Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Argumentation 1/2022

29-10-2021 | Original Research

Reasonable Reconstruction of Socratic Irony in Public Discourse

Author: Michael J. Hoppmann

Published in: Argumentation | Issue 1/2022

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Reasonable reconstruction of public statements is an essential component of civil discourse especially in contentious political contexts. This essay addresses the problems posed by irony through the perspective of the speaker and the audience. I argue that existing attempts to systematize the identification and reconstruction of irony focus unduly on forms of contrary irony, thereby neglecting the more complex figure of Socratic Irony. Socratic Irony (also discussed as referential irony, echotic irony or dialectical irony), which can be characterized by the invocation of the voice of the other, is distinguished from other important meanings of the word “irony” and illustrated by one ancient and three contemporary examples. When encountering this stylistic device, reasonable audiences must choose their principle of reconstruction. Of the five options for this choice, the final one reconstructing Socratic Irony using recurring markers is ultimately championed and its functionality demonstrated on the four earlier examples.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
It is of course also critical for the reasonable interpretation of legally relevant statements (e.g. defamations, see Macagno and Capone 2016), but by no means limited to a formal legal context.
 
2
Depending on their historical context and background, theorists emphasize either the “Dialectical” or the “Socratic” aspect of this type of irony. As will be shown below, the defining core is the same and I will use the two labels interchangeably in this essay.
 
3
Excellent introductions into the various meanings of ‘irony’ are given by Muecke 1969, 64ff.; Ibid. 1970, 7ff.; Behler 1998, 599ff.; Olson and Olson 2004, 28ff.; Dynel 2018, 157ff. Regarding the problem of defining the essence of irony see also Detweiler 2016, 152ff.
 
4
Contrary to the above assessment, Fogelin presents a strong case in favour of a limited number of cases of popular irony, namely poetic justice, structurally resembling irony in the narrow sense, thus providing a connection between the popular usage and the more theoretical terminology (2011, 22f.). The use of ‘irony’ in the popular sense can also be found in the rhetorical literature, e.g. in Mercieca (2008) 447ff.
 
5
Leaning heavily on Schlegel’s work, Oesterreich (2002, 292ff.) dedicates three of his thirteen theses about philosophical rhetoric in the 21st century to different aspects of irony. Interestingly, he predicts that one of the dangers of the “boundless ironification” (thesis VIII), the “loss of serious meaning” could lead to a longing for a totalitarian feeling of security.
 
6
In a related sense, Plett (1999, 315) describes intertextual irony as resulting from “the tropical inversion of a pre-text statement in a post-text.”
 
7
Wright (2001, 93ff.) observes complications in reconstructing meaning within the space of the opposite, but it is not entirely clear if the kind of irony she discusses in the works of Fanny Fern is Textbook Irony proper or may be closer to the Dialectical Irony discussed below.
 
8
Although even the hostile misinterpreter should have accused him of calling her a lipstick, not a pig; but once one chooses to ignore the evident rules of reasonable reconstruction, these details might easily fall by the wayside as well.
 
9
Grano (2006, 9) adds an interesting perspective on Socratic Irony by comparing it to Bakhtin’s internal dialogue or microdialogue that is also characterized by simultaneously invoked contrasting voices. Schaeffer (1996, 14) illustrates the close relationship between Burkean and Socratic Irony by contrasting it with Vico’s Contrary Irony, and Murray (2002, 24ff.) shows its connection to Levinas. See also Linck 2003, 266. For a narrower interpretation of the role of the “enemy” in irony see Jensen 2018, 395.
 
10
See for example the sharp contrast between the literal meaning of this section and Lévystone’s interpretation of Callicles contribution and aims in the Gorgias (2020, 140f.)
 
11
Eiron and alazon are famous stock characters and antagonists in ancient Greek comedy. The former, frequently portrayed as sly trickster with deceitful understatement is usually victorious over the latter who is commonly boastful and vein (Behler 1998, 601).
 
12
Metcalf (2004, 158) analyses similar cases of Socrates “deep irony” in the Apology, Euthyphro and Theaetetus as a tool “to catalyze the agonistic combativeness that will make the elenctic encounter genuinely epideictic.”
 
13
In Sperber & Wilson’s sense (see above) the speakers technically of course do not “use” these words, but rather “mention” them. This systematically very useful difference will however be all but indistinguishable to the literally minded listener.
 
14
Given the highly offensive nature of some of the words that occur in the examples, the question of including the term unaltered, or changing them to reduce the offensiveness needs to be addressed. This is a hard question with no easy answer. I have chosen to print them unaltered in this text for three reasons: 1) doing so seems to follow the best practice of experts in the field (e.g. Hayes 2019, Xiong and Zenker 2018, Eguchi 2016, Blair 2015 and Linker 2014), 2) it avoids the “use” of the term acknowledging the use-mention distinction (Sperber and Wilson 1981) and 3) given the target audience of this journal, a normalization of the terms by mentioning alone seems unlikely, while the need for distinguishing very similar terms is high. I hope that with this warning, readers will not take offense at the examples.
 
15
This is the contrary opposite of “big bad dude”, as explicitly invoked by Anaximenes, Quintilian, Lanham, Burgers, Van Mulken & Schellens, and other representatives of Textbook Irony. Reconstructing it as mere contradictory opposite “not a big bad dude” would make the example less absurd, but it would also melt down any meaningful distinction between irony most other tropes (metaphor, hyperbola, etc).
 
16
Desilet and Appel (2011, 353) hint at a third important function of Dialectical Irony, its ability to help understand the “enemy” and introduce a level or “ironic humility”. Contrary to the observations of Wright, Holcomb (2006, 85) notes that some forms of irony are historically reserved for socially superiors addressing their inferiors or at least equals. Boogaart et al. (2021, 217) also additionally note the value of irony for variety and brevity of discourse. For the role of irony in feminism see also Renegar and Sowards (2003, 344ff.), Graban (2007, 389ff.), Galewski (2007, 84ff. and 2008, 291ff.). Kauffer (1983, 453) additionally emphasizes the function of irony in building group cohesion. Rossing (2017, 547ff.) and Waisanen (2018, 75ff.) discuss comedic silence and comic counterfactuals as an alternative tool with the potential of similar subversive effects. “Banishing” Socratic Irony, or declaring it an “indecent luxury” (the position that Terrill 2003, 216 critically opposes) would still leave room for the kind of Irony as contrastive performance that Steudeman (2013, 69ff.) observes in Nixon and Obama.
 
17
Irony is of course not the only figure that could be abused thusly if one uses the subjective speaker autonomy as the sole standard for reasonable interpretation (see e.g. Walton 1996, 50ff.) Gunn discusses a similar problem for occultatio (Gunn 2018, 161, 172f.) and goes as far as to call Trump’s frequent disavowals from his statements via this figure one of the main symptoms of his rhetorical perversion (ibid. 179). Attardo (2000, 13) considers “Retractability” to be a (seemingly unproblematic) feature of irony.
 
18
Brooke Stanley points out that there is another systematically possible, and frequently practiced option (3b), based on comparative social status of speaker and audience. In the case of the Machine Head line cited above, it would give interpretative priority to gay audiences, people of color and Hispanics to determine whether the expressions should be read literally (offensively) or ironically (inoffensively). The problems with this option are however even graver then those of Option 3, because it inherits all disadvantages of Option 3 (loss of communicative reliability and violation of principle of charity) and adds two additional ones: a) challenges in reasonably and defensibly determining speaker and audience social status or group membership and b) loss of conversational egality and reciprocity. Additionally, this option would, of course, only work for cases in which the potential offense is clearly linked to an identifiable group of people. Ultimately, this option might be less apt to identify if offense was given (ironic vs literal) and instead might be a tool to assess whether offense may be given (speaker-audience relationship).
 
19
For the general value of Grice’s model for the reasonable reconstruction of text comp. Dynel 2008 162ff. I have no intention in taking sides in the complex Gricean vs Neo-Gricean versus Post-Gricean vs Relevance Theory disputes, but rather take Grice as an example of a reconstructive model. For a more detailed discussion see Hoppmann 2019. Comp. also Dynel 2018, 33ff. and Garmendia 2015, 40ff. for a defense of the Gricean group against some of the Relevance Theory challenges.
 
20
In the case of some, e.g. Veach, the sufficiency of the list for the presence of humour is even made explicit (Veatch 1998, 163ff).
 
21
These three steps are then followed by fourth step: choosing a new meaning. It is important to note that while Booth is here grouped with Quintilian and the VIP as a representative of Textbook Irony, he explicitly rejects the idea that that the literal expression of an ironic statements and its means have to be necessarily contrary to each other (Booth 1974, 11) and the Candide example he takes from Muecke (Ibid, 10) is actually a rather clear example of Socratic Irony. Attardo (2000, 3f.) adopts a similar list to Booth, but clearly restricts irony to the textbook variety.
 
22
Boogaart et al (2021, 233) list two additional considerations: activity type in which the potential irony occurs and the perceived personality of the speaker, but they do not develop these criteria into concrete markers.
 
23
Making the attribution thus explicit thereby also implies that Socrates does not (necessarily) believe that Callicles has these characteristics. Similarly, Dr. Crutcher does not hold that her brother was a “big bad dude” and so on.
 
24
Note that the final section of this enumeration already breaks out of the irony by making the reference to the other explicit. Whether this is an intentional solving of the figure or simply follows metric necessity (or both) is difficult to decide.
 
25
The lead singer, Robb Flynn, delivered a purely vocal poetry slam version of the song’s lyrics in 2018, but this delivery does not provide bonus cues of Socratic Irony either.
 
26
Evidently having made a twice removed statement did not save Norton from being at once removed from a position at the New York Times.
 
Literature
go back to reference Anaximenes. 1957. Rhetorica ad Alexandrum. Trans. by H. Rackham, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Anaximenes. 1957. Rhetorica ad Alexandrum. Trans. by H. Rackham, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Attardo, S. 1994. Linguistic theories of humor. Berlin & New York: Mouton de Gruyter. Attardo, S. 1994. Linguistic theories of humor. Berlin & New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
go back to reference Attardo, S. 2000. Irony markers and functions: towards a goal-oriented theory of irony and its processing. RASK 12: 3–20. Attardo, S. 2000. Irony markers and functions: towards a goal-oriented theory of irony and its processing. RASK 12: 3–20.
go back to reference Behler, E. 1998. Ironie. In. G. Ueding (Ed.) Historisches Wörterbuch der Rhetorik Bd. 4, 599-624. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag. Behler, E. 1998. Ironie. In. G. Ueding (Ed.) Historisches Wörterbuch der Rhetorik Bd. 4, 599-624. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.
go back to reference Blair, A. 2015. Probative norms for multimodal visual arguments. Argumentation 29: 217–233. Blair, A. 2015. Probative norms for multimodal visual arguments. Argumentation 29: 217–233.
go back to reference Boogaart, R., H. Jansen, and M. van Leeuwen. 2021. “Those are your words, not mine!” defence strategies for denying speaker commitment. Argumentation 35: 209–235. Boogaart, R., H. Jansen, and M. van Leeuwen. 2021. “Those are your words, not mine!” defence strategies for denying speaker commitment. Argumentation 35: 209–235.
go back to reference Booth, W. 1974. A rhetoric of irony. Chicago & London: University of Chicago Press. Booth, W. 1974. A rhetoric of irony. Chicago & London: University of Chicago Press.
go back to reference Brown, Penelope, and Stephen Levinson. 1978. Universals in language usage: politeness phenomena. In Questions and Politeness, ed. Esther N. Goody, 56–289. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brown, Penelope, and Stephen Levinson. 1978. Universals in language usage: politeness phenomena. In Questions and Politeness, ed. Esther N. Goody, 56–289. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Brown, Penelope, and Stephen Levinson. 1987. Politeness: some universals in language use. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brown, Penelope, and Stephen Levinson. 1987. Politeness: some universals in language use. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Burgers, C., M. van Mulken, and P. Schellens. 2011. Finding Irony: an introduction of the verbal irony procedure (VIP). Metaphors and Symbol 26 (3): 186–205. Burgers, C., M. van Mulken, and P. Schellens. 2011. Finding Irony: an introduction of the verbal irony procedure (VIP). Metaphors and Symbol 26 (3): 186–205.
go back to reference Burgers, C., M. van Mulken, and P. Schellens. 2012. Verbal Irony: Differences in usage across written genres. Journal of Language and Social Psychology 31 (3): 290–310. Burgers, C., M. van Mulken, and P. Schellens. 2012. Verbal Irony: Differences in usage across written genres. Journal of Language and Social Psychology 31 (3): 290–310.
go back to reference Burke, K. 1941. Four master tropes. The Kenyon Review 3 (4): 421–438. Burke, K. 1941. Four master tropes. The Kenyon Review 3 (4): 421–438.
go back to reference Desilet, G., and E. Appel. 2011. Choosing a rhetoric of the enemy: Kenneth Burke’s comic frame, warrantable outrage, and the problem of scapegoating. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 41 (4): 340–362. Desilet, G., and E. Appel. 2011. Choosing a rhetoric of the enemy: Kenneth Burke’s comic frame, warrantable outrage, and the problem of scapegoating. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 41 (4): 340–362.
go back to reference Detweiler, E. 2016. Disfiguring socratic irony. Philosophy & Rhetoric 49 (2): 149–172. Detweiler, E. 2016. Disfiguring socratic irony. Philosophy & Rhetoric 49 (2): 149–172.
go back to reference Dynel, M. 2018. Irony, deception and humour. Boston & Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton. Dynel, M. 2018. Irony, deception and humour. Boston & Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.
go back to reference Eguchi, S. 2016. Sexual discretion: black masculinity and the politics of passing. Text and Performance Quarterly 36 (2–3): 180–182. Eguchi, S. 2016. Sexual discretion: black masculinity and the politics of passing. Text and Performance Quarterly 36 (2–3): 180–182.
go back to reference Flores, L. 2018. Laboring to belong: differentiation, spatial relocation, and the ironic presence of (Un)documented immigrants in the united farm workers “take our jobs” campaign. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 21 (3): 447–480. Flores, L. 2018. Laboring to belong: differentiation, spatial relocation, and the ironic presence of (Un)documented immigrants in the united farm workers “take our jobs” campaign. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 21 (3): 447–480.
go back to reference Flynn, R. 2018. Bastards. Recorded by Machine Head. On Catharsis. Oakland, CA: Sharkbite Studios. Flynn, R. 2018. Bastards. Recorded by Machine Head. On Catharsis. Oakland, CA: Sharkbite Studios.
go back to reference Fogelin, R. 2011. Figuratively speaking. Rev. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Fogelin, R. 2011. Figuratively speaking. Rev. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Galewski, E. 2007. The strange case for women’s capacity to reason: Judith Sargent Murray’s use of irony in “on the equality of the sexes” (1790). Quarterly Journal of Speech 93 (1): 84–108. Galewski, E. 2007. The strange case for women’s capacity to reason: Judith Sargent Murray’s use of irony in “on the equality of the sexes” (1790). Quarterly Journal of Speech 93 (1): 84–108.
go back to reference Galewski, E. 2008. “Playing up being a woman”: femme performance and the potential for ironic representation. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 11 (2): 279–302. Galewski, E. 2008. “Playing up being a woman”: femme performance and the potential for ironic representation. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 11 (2): 279–302.
go back to reference Garmendia, J. 2015. A (Neo)Gricean account of irony: an answer to relevance theory. International Review of Pragmatics 7 (1): 40–79. Garmendia, J. 2015. A (Neo)Gricean account of irony: an answer to relevance theory. International Review of Pragmatics 7 (1): 40–79.
go back to reference Govier, T. 2018. Problems in argument analysis and evaluation. Windsor: University of Windsor Press. Govier, T. 2018. Problems in argument analysis and evaluation. Windsor: University of Windsor Press.
go back to reference Graban, T.S. 2007. Feminine irony and the art of linguistic cooperation in Anne Askew’s sixteenth-century examinacyons. Rhetorica 25 (4): 385–411. Graban, T.S. 2007. Feminine irony and the art of linguistic cooperation in Anne Askew’s sixteenth-century examinacyons. Rhetorica 25 (4): 385–411.
go back to reference Grano, D. 2006. Wise ignorance and socratic interiority: recovering a dialogic rhetoric. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 37 (1): 1–18. Grano, D. 2006. Wise ignorance and socratic interiority: recovering a dialogic rhetoric. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 37 (1): 1–18.
go back to reference Grice, P. 1989. Logic and conversation. In Studies in the way of words, ed. P. Grice, 22–40. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Grice, P. 1989. Logic and conversation. In Studies in the way of words, ed. P. Grice, 22–40. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Gunn, J. 2018. On political perversion. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 48 (2): 161–186. Gunn, J. 2018. On political perversion. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 48 (2): 161–186.
go back to reference Hayes, H.A. 2019. This new world is not for the faint hearted: confronting the many dimensions of Philippe-Joseph Salazar’s words are weapons: inside Isis’s rhetoric of terror. Philosophy & Rhetoric 52 (3): 301–311. Hayes, H.A. 2019. This new world is not for the faint hearted: confronting the many dimensions of Philippe-Joseph Salazar’s words are weapons: inside Isis’s rhetoric of terror. Philosophy & Rhetoric 52 (3): 301–311.
go back to reference Hofmann, J.B. 1951. Lateinische Umgangssprache, 3rd ed. Heidelberg: Carl Winter. Hofmann, J.B. 1951. Lateinische Umgangssprache, 3rd ed. Heidelberg: Carl Winter.
go back to reference Holcomb, C. 2006. “Anyone can be president”: figures of speech, cultural forms, and performance. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 37 (1): 71–96. Holcomb, C. 2006. “Anyone can be president”: figures of speech, cultural forms, and performance. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 37 (1): 71–96.
go back to reference Hoppmann, M. 2017. Competition and conflict between communicative norms: is it reasonable to be polite? Journal of Argumentation in Context 6 (2): 220–246. Hoppmann, M. 2017. Competition and conflict between communicative norms: is it reasonable to be polite? Journal of Argumentation in Context 6 (2): 220–246.
go back to reference Hoppmann, M. 2019. Grice, Machine Head and the problem of overexpressed premises. In Proceedings of the 3rd European conference on argumentation, eds. C. Dutilh Novaes & B. Verheij, Groningen 2019. Hoppmann, M. 2019. Grice, Machine Head and the problem of overexpressed premises. In Proceedings of the 3rd European conference on argumentation, eds. C. Dutilh Novaes & B. Verheij, Groningen 2019.
go back to reference Jensen, K. 2018. Rhetorical counteraction in Kenneth Burke’s a rhetoric of motives and the war of words. Quarterly Journal of Speech 104 (4): 384–399. Jensen, K. 2018. Rhetorical counteraction in Kenneth Burke’s a rhetoric of motives and the war of words. Quarterly Journal of Speech 104 (4): 384–399.
go back to reference Kauffer, D. 1983. Irony, interpretive form, and the theory of meaning. Poetics Today 4 (3): 451–464. Kauffer, D. 1983. Irony, interpretive form, and the theory of meaning. Poetics Today 4 (3): 451–464.
go back to reference Lanham, R. 1991. A handlist of rhetorical terms, 2nd ed. Berkeley: University of California Press. Lanham, R. 1991. A handlist of rhetorical terms, 2nd ed. Berkeley: University of California Press.
go back to reference Lausberg, H. 1949. Elemente der literarischen Rhetorik. München: Max Huber Verlag. Lausberg, H. 1949. Elemente der literarischen Rhetorik. München: Max Huber Verlag.
go back to reference Lausberg, H. 1960. Handbuch der literarischen Rhetorik. München: Max Huber Verlag. Lausberg, H. 1960. Handbuch der literarischen Rhetorik. München: Max Huber Verlag.
go back to reference Leech, G.N. 1983. Principles of pragmatics. London: Longman. Leech, G.N. 1983. Principles of pragmatics. London: Longman.
go back to reference Leech, G.N. 2014. The pragmatics of politeness. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Leech, G.N. 2014. The pragmatics of politeness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Lévystone, D. 2020. Socrates’ versatile rhetoric and the soul of the crowd. Rhetorica 38 (2): 135–155. Lévystone, D. 2020. Socrates’ versatile rhetoric and the soul of the crowd. Rhetorica 38 (2): 135–155.
go back to reference Linck, M.S. 2003. Unmastering speech: irony in plato’s phaedrus. Philosophy & Rhetoric 36 (3): 264–276. Linck, M.S. 2003. Unmastering speech: irony in plato’s phaedrus. Philosophy & Rhetoric 36 (3): 264–276.
go back to reference Linker, M. 2014. Epistemic privilege and expertise in the context of meta-debate. Argumentation 28: 67–84. Linker, M. 2014. Epistemic privilege and expertise in the context of meta-debate. Argumentation 28: 67–84.
go back to reference Macagno, F., and A. Capone. 2016. Interpretative disputes, explicatures, and argumentative reasoning. Argumentation 30: 399–422. Macagno, F., and A. Capone. 2016. Interpretative disputes, explicatures, and argumentative reasoning. Argumentation 30: 399–422.
go back to reference McCann, B.J. 2016. “Chrysler pulled the trigger”: the affective politics of insanity and black rage at the trial of James Johnson Jr. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 46 (2): 131–155. McCann, B.J. 2016. “Chrysler pulled the trigger”: the affective politics of insanity and black rage at the trial of James Johnson Jr. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 46 (2): 131–155.
go back to reference McGraw, P., and C.Warren. 2014. Benign violation theory. In Encyclopedia of humor studies (pp. 75–77). Thousand Oaks, California: SAGE. McGraw, P., and C.Warren. 2014. Benign violation theory. In Encyclopedia of humor studies (pp. 75–77). Thousand Oaks, California: SAGE.
go back to reference McGraw, P., and J. Warner. 2014. The humor code: a global search for what makes things funny. New York: Simon & Schuster. McGraw, P., and J. Warner. 2014. The humor code: a global search for what makes things funny. New York: Simon & Schuster.
go back to reference McGraw, A.P., and C. Warren. 2010. Benign violations: making immoral behavior funny. Psychological Science 21 (8): 1141–1149. McGraw, A.P., and C. Warren. 2010. Benign violations: making immoral behavior funny. Psychological Science 21 (8): 1141–1149.
go back to reference Mercieca, J. 2008. The irony of the democratic style. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 11 (3): 441–449. Mercieca, J. 2008. The irony of the democratic style. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 11 (3): 441–449.
go back to reference Metcalf, R. 2004. The philosophical rhetoric of socrates’ mission. Philosophy and Rhetoric 37 (2): 143–165. Metcalf, R. 2004. The philosophical rhetoric of socrates’ mission. Philosophy and Rhetoric 37 (2): 143–165.
go back to reference Morissette, A. 1995. Isn’t it ironic. On Jagged Little Pill. Beverly Hills, CA: Maverick, Reprise. Morissette, A. 1995. Isn’t it ironic. On Jagged Little Pill. Beverly Hills, CA: Maverick, Reprise.
go back to reference Muecke, D.C. 1969. The compass of irony. London & New York: Methuen. Muecke, D.C. 1969. The compass of irony. London & New York: Methuen.
go back to reference Muecke, D.C. 1970. Irony and the ironic. London & New York: Methuen. Muecke, D.C. 1970. Irony and the ironic. London & New York: Methuen.
go back to reference Murray, J.W. 2002. Dialogue of motives. Philosophy & Rhetoric 35 (1): 22–4. Murray, J.W. 2002. Dialogue of motives. Philosophy & Rhetoric 35 (1): 22–4.
go back to reference Oesterreich, P.L. 2002. Thesen zum homo rhetoricus und zur Neugestaltung der Philosophie im 21 Jahrhundert. Rhetorica 20 (3): 289–298. Oesterreich, P.L. 2002. Thesen zum homo rhetoricus und zur Neugestaltung der Philosophie im 21 Jahrhundert. Rhetorica 20 (3): 289–298.
go back to reference Olson, K., and C. Olson. 2004. Beyond strategy: a reader-centered analysis of irony’s dual persuasive uses. Quarterly Journal of Speech 90 (1): 24–52. Olson, K., and C. Olson. 2004. Beyond strategy: a reader-centered analysis of irony’s dual persuasive uses. Quarterly Journal of Speech 90 (1): 24–52.
go back to reference Pitchford, M. 2020. The empire of outrage: topical systems at the death of cecil the lion. Quarterly Journal of Speech 106 (2): 156–178. Pitchford, M. 2020. The empire of outrage: topical systems at the death of cecil the lion. Quarterly Journal of Speech 106 (2): 156–178.
go back to reference Plato. 1925. Lysis. Symposium. Gorgias. W. R. M. Lamb (trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Plato. 1925. Lysis. Symposium. Gorgias. W. R. M. Lamb (trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Plett, H.F. 1999. Rhetoric and Intertextuality. Rhetorica 17 (3): 313–329. Plett, H.F. 1999. Rhetoric and Intertextuality. Rhetorica 17 (3): 313–329.
go back to reference Quintilian, M. F. 2001. The orator's education. D. A. Russell (trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Quintilian, M. F. 2001. The orator's education. D. A. Russell (trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Raskin, V. 1985. Semantic mechanisms of humor. Dordrecht et al.: D. Seidel. Raskin, V. 1985. Semantic mechanisms of humor. Dordrecht et al.: D. Seidel.
go back to reference Renegar, V.R., and S.K. Sowards. 2003. Liberal irony, rhetoric, and feminist thought: a unifying third wave feminist theory. Philosophy & Rhetoric 36 (4): 330–352. Renegar, V.R., and S.K. Sowards. 2003. Liberal irony, rhetoric, and feminist thought: a unifying third wave feminist theory. Philosophy & Rhetoric 36 (4): 330–352.
go back to reference Rossing, J. 2017. No joke: silent jesters and comedic refusals. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 20 (3): 545–555. Rossing, J. 2017. No joke: silent jesters and comedic refusals. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 20 (3): 545–555.
go back to reference Schaeffer, J. 1996. Vico and Kenneth Burke. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 26 (2): 7–17. Schaeffer, J. 1996. Vico and Kenneth Burke. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 26 (2): 7–17.
go back to reference Seneca the Elder. 1974. Declamations. Vol. II. W. C. Wright (trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Seneca the Elder. 1974. Declamations. Vol. II. W. C. Wright (trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Simpson, P. 2011. “That’s not ironic, that’s just stupid” Towards an eclectic account of the discourse of irony. In The pragmatics of humour across discourse domains, ed. M. Dynel, 33–50. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Simpson, P. 2011. “That’s not ironic, that’s just stupid” Towards an eclectic account of the discourse of irony. In The pragmatics of humour across discourse domains, ed. M. Dynel, 33–50. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
go back to reference Sperber, D., and D. Wilson. 1981. Irony and the use-mention distinction. In Radical pragmatics, ed. P. Cole, 295–318. New York: Academic Press. Sperber, D., and D. Wilson. 1981. Irony and the use-mention distinction. In Radical pragmatics, ed. P. Cole, 295–318. New York: Academic Press.
go back to reference Sperber, D., and D. Wilson. 1995. Relevance: communication and cognition, 2nd ed. Malden: Blackwell Publishing. Sperber, D., and D. Wilson. 1995. Relevance: communication and cognition, 2nd ed. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.
go back to reference Steudeman, M. 2013. Entelechy and irony in political time: the preemptive rhetoric of nixon and Obama. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 16 (1): 59–96. Steudeman, M. 2013. Entelechy and irony in political time: the preemptive rhetoric of nixon and Obama. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 16 (1): 59–96.
go back to reference Stevens, K. 2021. Charity for moral reasons? A defense of the principle of charity in argumentation. Argumentation and Advocacy 57 (2): 67–84. Stevens, K. 2021. Charity for moral reasons? A defense of the principle of charity in argumentation. Argumentation and Advocacy 57 (2): 67–84.
go back to reference Terrill, R. 2003. Irony, silence, and time: frederick douglass on the fifth of july. Quarterly Journal of Speech 89 (3): 216–234. Terrill, R. 2003. Irony, silence, and time: frederick douglass on the fifth of july. Quarterly Journal of Speech 89 (3): 216–234.
go back to reference van Eemeren, F.H. 2018. Argumentation theory: a pragma-dialectical perspective. Cham: Springer. van Eemeren, F.H. 2018. Argumentation theory: a pragma-dialectical perspective. Cham: Springer.
go back to reference van Eemeren, F.H., and A.F. Snoeck Henkemans. 2017. Argumentation: analysis and evaluation. New York & London: Routledge. van Eemeren, F.H., and A.F. Snoeck Henkemans. 2017. Argumentation: analysis and evaluation. New York & London: Routledge.
go back to reference van Eemeren, F.H., R. Grootendorst, S. Jackson, and S. Jacobs. 1993. Reconstructing argumentative discourse. Tuscaloosa, AL: University of Alabama Press. van Eemeren, F.H., R. Grootendorst, S. Jackson, and S. Jacobs. 1993. Reconstructing argumentative discourse. Tuscaloosa, AL: University of Alabama Press.
go back to reference Veatch, T.C. 1998. A theory of humor. Humor-International Journal of Humor Research 11 (2): 161–215. Veatch, T.C. 1998. A theory of humor. Humor-International Journal of Humor Research 11 (2): 161–215.
go back to reference Waisanen, D. 2018. The comic counterfactual: laughter, affect, and civic alternatives. Quarterly Journal of Speech 104 (1): 71–93. Waisanen, D. 2018. The comic counterfactual: laughter, affect, and civic alternatives. Quarterly Journal of Speech 104 (1): 71–93.
go back to reference Walton, D. 1996. Plausible deniability and evasion of burden of proof. Argumentation 10: 47–58. Walton, D. 1996. Plausible deniability and evasion of burden of proof. Argumentation 10: 47–58.
go back to reference Warren, C., and A.P. McGraw. 2016. Differentiating what is Humorous from what is Not. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 110 (3): 407. Warren, C., and A.P. McGraw. 2016. Differentiating what is Humorous from what is Not. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 110 (3): 407.
go back to reference Wilson, D., and D. Sperber. 2012. Explaining irony. In Meaning and relevance, ed. D. Wilson and D. Sperber, 123–145. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wilson, D., and D. Sperber. 2012. Explaining irony. In Meaning and relevance, ed. D. Wilson and D. Sperber, 123–145. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Wright, E. 2001. “Joking isn’t safe”: fanny fern, irony, and signifyin(g). Rhetoric Society Quarterly 31 (2): 91–111. Wright, E. 2001. “Joking isn’t safe”: fanny fern, irony, and signifyin(g). Rhetoric Society Quarterly 31 (2): 91–111.
go back to reference Xiong, M., and F. Zenker. 2018. Legal facts in argumentation-based litigation games. Argumentation 32: 197–211. Xiong, M., and F. Zenker. 2018. Legal facts in argumentation-based litigation games. Argumentation 32: 197–211.
Metadata
Title
Reasonable Reconstruction of Socratic Irony in Public Discourse
Author
Michael J. Hoppmann
Publication date
29-10-2021
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Argumentation / Issue 1/2022
Print ISSN: 0920-427X
Electronic ISSN: 1572-8374
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-021-09557-z

Other articles of this Issue 1/2022

Argumentation 1/2022 Go to the issue

Premium Partner