Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Argumentation 3/2017

28-12-2016

Presumptions, Assumptions, and Presuppositions of Ordinary Arguments

Author: Gilbert Plumer

Published in: Argumentation | Issue 3/2017

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Although in some contexts the notions of an ordinary argument’s presumption, assumption, and presupposition appear to merge into the one concept of an implicit premise, there are important differences between these three notions. It is argued that assumption and presupposition, but not presumption, are basic logical notions. A presupposition of an argument is best understood as pertaining to a propositional element (a premise or the conclusion) e of the argument, such that the presupposition is a necessary condition for the truth of e or for a term in e to have a referent. In contrast, an assumption of an argument pertains to the argument as a whole in that it is integral to the reasoning or inferential structure of the argument. A logical assumption of an argument is essentially a proposition that must be true in order for the argument aside from that proposition to be fully cogent. Nothing that is both comparable and distinguishing can be said about presumptions of arguments. Rather, presumptions of arguments are distinctively conventional; they are introduced through conventional rules (e.g., those that concern how to treat promises). So not all assumptions and not all presuppositions of arguments are presumptions of those arguments, although all presumptions of arguments are either assumptions or presuppositions of those arguments. This account avoids making the (monological) notion of presumption vacuous and dissolving the distinction between assumption and presumption, which is a vulnerability of alternative views such as Hansen’s and Bermejo-Luque’s, as is shown.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
Hypothetical Syllogism is the conditionalized form of the Barbara syllogism. Hitchcock (2002) presents a challenge, with respect to an enthymematic argument putatively a Barbara syllogism, to show why the implicit assumption completes a Barbara syllogism and not a recherché Disjunctive Syllogism. Paglieri and Woods convincingly answer this challenge (2011a, pp. 488–489).
 
2
Some of the ideas in this section appeared in earlier form in Plumer (1999).
 
3
Note that in this paper I am not directly concerned with the matter of how, in the first place, one finds implicit assumption candidates (that can then be subjected to my criteria). For procedures that are designed to help with this and that embody criteria that are in some respects comparable to my principal criterion, see Donn (1990, p. 159ff.) and Malone (2003, p. 246ff.).
 
4
1 satisfies the other criteria proposed above for determining implicit assumptions of arguments if we suppose, as Ennis apparently does (p. 75), that 1 is not a necessary truth. If 1 were taken to be a necessary or conceptual truth such that the concept of animal is involved in the concept of dog, then as ‘materially’ or ‘substantively’ valid, it would not be at all clear that the stated argument has any such implicit assumption. For discussion, see Plumer (2000, pp. 3–4).
 
5
Here is a richer nondeductive case (from the Feb. 1992 Law School Admission Test, Copyright © 1992 by Law School Admission Council):
“The brains of identical twins are genetically identical. When only one of a pair of identical twins is a schizophrenic, certain areas of the affected twin's brain are smaller than corresponding areas in the brain of the unaffected twin. No such differences are found when neither twin is schizophrenic. Therefore, this discovery provides definitive evidence that schizophrenia is caused by damage to the physical structure of the brain.”
The test question asks “Which one of the following is an assumption required by the argument?” and the credited response says “The relative smallness of certain parts of the brains of schizophrenics is not the result of schizophrenia or of medications used in its treatment.”
I interpret the causal relationships propounded by the argument to be that damage to the physical structure of the brain is the common cause of both schizophrenia and the relative smallness of certain parts of the brains of schizophrenics. This is how the argument explains the “discovery,” i.e., the apparently perfect correlation of schizophrenia and the relative smallness, after in effect ruling out a genetic explanation. The credited response contributes to the argument’s cogency in an essential way by ruling out two further salient alternative explanations of this correlation. If the negation of this response were the case, then (at least) one of these alternative explanations would be true, and it would fully explain the discovery or evidence without any need to appeal to a damaging mechanism, contrary to the argument.
 
6
Actually, I am not sure that the idea of an argument that is wholly or irredeemably fallacious makes sense. What would the alleged premises or assumptions, let alone the alleged conclusion, be doing in such a case?
 
7
For more on the problems with this sort of move, see Plumer (1999, pp. 52–54), and Plumer (2000).
 
8
A presuppositional (vs. premissory) presumption of an argument would be a presupposition of a premissory presumption of that argument.
 
9
For helpful comments on earlier drafts, I am grateful to Lyra Hostetter, Kenneth Olson, Teresa Plumer, and audience members at the Conference on Presumptions, Presumptive Inferences and Burden of Proof, University of Granada, April 2016.
 
Literature
go back to reference Adler, J. 2006. Confidence in argument. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (2): 225–258.CrossRef Adler, J. 2006. Confidence in argument. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (2): 225–258.CrossRef
go back to reference Allen, D. 1998. Should we assess the basic premises of an argument for truth or acceptability? In Proceedings of the 2nd conference of the Ontario society for the study of argumentation, 1–9. Windsor, ON: OSSA (CD ROM). Allen, D. 1998. Should we assess the basic premises of an argument for truth or acceptability? In Proceedings of the 2nd conference of the Ontario society for the study of argumentation, 1–9. Windsor, ON: OSSA (CD ROM).
go back to reference Bermejo-Luque, L. 2013. Assessing presumptions in argumentation: Being a sound presumption vs. being presumably the case. In Virtues of argumentation: Proceedings of the 10th international conference of the Ontario society for the study of argumentation, ed. D. Mohammed and M. Lewiński, 1–13. Windsor, ON: OSSA (CD-ROM). Bermejo-Luque, L. 2013. Assessing presumptions in argumentation: Being a sound presumption vs. being presumably the case. In Virtues of argumentation: Proceedings of the 10th international conference of the Ontario society for the study of argumentation, ed. D. Mohammed and M. Lewiński, 1–13. Windsor, ON: OSSA (CD-ROM).
go back to reference Bermejo-Luque, L. 2016. Being a correct presumption vs. being presumably the case. Informal Logic 36 (1): 1–25.CrossRef Bermejo-Luque, L. 2016. Being a correct presumption vs. being presumably the case. Informal Logic 36 (1): 1–25.CrossRef
go back to reference Burke, M. 1985. Unstated premises. Informal Logic 7 (2–3): 107–118. Burke, M. 1985. Unstated premises. Informal Logic 7 (2–3): 107–118.
go back to reference Copi, I.M. 1978. Introduction to logic, 5th ed. New York: Macmillan. Copi, I.M. 1978. Introduction to logic, 5th ed. New York: Macmillan.
go back to reference Donn, M. 1990. Help in finding missing premises. Teaching Philosophy 13 (2): 159–164.CrossRef Donn, M. 1990. Help in finding missing premises. Teaching Philosophy 13 (2): 159–164.CrossRef
go back to reference Ennis, R.H. 1982. Identifying implicit assumptions. Synthese 51 (1): 61–86.CrossRef Ennis, R.H. 1982. Identifying implicit assumptions. Synthese 51 (1): 61–86.CrossRef
go back to reference Freeman, J.B. 2005. Acceptable premises: An epistemic approach to an informal logic problem. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Freeman, J.B. 2005. Acceptable premises: An epistemic approach to an informal logic problem. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Godden, D.M., and D. Walton. 2007. A theory of presumption for everyday argumentation. Pragmatics and Cognition 15 (2): 313–346.CrossRef Godden, D.M., and D. Walton. 2007. A theory of presumption for everyday argumentation. Pragmatics and Cognition 15 (2): 313–346.CrossRef
go back to reference Govier, T. 1972. Presuppositions, conditions, and consequences. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 1 (4): 443–456.CrossRef Govier, T. 1972. Presuppositions, conditions, and consequences. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 1 (4): 443–456.CrossRef
go back to reference Govier, T. 1987. Problems in argument analysis and evaluation. Dordrecht: Foris. Govier, T. 1987. Problems in argument analysis and evaluation. Dordrecht: Foris.
go back to reference Govier, T. 1992. What is a good argument? Metaphilosophy 23 (4): 393–409.CrossRef Govier, T. 1992. What is a good argument? Metaphilosophy 23 (4): 393–409.CrossRef
go back to reference Govier, T. 2010. A practical study of argument, 7th ed. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth. Govier, T. 2010. A practical study of argument, 7th ed. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
go back to reference Grennan, W. 1994. Are “gap-fillers” missing premises? Informal Logic 16 (3): 185–196.CrossRef Grennan, W. 1994. Are “gap-fillers” missing premises? Informal Logic 16 (3): 185–196.CrossRef
go back to reference Hansen, H.V. 2003. Theories of presumptions and burdens of proof. In Informal logic at 25: Proceedings of the Windsor conference, ed. J.A. Blair, et al., 1–12. Windsor, ON: OSSA (CD-ROM). Hansen, H.V. 2003. Theories of presumptions and burdens of proof. In Informal logic at 25: Proceedings of the Windsor conference, ed. J.A. Blair, et al., 1–12. Windsor, ON: OSSA (CD-ROM).
go back to reference Hitchcock, D. 1985. Enthymematic arguments. Informal Logic 7 (2–3): 83–97. Hitchcock, D. 1985. Enthymematic arguments. Informal Logic 7 (2–3): 83–97.
go back to reference Hitchcock, D. 2002. A note on implicit premisses. Informal Logic 22 (2): 159–160.CrossRef Hitchcock, D. 2002. A note on implicit premisses. Informal Logic 22 (2): 159–160.CrossRef
go back to reference Johnson, R.H., and J.A. Blair. 1977/2006. Logical self-defense. Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson/New York: International Debate Education Association. Johnson, R.H., and J.A. Blair. 1977/2006. Logical self-defense. Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson/New York: International Debate Education Association.
go back to reference Kauffeld, F.J. 1995. On the difference between assumptions and presumptions. In Argumentation and values: Proceedings of the Ninth SCA/AFA conference on argumentation, ed. S. Jackson, et al., 509–514. Annadale, VA: Speech Communication Association. Kauffeld, F.J. 1995. On the difference between assumptions and presumptions. In Argumentation and values: Proceedings of the Ninth SCA/AFA conference on argumentation, ed. S. Jackson, et al., 509–514. Annadale, VA: Speech Communication Association.
go back to reference Kauffeld, F.J. 2013. Commentary on: Lilian Bermejo-Luque’s “Assessing presumptions in argumentation: Being a sound presumption vs. being presumably the case.” In Virtues of argumentation: Proceedings of the 10th international conference of the Ontario society for the study of argumentation, ed. D. Mohammed and M. Lewiński, 1–5. Windsor, ON: OSSA (CD-ROM). Kauffeld, F.J. 2013. Commentary on: Lilian Bermejo-Luque’s “Assessing presumptions in argumentation: Being a sound presumption vs. being presumably the case.” In Virtues of argumentation: Proceedings of the 10th international conference of the Ontario society for the study of argumentation, ed. D. Mohammed and M. Lewiński, 1–5. Windsor, ON: OSSA (CD-ROM).
go back to reference Llewelyn, J.E. 1962. Presuppositions, assumptions and presumptions. Theoria 28 (2): 158–172.CrossRef Llewelyn, J.E. 1962. Presuppositions, assumptions and presumptions. Theoria 28 (2): 158–172.CrossRef
go back to reference Malone, M. 2003. Three recalcitrant problems of argument identification. Informal Logic 23 (3): 237–261.CrossRef Malone, M. 2003. Three recalcitrant problems of argument identification. Informal Logic 23 (3): 237–261.CrossRef
go back to reference Nolt, J.E. 1986. Entailment, enthymemes, and formalization. Journal of Philosophy 83 (10): 572–573.CrossRef Nolt, J.E. 1986. Entailment, enthymemes, and formalization. Journal of Philosophy 83 (10): 572–573.CrossRef
go back to reference Nosich, G.M. 1982. Reasons and arguments. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth. Nosich, G.M. 1982. Reasons and arguments. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
go back to reference Paglieri, F., and J. Woods. 2011a. Enthymematic parsimony. Synthese 178 (3): 461–501.CrossRef Paglieri, F., and J. Woods. 2011a. Enthymematic parsimony. Synthese 178 (3): 461–501.CrossRef
go back to reference Paglieri, F., and J. Woods. 2011b. Enthymemes: From reconstruction to understanding. Argumentation 25 (2): 127–139.CrossRef Paglieri, F., and J. Woods. 2011b. Enthymemes: From reconstruction to understanding. Argumentation 25 (2): 127–139.CrossRef
go back to reference Paglieri, F. 2015. Bogency and goodacies: On argument quality in virtue argument theory. Informal Logic 35 (1): 65–87.CrossRef Paglieri, F. 2015. Bogency and goodacies: On argument quality in virtue argument theory. Informal Logic 35 (1): 65–87.CrossRef
go back to reference Plumer, G. 2000. The paradoxical associated conditional of enthymemes. In Argumentation at the century's turn, ed. C.W. Tindale, et al., 1–8. Windsor, ON: OSSA (CD-ROM). Plumer, G. 2000. The paradoxical associated conditional of enthymemes. In  Argumentation at the century's turn, ed. C.W. Tindale, et al., 1–8. Windsor, ON: OSSA (CD-ROM).
go back to reference Rescher, N. 1977. Dialectics. A controversy-oriented approach to the theory of knowledge. Albany: State University of New York Press. Rescher, N. 1977. Dialectics. A controversy-oriented approach to the theory of knowledge. Albany: State University of New York Press.
go back to reference Shanon, B. 1976. On the two kinds of presuppositions in natural language. Foundations of Language 14 (2): 247–249. Shanon, B. 1976. On the two kinds of presuppositions in natural language. Foundations of Language 14 (2): 247–249.
go back to reference Sloman, A. 1964. Rules of inference, or suppressed premisses? Mind 73 (289): 84–96.CrossRef Sloman, A. 1964. Rules of inference, or suppressed premisses? Mind 73 (289): 84–96.CrossRef
go back to reference Ullman-Margalit, E. 1983. On presumption. Journal of Philosophy 80 (3): 143–163.CrossRef Ullman-Margalit, E. 1983. On presumption. Journal of Philosophy 80 (3): 143–163.CrossRef
go back to reference Walton, D., C. Reed, and F. Macagno. 2008. Argumentation schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Walton, D., C. Reed, and F. Macagno. 2008. Argumentation schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Walton, D. 2014. Burden of proof, presumption and argumentation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Walton, D. 2014. Burden of proof, presumption and argumentation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Metadata
Title
Presumptions, Assumptions, and Presuppositions of Ordinary Arguments
Author
Gilbert Plumer
Publication date
28-12-2016
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Argumentation / Issue 3/2017
Print ISSN: 0920-427X
Electronic ISSN: 1572-8374
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-016-9419-1

Other articles of this Issue 3/2017

Argumentation 3/2017 Go to the issue

Premium Partner