Skip to main content
Top

2022 | OriginalPaper | Chapter

7. The Metaphysics of Social Collectives

Author : Ricardo F. Crespo

Published in: The Nature of the Economy

Publisher: Springer International Publishing

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Once established the metaphysic nature of the economy and of the economic agent as deciding and acting subject, and also as worker, we need to elaborate on the metaphysical nature of the economic system—i.e., the macroeconomy. This chapter will serve as a prelude to this discussion, noting that the macroeconomy refers to the economic dimension of a whole composed of a great number of people interacting between them—a social collective. Thus, before delving into the topic of the nature of the macroeconomy or macroeconomic entities, we have to establish the nature of social collectives. First, the chapter surveys dictionary definitions of social collectives in order to identify their shared characteristics, using this basic notion as a starting point to ascertain the ontology of social collectives. Next, the chapter describes and analyzes Aristotle’s seminal views on social collectives. The last section introduces some views that have some similarities with Aristotle’s and that will benefit from Aristotelian notions.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
Margaret Gilbert (2001: 109, nt. 1) uses the term “collective” because she considers it as the “genus”.
 
2
For a review of issues and positions described by Brian Epstein (2018), see the Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, entry “Social Ontology”: https://​plato.​stanford.​edu/​entries/​social-ontology/​ and https://​plato.​stanford.​edu/​entries/​social-ontology/​history.​html.
 
3
Here I follow Aristotle’s enumeration of accidents in Categories 4, 1b 25–2a 4.
 
4
See George Duke (2020: 88) for the translation of sympheron.
 
5
For example, Adam Smith claims that “[t]he wise and virtuous man is at all times willing that his own private interest should be sacrificed to the public interest of his own particular order or society” (1976: 235 –VI, iii). For John Stuart Mill, a fair government must look for citizens’ common good (see Brink 2018).
 
6
I think that the difference made by Tony Honoré between a crowd and a group illustrates this limit:
A group is more than a mere collection of individuals. A crowd is not as such a group, even if it exhibits the pattern of behavior called “crowd behavior.” On the other hand, a band of conspirators, a mountaineering expedition, and those engaged in a scientific experiment form groups. What unites them? A common purpose or activity is no doubt necessary, but hardly seems sufficient… Some shared understanding as to the means to be pursued is also needed. To constitute a group there must be an element of prescription, which limits the freedom of at least some of the group simply to go their own way. (1987: 34, my cursive)
Honoré mentions some consequences of having a common purpose or activity—I will come back to them later. At this point, I want to highlight that a mere crowd is not a social collective because its common aim is merely circumstantial. Carl Welleman (1995), following Honoré’s criterion, considers other groupings that are not “social collectives”:
Very different from organizations are unorganized groups. Among the latter, it is important to distinguish between collections and classes, between groups of people gathered together at some place at some time and groups of people classified together on the basis of a common attribute. (1995: 169)
The togetherness of this sort of group [collections] is purely spatiotemporal. The several members of a collection belong to the same group because they are at the same place at the same time. (1995: 169)
The unity of any class consists simply of some common attribute possessed by and some general name predicated of a number of individuals—not the oneness of the ontological or linguistic subject. Hence, statements about a class must be generalizations about its members (1995: 171).
 
7
Aristotle states: “For the city is, with regard to its nature, some multitude, and becoming more of a unity it will be a household rather than a city, and a human being rather than a household. For we would say that the household is more of a unity than the city, and the individual more than the household. So even if someone were able to do this, he should not do it; for this would destroy the city” (Politics 1261a 16–22; cf. 1263b 29–35).
 
8
See Robert Gallagher (2011) analysis on this and related passages of Aristotle and their consequences.
 
9
For the development of an argument applying this idea to modern society, see Charles Taylor (1985).
 
10
Barker states: “As a whole, it [the polis] is viewed as composed of parts different in kind, which are subordinates one to another; for in all compounds which form a whole, there may be traced a ruling element and a ruled” (1959: 234). In this sense, he considers the nature of a constitution as vital element (1959: 301).
 
11
Aristotle enumerates “all the elements necessary for the existence of the state. Our list of these elements will include what we have called the ‘parts’ of the state as well as we have termed its ‘conditions’. To make such a list we must first determine how many services a state performs; and then we shall easily see how many elements it must contain. The first thing to be provided is food. The next is arts and crafts; for life is a business which needs many tools. The third is arms: the members of a state must bear arms in person, partly in order to maintain authority and repress disobedience, and partly in order to meet any thread of external aggression. The fourth thing which has to be provided is a certain supply of property, alike for domestic use and for military purposes. The fifth (but in order of merit, the first) is an establishment for the service of the gods, or as it is called, public worship. The sixth thing, and the most vitally necessary, is a method of deciding what is demanded by the public interest and what is just in men’s private dealings. These are the services which every state may be said to need” (Politics VII, 8, 1328b 3–16).
 
12
For discussions on Searle’s position, see, among others, Barry Smith (Smith and Searle 2003); Frank Hindriks (2005); J.P Smit, Filip Buekens, and Stan du Plessis (2011); Georgios Papadopoulos (2015), and Francesco Guala (2016a, b).
 
13
It should be noted that, for Searle, “natural” means “physical” (see, for example, Searle 1995: Chapter 1).
 
14
Tuomela notes that some elements drawn from Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s, William McDougall’s, Alfred Vierkandt’s, and Ferdinand Tönnies’s views are relevant for his theory (2013: 93–94).
 
15
He criticizes List and Pettit (2011) for this reason (2013: 53–54). This section does not intend to discuss the different versions of supervenience and emergence in the specific literature.
 
16
Epstein is critical of Gilbert’s and Tuomela’s theories (2015: Chapter 17) on the basis that they are only applicable to small groups. This is not, as I have mentioned, Gilbert’s and Tuomela’s intention.
 
Literature
go back to reference Aquinas. (1964). In Decem Libros Ethicorum Aristotelis ad Nicomachum Expositio. Torino: Marietti. Aquinas. (1964). In Decem Libros Ethicorum Aristotelis ad Nicomachum Expositio. Torino: Marietti.
go back to reference Aquinas (1922.). Summa contra Gentiles. Torino: Marietti. Aquinas (1922.). Summa contra Gentiles. Torino: Marietti.
go back to reference Aristotle. (1954). Nicomachean Ethics. Translated and Introduced by Sir David Ross. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Aristotle. (1954). Nicomachean Ethics. Translated and Introduced by Sir David Ross. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Terence Irwin (second edition 1999). Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett. Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Terence Irwin (second edition 1999). Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett.
go back to reference Aristotle. (1958). Politics. Edited and Translated by Ernest Barker. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Aristotle. (1958). Politics. Edited and Translated by Ernest Barker. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Aristotle. (1943). Politics. Translated by Benjamin Jowett. New York: Random House. Aristotle. (1943). Politics. Translated by Benjamin Jowett. New York: Random House.
go back to reference Aristotle. The Complete Works of Aristotle. Edited by Jonathan Barnes (1984). Princeton: Princeton University Press. Aristotle. The Complete Works of Aristotle. Edited by Jonathan Barnes (1984). Princeton: Princeton University Press.
go back to reference Aroney, N. (2014). “Subsidiarity in the Writings of Aristotle and Aquinas”. In: M. Evans and A. Zimmermann (eds.) Global Perspectives on Subsidiarity. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 9–27.CrossRef Aroney, N. (2014). “Subsidiarity in the Writings of Aristotle and Aquinas”. In: M. Evans and A. Zimmermann (eds.) Global Perspectives on Subsidiarity. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 9–27.CrossRef
go back to reference Barker, E. (1959). The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle. New York: Dover Publications. Barker, E. (1959). The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle. New York: Dover Publications.
go back to reference Duke, G. (2020). Aristotle and Law: The Politics of Nomos. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Duke, G. (2020). Aristotle and Law: The Politics of Nomos. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Elder-Vass, D. (2010). The Causal Power of Social Structures. Emergence, Structure and Agency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Elder-Vass, D. (2010). The Causal Power of Social Structures. Emergence, Structure and Agency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Elder-Vass, D. (2014). “Social Entities and the Basis of Their Power”. In: J. Zahle and F. Collin (eds.) Rethinking the Individualism-Holism Debate. Essays in the Philosophy of Social Science. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 39–54. Elder-Vass, D. (2014). “Social Entities and the Basis of Their Power”. In: J. Zahle and F. Collin (eds.) Rethinking the Individualism-Holism Debate. Essays in the Philosophy of Social Science. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 39–54.
go back to reference Elder-Vass, D. (2017). “Material Parts in Social Structures”, Journal of Social Ontology 3/1, pp. 1–17.CrossRef Elder-Vass, D. (2017). “Material Parts in Social Structures”, Journal of Social Ontology 3/1, pp. 1–17.CrossRef
go back to reference Epstein, B. (2015). The Ant Trap: Rebuilding the Foundations of the Social Sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Epstein, B. (2015). The Ant Trap: Rebuilding the Foundations of the Social Sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Gallagher, R. L. (2011). “Aristotle on Eidei Diapherontoi”, British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19/3: 363–384.CrossRef Gallagher, R. L. (2011). “Aristotle on Eidei Diapherontoi”, British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19/3: 363–384.CrossRef
go back to reference Finnis, J. M. (1980). Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Finnis, J. M. (1980). Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
go back to reference Finnis, J. M. (1989). “Persons and Their Associations”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Suppl. Vol. LXIII, pp. 267–274. Finnis, J. M. (1989). “Persons and Their Associations”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Suppl. Vol. LXIII, pp. 267–274.
go back to reference Gilbert, M. (2001). “Collective Preferences, Obligations, and Rational Choice”, Economics and Philosophy 17: 109–119.CrossRef Gilbert, M. (2001). “Collective Preferences, Obligations, and Rational Choice”, Economics and Philosophy 17: 109–119.CrossRef
go back to reference Gilbert, M. (2006). A Theory of Political Obligation: Membership, Commitment, and the Bonds of Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Gilbert, M. (2006). A Theory of Political Obligation: Membership, Commitment, and the Bonds of Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Gilbert, M. (2014). Joint Commitment: How We Make the Social World. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gilbert, M. (2014). Joint Commitment: How We Make the Social World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Guala, F. (2016a). “Philosophy of the Social Sciences: Naturalism and Anti-naturalism”. In: P. Humphreys (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Science. Oxford University Press, pp. 43–64. Guala, F. (2016a). “Philosophy of the Social Sciences: Naturalism and Anti-naturalism”. In: P. Humphreys (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Science. Oxford University Press, pp. 43–64.
go back to reference Guala, F. (2016b). Understanding Institutions: The Science and Philosophy of Living Together. Princeton University Press: Princeton.CrossRef Guala, F. (2016b). Understanding Institutions: The Science and Philosophy of Living Together. Princeton University Press: Princeton.CrossRef
go back to reference Hindriks, F. (2005). Rules & Institutions: Essays on Meaning, Speech Acts and Social Ontology. Doctoral Thesis, Erasmus Universiteit Rotterdam. Amsterdam: Kloof Booksellers & Scientia Verlag. Hindriks, F. (2005). Rules & Institutions: Essays on Meaning, Speech Acts and Social Ontology. Doctoral Thesis, Erasmus Universiteit Rotterdam. Amsterdam: Kloof Booksellers & Scientia Verlag.
go back to reference Hindriks, F. and F. Guala (2019). “The Functions of Institutions: Etiology and Teleology”, Synthese, online first. Hindriks, F. and F. Guala (2019). “The Functions of Institutions: Etiology and Teleology”, Synthese, online first.
go back to reference Honoré, T. (1987). Making Law Bind. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Honoré, T. (1987). Making Law Bind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
go back to reference Irwin, T. W. (1990). Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRef Irwin, T. W. (1990). Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Kraut, R. (2002). Aristotle: Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kraut, R. (2002). Aristotle: Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference List, C. and P. Pettit (2011). Group Agency: The Possibility, Design and Status of Corporate Agents. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef List, C. and P. Pettit (2011). Group Agency: The Possibility, Design and Status of Corporate Agents. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Lukes, S. (1968). “Methodological Individualism Reconsidered”, The British Journal of Sociology 19/2: 119–129.CrossRef Lukes, S. (1968). “Methodological Individualism Reconsidered”, The British Journal of Sociology 19/2: 119–129.CrossRef
go back to reference Mayhew, R. (1997). “Part and Whole in Aristotle’s Political Philosophy”, The Journal of Ethics 1/4: 325–340.CrossRef Mayhew, R. (1997). “Part and Whole in Aristotle’s Political Philosophy”, The Journal of Ethics 1/4: 325–340.CrossRef
go back to reference Miller, S. (2001). Social Action: A Teleological Account. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Miller, S. (2001). Social Action: A Teleological Account. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Miller, S. (2010). The Moral Foundations of Social Institutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Miller, S. (2010). The Moral Foundations of Social Institutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Papadopoulos, G. (2015). “Collective Intentionality and the State Theory of Money”, Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics, 8/2: 1–20.CrossRef Papadopoulos, G. (2015). “Collective Intentionality and the State Theory of Money”, Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics, 8/2: 1–20.CrossRef
go back to reference Pettit, P. (1996). The Common Mind: An Essay on Psychology, Society, and Politics. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pettit, P. (1996). The Common Mind: An Essay on Psychology, Society, and Politics. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Quinton, A. (1976). “Social Objects”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, 76 (1975–1976): 1–27+viii. Quinton, A. (1976). “Social Objects”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, 76 (1975–1976): 1–27+viii.
go back to reference Searle, J. R. (1995). The Construction of Social Reality. New York: Free Press. Searle, J. R. (1995). The Construction of Social Reality. New York: Free Press.
go back to reference Searle, J. R. (2005). “What is An institution?”, Journal of Institutional Economics 1/1: 1–22.CrossRef Searle, J. R. (2005). “What is An institution?”, Journal of Institutional Economics 1/1: 1–22.CrossRef
go back to reference Searle, J. R. (2006). “Social ontology: Some basic principles”, Anthropological Theory 6: 12–29.CrossRef Searle, J. R. (2006). “Social ontology: Some basic principles”, Anthropological Theory 6: 12–29.CrossRef
go back to reference Smit, J. P., F. Buekens and S. du Plessis (2011). “What Is Money? An Alternative to Searle’s Institutional Facts”, Economics and Philosophy 27: 1–22.CrossRef Smit, J. P., F. Buekens and S. du Plessis (2011). “What Is Money? An Alternative to Searle’s Institutional Facts”, Economics and Philosophy 27: 1–22.CrossRef
go back to reference Smith, A. (1976). The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Glasgow Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Smith, A. (1976). The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Glasgow Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Smith, B. and J. Searle (2003). “The Construction of Social Reality: An Exchange”, American Journal of Economics and Sociology 62: 285–309.CrossRef Smith, B. and J. Searle (2003). “The Construction of Social Reality: An Exchange”, American Journal of Economics and Sociology 62: 285–309.CrossRef
go back to reference Taylor, C. (1985). “Atomism”. In: Ch. Taylor (ed.) Philosophy and the Human Sciences. Philosophical papers 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 187–210. Taylor, C. (1985). “Atomism”. In: Ch. Taylor (ed.) Philosophy and the Human Sciences. Philosophical papers 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 187–210.
go back to reference Tollefsen, D. (2014). “Social Ontology”. In: N. Cartwright and E. Montuschi (eds.) Philosophy of Social Science: A New Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 85–101. Tollefsen, D. (2014). “Social Ontology”. In: N. Cartwright and E. Montuschi (eds.) Philosophy of Social Science: A New Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 85–101.
go back to reference Tollefsen, D. (2017). “Collective Intentionality and Methodology in the Social Sciences”. In: M. Jankovic and K. Ludwig (eds.) The Routledge Handbook of Collective Intentionality, pp. 389–401. Tollefsen, D. (2017). “Collective Intentionality and Methodology in the Social Sciences”. In: M. Jankovic and K. Ludwig (eds.) The Routledge Handbook of Collective Intentionality, pp. 389–401.
go back to reference Tuomela, R. (2013). Social Ontology. Collective Intentionality and Group Agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Tuomela, R. (2013). Social Ontology. Collective Intentionality and Group Agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Welleman, C. (1995). Real Rights. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press. Welleman, C. (1995). Real Rights. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Wiggins, D. (2001). Substance and Sameness Renewed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Wiggins, D. (2001). Substance and Sameness Renewed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Zahle, J. (2021). “Limits to levels in the methodological individualism–holism debate”, Synthese 198: 6435–6454.CrossRef Zahle, J. (2021). “Limits to levels in the methodological individualism–holism debate”, Synthese 198: 6435–6454.CrossRef
go back to reference Zanetti, G. (1993). La nozione di Giustizia in Aristotele. Bologna: Il Mulino. Zanetti, G. (1993). La nozione di Giustizia in Aristotele. Bologna: Il Mulino.
Metadata
Title
The Metaphysics of Social Collectives
Author
Ricardo F. Crespo
Copyright Year
2022
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-02453-5_7