Skip to main content
Top

2017 | OriginalPaper | Chapter

Mixed-Strategy Kant-Nash Equilibrium and Private Contributions to a Public Good

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

This paper models situations where contributors to a public good belong to two distinct behavioral types: Kantian and Nashian. In particular, we study how the expected level of aggregate contribution to public good may change across mixed strategy equilibria when the proportion of Kantian in the population changes. The model provides a simple theoretical account of the observed phenomenon that the extent of private provision of public goods varies considerably across time and across countries that have similar levels of per capita income.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Appendix
Available only for authorised users
Footnotes
1
Laffont (1975) was the first paper to model Kantian behavior in the context of public goods. Cornes and Sandler (1984) made a brief reference to Kantian ethics: “…the Pareto path corresponds to Kantian behaviour, since the ‘categorical imperative, whereby each acts as they want others to act, is satisfied” (p. 377). I thank Wolfgang Buchholz for this quotation.
 
2
For example, the level of cleanliness of the sidewalks in a typical suburb in Kobe, Japan, is much higher than that of a typical suburb of Montreal, Canada with the same per capita income. On a positive note, Montreal’s student ghetto near McGill University has gradually become cleaner over the past two decades, suggesting that the Kantian mode of behavior has become more widespread.
 
3
See Smith (1790, [2002]), Part III, Chapter V, p. 190. Smith’s view was echoed in Leif Johansen (1976), who wrote that economic theory “tends to suggest that people are honest only to the extent that they have economic incentives for being so”, and went on to argue that “the assumption can hardly be true in its most extreme form. No society would be viable without some norms and rules of conduct.”
 
4
Roemer (2015) also introduces the ‘Kantian variation’ which contains additive Kantian equilibrium and multiplicative Kantian equilibrium as special cases. The Kantian variation is reminiscent of the notion of conjectural variation, which was insightfully used by Cornes and Sandler (1984) in the analysis of non-Nash behavior in public good games. See also Buchholz et al. (2014a) and Buchholz (2016).
 
5
Roemer (2010) has an example of a two-person prisoner dilemma game in which mixed strategies are allowed.
 
6
The concept of Kant-Nash equilibrium in pure strategies was developed in Long (2016), and has been generalized by Grafton et al. (2016).
 
7
In a model with only two Kantians and no Nashian, Roemer (2010) also showed the possibility of a mixed strategy equilibrium. He wrote that “only if utility from cheating is not too high will Kantian ethics induce full cooperation.” That statement is somewhat misleading, as it incorrectly equates “full cooperation” with “always contributing.” It should be restated as follows: The strategy profile “always contributing” (i.e. choosing C with probability 1) is a collusive equilibrium if and only if a player’s personal gain from non-contributing (while others contribute) is sufficiently low”. In fact, when a player’s personal gain from non-contributing (while others contribute) is high enough, all players will agree that they will be better off by choosing a common non-degenerate mixed strategy, and a social planner would advise them to do the same thing.
 
8
See Bertrand Russell’s A History of Western Philosophy. As explained by Russell (1945, p. 737) ‘There are two sorts of imperative: the hypothetical imperative, which says “You must do so-and-so if you wish to achieve such-and-such an end”; and the categorical imperative, which says that a certain kind of action is objectively necessary, without regard to any end.’
 
9
For examples of replicator dynamics, see Bala and Long (2005), Breton et al. (2010), Sethi and Somanathan (1996). For an account of the evolution of cooperation in human society, see Seabright (2010).
 
Literature
go back to reference Arrow, K. J. (1973). Social responsibility and economic efficiency. Public Policy, 21, 303–317. Arrow, K. J. (1973). Social responsibility and economic efficiency. Public Policy, 21, 303–317.
go back to reference Bala, V., & Long, N. V. (2005). International trade and cultural diversity with preference selection. European Journal of Political Economy, 21(1), 143–162.CrossRef Bala, V., & Long, N. V. (2005). International trade and cultural diversity with preference selection. European Journal of Political Economy, 21(1), 143–162.CrossRef
go back to reference Bergstrom, T., Blume, L., & Varian, H. (1986). On the private provision of public goods. Journal of Public Economics, 29(1), 25–49.CrossRef Bergstrom, T., Blume, L., & Varian, H. (1986). On the private provision of public goods. Journal of Public Economics, 29(1), 25–49.CrossRef
go back to reference Brekke, K. A., Kverndokk, S., & Nyborg, K. (2003). An economic model of moral motivation. Journal of Public Economics, 87, 1967–1983.CrossRef Brekke, K. A., Kverndokk, S., & Nyborg, K. (2003). An economic model of moral motivation. Journal of Public Economics, 87, 1967–1983.CrossRef
go back to reference Breton, M., Sbragia, L., & Zaccour, G. (2010). A dynamic model of international environmental agreements. Environmental and Resource Economics, 45, 25–48.CrossRef Breton, M., Sbragia, L., & Zaccour, G. (2010). A dynamic model of international environmental agreements. Environmental and Resource Economics, 45, 25–48.CrossRef
go back to reference Buchholz, W. (2016). Voluntary Public Good Provision as an Aggregative Game - A Pedagogical Note. Typescript, University of Regensburg. Buchholz, W. (2016). Voluntary Public Good Provision as an Aggregative Game - A Pedagogical Note. Typescript, University of Regensburg.
go back to reference Buchholz, W., Cornes, R., & Rübbelke, D. (2014a). Potentially harmful international cooperation on global public good provision. Economica, 81(322), 205–223. Buchholz, W., Cornes, R., & Rübbelke, D. (2014a). Potentially harmful international cooperation on global public good provision. Economica, 81(322), 205–223.
go back to reference Buchholz, W., Falkinger, J., & Rübbelke, D. (2014b). Non-governmental public norm enforcement in large societies as a two-stage game of voluntary public good provision. Journal of Public Economic Theory, 16(6), 899–916. Buchholz, W., Falkinger, J., & Rübbelke, D. (2014b). Non-governmental public norm enforcement in large societies as a two-stage game of voluntary public good provision. Journal of Public Economic Theory, 16(6), 899–916.
go back to reference Cornes, R., Long, N. V., & Shimomura, K. (2001). Drugs and pests: Intertemporal production externalities. Japan and the World Economy, 13(3), 255–278.CrossRef Cornes, R., Long, N. V., & Shimomura, K. (2001). Drugs and pests: Intertemporal production externalities. Japan and the World Economy, 13(3), 255–278.CrossRef
go back to reference Cornes, R., & Sandler, T. (1984). The theory of public goods: Non-nash behavior. Journal of Public Economics, 23, 367–379.CrossRef Cornes, R., & Sandler, T. (1984). The theory of public goods: Non-nash behavior. Journal of Public Economics, 23, 367–379.CrossRef
go back to reference Dockner, E., Jorgensen, S., Long, N. V., & Sorger, G. (2000). Differential games, with applications to economics and management science. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Dockner, E., Jorgensen, S., Long, N. V., & Sorger, G. (2000). Differential games, with applications to economics and management science. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Grafton, Q., Kompas, T., & Long, N. V. (2016). Virtual co-mover equilibria in games of climate change mitigation. Paper presented at the 11th Tinbergen Institute-ERC Conference: Combating Climate Change, Amsterdam, April 2016. Grafton, Q., Kompas, T., & Long, N. V. (2016). Virtual co-mover equilibria in games of climate change mitigation. Paper presented at the 11th Tinbergen Institute-ERC Conference: Combating Climate Change, Amsterdam, April 2016.
go back to reference Johansen, L. (1976). The theory of public goods: Misplaced emphasis. Oslo: Institute of Economics, University of Oslo. Johansen, L. (1976). The theory of public goods: Misplaced emphasis. Oslo: Institute of Economics, University of Oslo.
go back to reference Kay, J. (2015). Other people’s money. Masters of the universe or servants of the people? London, U.K.: Profile Books Ltd. Kay, J. (2015). Other people’s money. Masters of the universe or servants of the people? London, U.K.: Profile Books Ltd.
go back to reference Kemp, M. C. (1984). A note on the theory of international transfers. Economics Letters, 14(2–3), 259–262.CrossRef Kemp, M. C. (1984). A note on the theory of international transfers. Economics Letters, 14(2–3), 259–262.CrossRef
go back to reference Kemp, M. C., & Long, N. V. (2009). Foreign aid in the presence of corruption: A differential game. Review of International Economics, 17(2), 230–243.CrossRef Kemp, M. C., & Long, N. V. (2009). Foreign aid in the presence of corruption: A differential game. Review of International Economics, 17(2), 230–243.CrossRef
go back to reference Laffont, J.-J. (1975). Macroeconomic constraints, economic efficiency and ethics: An introduction to Kantian economics. Economica, 42, 430–437.CrossRef Laffont, J.-J. (1975). Macroeconomic constraints, economic efficiency and ethics: An introduction to Kantian economics. Economica, 42, 430–437.CrossRef
go back to reference Long, N. V. (2016), Kant-Nash equilibrium in a quantity-setting oligopoly. In P. von Mouche & F. Quartieri (Eds.), Equilibrium theory for cournot oligopolies and related games: Essays in honour of Koji Okuguchi (pp. 179–202). Switzerland: Springer.CrossRef Long, N. V. (2016), Kant-Nash equilibrium in a quantity-setting oligopoly. In P. von Mouche & F. Quartieri (Eds.), Equilibrium theory for cournot oligopolies and related games: Essays in honour of Koji Okuguchi (pp. 179–202). Switzerland: Springer.CrossRef
go back to reference Roemer, J. E. (2010). Kantian equilibrium. Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 112(1), 1–24.CrossRef Roemer, J. E. (2010). Kantian equilibrium. Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 112(1), 1–24.CrossRef
go back to reference Roemer, J. E. (2015). Kantian optimization: A microfoundation for cooperation. Journal of Public Economics, 127, 45–57.CrossRef Roemer, J. E. (2015). Kantian optimization: A microfoundation for cooperation. Journal of Public Economics, 127, 45–57.CrossRef
go back to reference Russell, B. (1945). A history of western philosophy. London: George Allen and Unwin. Russell, B. (1945). A history of western philosophy. London: George Allen and Unwin.
go back to reference Seabright, P. (2010). The company of strangers: A natural history of economic life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRef Seabright, P. (2010). The company of strangers: A natural history of economic life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Sen, A. (1977). Rational fools: A critique of the behavioral foundation of utility. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6(4), 317–344. Sen, A. (1977). Rational fools: A critique of the behavioral foundation of utility. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6(4), 317–344.
go back to reference Sen, A. (1993). Does business ethics make economic sense? Business Ethics Quarterly, 3(1), 45–54.CrossRef Sen, A. (1993). Does business ethics make economic sense? Business Ethics Quarterly, 3(1), 45–54.CrossRef
go back to reference Sethi, R., & Somanathan, E. (1996). The evolution of social norms in common property resource use. American Economic Review, 86(4), 766–788. Sethi, R., & Somanathan, E. (1996). The evolution of social norms in common property resource use. American Economic Review, 86(4), 766–788.
go back to reference Smith, A. (1790 [2002]) The theory of moral sentiments (revised edition, 1790). Republished in the series Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy, edited by Knud Haakonssen. Smith, A. (1790 [2002]) The theory of moral sentiments (revised edition, 1790). Republished in the series Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy, edited by Knud Haakonssen.
go back to reference Warr, P. (1983). The private provision of public goods is independent of the distribution of income. Economics Letters, 13(2–3), 207–211.CrossRef Warr, P. (1983). The private provision of public goods is independent of the distribution of income. Economics Letters, 13(2–3), 207–211.CrossRef
Metadata
Title
Mixed-Strategy Kant-Nash Equilibrium and Private Contributions to a Public Good
Author
Ngo Van Long
Copyright Year
2017
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-49442-5_6