva, M., & Tallon, J. (2012). Decision theory under ambiguity. Journal of Economic Surveys, 26(2), 234–270.CrossRef
go back to reference Feltovich, N., & Ejebu, O. (2014). Do positional goods inhibit saving? Evidence from a life-cycle experiment. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 107, 440–454. (Empirical Behavioral Finance).CrossRef Feltovich, N., & Ejebu, O. (2014). Do positional goods inhibit saving? Evidence from a life-cycle experiment. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 107, 440–454. (Empirical Behavioral Finance).CrossRef
go back to reference Fischbacher, U. (2007). z-Tree: Zurich toolbox for ready-made economic experiments. Experimental Economics, 10(2), 171–178.CrossRef Fischbacher, U. (2007). z-Tree: Zurich toolbox for ready-made economic experiments. Experimental Economics, 10(2), 171–178.CrossRef
go back to reference Gillet, J., Schram, A., & Sonnemans, J. (2009). The tragedy of the commons revisited: The importance of group decision-making. Journal of Public Economics, 93(5–6), 785–797.CrossRef Gillet, J., Schram, A., & Sonnemans, J. (2009). The tragedy of the commons revisited: The importance of group decision-making. Journal of Public Economics, 93(5–6), 785–797.CrossRef
go back to reference Güney, c, & Newell, B. (2015). Overcoming ambiguity aversion through experience. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 28, 188–199.CrossRef Güney, c, & Newell, B. (2015). Overcoming ambiguity aversion through experience. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 28, 188–199.CrossRef
go back to reference Halevy, Y. (2007). Ellsberg revisited: An experimental study. Econometrica, 75(2), 503–536.CrossRef Halevy, Y. (2007). Ellsberg revisited: An experimental study. Econometrica, 75(2), 503–536.CrossRef
go back to reference Hey, J., & Pace, N. (2014). The explanatory and predictive power of non two-stage-probability models of decision making under ambiguity. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 49(1), 1–29.CrossRef Hey, J., & Pace, N. (2014). The explanatory and predictive power of non two-stage-probability models of decision making under ambiguity. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 49(1), 1–29.CrossRef
go back to reference Hey, J. D., & Dardanoni, V. (1988). Optimal consumption under uncertainty: An experimental investigation. The Economic Journal, 98(390), 105–116.CrossRef Hey, J. D., & Dardanoni, V. (1988). Optimal consumption under uncertainty: An experimental investigation. The Economic Journal, 98(390), 105–116.CrossRef
go back to reference Jackson, M. O., & Yariv, L. (2014). Present bias and collective dynamic choice in the lab. American Economic Review, 104(12), 4184–4204.CrossRef Jackson, M. O., & Yariv, L. (2014). Present bias and collective dynamic choice in the lab. American Economic Review, 104(12), 4184–4204.CrossRef
go back to reference Keck, S., Diecidue, E., & Budescu, D. (2014). Group decisions under ambiguity: Convergence to neutrality. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 103, 60–71.CrossRef Keck, S., Diecidue, E., & Budescu, D. (2014). Group decisions under ambiguity: Convergence to neutrality. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 103, 60–71.CrossRef
go back to reference Keller, R., Sarin, R., & Sounderpandian, J. (2007). An examination of ambiguity aversion: Are two heads better than one? Judgment and Decision Making, 2(6), 390–397. Keller, R., Sarin, R., & Sounderpandian, J. (2007). An examination of ambiguity aversion: Are two heads better than one? Judgment and Decision Making, 2(6), 390–397.
go back to reference Klibanoff, P., Marinacci, M., & Mukerji, S. (2005). A smooth model of decision making under ambiguity. Econometrica, 73(6), 1849–1892.CrossRef Klibanoff, P., Marinacci, M., & Mukerji, S. (2005). A smooth model of decision making under ambiguity. Econometrica, 73(6), 1849–1892.CrossRef
go back to reference Kugler, T., Kausel, E. E., & Kocher, M. G. (2012). Are group more rational than individuals? A review of interactive decision making in groups. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews Cognitive Science, 3(4), 471–482.CrossRef Kugler, T., Kausel, E. E., & Kocher, M. G. (2012). Are group more rational than individuals? A review of interactive decision making in groups. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews Cognitive Science, 3(4), 471–482.CrossRef
go back to reference Lahno, A. M. (2014). Social anchor effects in decision-making under ambiguity. Discussion Papers in Economics 20960, University of Munich, Department of Economics. Lahno, A. M. (2014). Social anchor effects in decision-making under ambiguity. Discussion Papers in Economics 20960, University of Munich, Department of Economics.
go back to reference Levati, V., Napel, S., & Soraperra, I. (2016). Collective choices under ambiguity. Group Decision and Negotiation, 26, 1–17. Levati, V., Napel, S., & Soraperra, I. (2016). Collective choices under ambiguity. Group Decision and Negotiation, 26, 1–17.
go back to reference Marinacci, M. (2002). Learning from ambiguous urns. Statistical Papers, 43, 145–151.CrossRef Marinacci, M. (2002). Learning from ambiguous urns. Statistical Papers, 43, 145–151.CrossRef
go back to reference Masclet, D., Colombier, N., Denant-Boemont, L., & Lohéac, Y. (2009). Group and individual risk preferences: A lottery-choice experiment with self-employed and salaried workers. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 70(3), 470–484. (Field Experiments in Economics).CrossRef Masclet, D., Colombier, N., Denant-Boemont, L., & Lohéac, Y. (2009). Group and individual risk preferences: A lottery-choice experiment with self-employed and salaried workers. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 70(3), 470–484. (Field Experiments in Economics).CrossRef
go back to reference Meissner, T. (2015). Intertemporal consumption and debt aversion: An experimental study. Experimental Economics, 19, 1–18. Meissner, T. (2015). Intertemporal consumption and debt aversion: An experimental study. Experimental Economics, 19, 1–18.
go back to reference Muthukrishnan, A., Wathieu, L., & Xu, J. (2009). Ambiguity aversion and the preference for established brands. Management Science, 55(12), 1933–1941.CrossRef Muthukrishnan, A., Wathieu, L., & Xu, J. (2009). Ambiguity aversion and the preference for established brands. Management Science, 55(12), 1933–1941.CrossRef
go back to reference Nicholls, N., Romm, A. T., & Zimper, A. (2015). The impact of statistical learning on violations of the sure-thing principle. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 50(2), 97–115.CrossRef Nicholls, N., Romm, A. T., & Zimper, A. (2015). The impact of statistical learning on violations of the sure-thing principle. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 50(2), 97–115.CrossRef
go back to reference Peijnenburg (2015). Life-cycle asset allocation with ambiguity aversion and learning. Working paper. Peijnenburg (2015). Life-cycle asset allocation with ambiguity aversion and learning. Working paper.
go back to reference R Core Team. (2013). R: A language and environment for statistical computing. Vienna: R Foundation for Statistical Computing. R Core Team. (2013). R: A language and environment for statistical computing. Vienna: R Foundation for Statistical Computing.
go back to reference Savage, L. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New York: Wiley. Savage, L. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New York: Wiley.
go back to reference Schotter, A., & Braunstein, Y. (1981). Economic search: An experinental study. Economic In, 19(1), 1–25. Schotter, A., & Braunstein, Y. (1981). Economic search: An experinental study. Economic In, 19(1), 1–25.
go back to reference Shapiro, J. (2010). Discounting for you, me and we: Time preference in groups and pairs. mimeo. Shapiro, J. (2010). Discounting for you, me and we: Time preference in groups and pairs. mimeo.
go back to reference Shupp, R., & Williams, A. (2008). Risk preference differentials of small groups and individuals. The Economic Journal, 118(525), 258–283.CrossRef Shupp, R., & Williams, A. (2008). Risk preference differentials of small groups and individuals. The Economic Journal, 118(525), 258–283.CrossRef
go back to reference Stahl, D. (2014). Heterogeneity of ambiguity preferences. The Review of Economics and Statistics, 96(5), 609–617.CrossRef Stahl, D. (2014). Heterogeneity of ambiguity preferences. The Review of Economics and Statistics, 96(5), 609–617.CrossRef
go back to reference Trautmann, S., & van de Kuilen, G. (2015). Wiley Blackwell handbook of judgment and decision making, chapter Ambiguity Attitudes (pp. 89–116). Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRef Trautmann, S., & van de Kuilen, G. (2015). Wiley Blackwell handbook of judgment and decision making, chapter Ambiguity Attitudes (pp. 89–116). Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRef
go back to reference Trautmann, S., Vieider, F., & Wakker, P. (2008). Causes of ambiguity aversion: Known versus unknown preferences. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 36(3), 225–243.CrossRef Trautmann, S., Vieider, F., & Wakker, P. (2008). Causes of ambiguity aversion: Known versus unknown preferences. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 36(3), 225–243.CrossRef
go back to reference Viscusi, W. (1985). A Bayesian perspective on biases in risk perception. Economics Letters, 17(1–2), 59–62.CrossRef Viscusi, W. (1985). A Bayesian perspective on biases in risk perception. Economics Letters, 17(1–2), 59–62.CrossRef
go back to reference Viscusi, W., & O’Connor, J. (1984). Adaptive responses to chemical labeling: Are workers Bayesian decision makers? The American Economic Review, 74(5), 942–956. Viscusi, W., & O’Connor, J. (1984). Adaptive responses to chemical labeling: Are workers Bayesian decision makers? The American Economic Review, 74(5), 942–956.
go back to reference Zhang, J., & Casari, M. (2012). How groups reach agreement in risky choices. Economic Inquiry, 50(2), 502–515.CrossRef Zhang, J., & Casari, M. (2012). How groups reach agreement in risky choices. Economic Inquiry, 50(2), 502–515.CrossRef
go back to reference Zimper, A., & Ludwig, A. (2009). On attitude polarization under Bayesian learning with non-additive beliefs. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 39(2), 181–212.CrossRef Zimper, A., & Ludwig, A. (2009). On attitude polarization under Bayesian learning with non-additive beliefs. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 39(2), 181–212.CrossRef
Metadata
Title
Individual vs. group decision-making: an experiment on dynamic choice under risk and ambiguity
Authors
Enrica Carbone
Konstantinos Georgalos
Gerardo Infante
Publication date
05-03-2019
Publisher
Springer US
Published in
Theory and Decision / Issue 1/2019
Print ISSN: 0040-5833
Electronic ISSN: 1573-7187
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-019-09694-8

Other articles of this Issue 1/2019

Theory and Decision 1/2019 Go to the issue