Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Argumentation 2/2017

08-10-2016

Toulmin’s Logical Types

Author: David Botting

Published in: Argumentation | Issue 2/2017

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

In “The Uses of Argument” Toulmin introduces a number of concepts that have become popular in argumentation theory, such as data, claim, warrant, backing, force, field, and, most fundamentally, the concept of a “logical type”. Toulmin never defines the concept of a logical type or a field very clearly, and different interpretations can be found in the literature, either reconstructing what Toulmin has in mind, or revising his concepts to suit other concerns. A natural history of these concepts is not my concern. I will analyse logical types according to what Toulmin uses this concept for, namely to raise a problem with deductive logic and motivate its replacement with the Toulmin model. I will argue that a logical type and the distinction he draws between different logical types resembles distinctions made in logical positivism between the directly and the indirectly verifiable, and the problem raised is, in essence, the positivist’s problem of how indirect propositions can be justified on the basis of direct propositions. I will show that Toulmin makes a straw man of the positivists’ own solution to the problem and hence does not prove there to be an adequate motivation for replacing deductive logic with the Toulmin model.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
Is the selection of a player for the Davis Cup of the same logical type as a prediction that a particular player will be selected, and as the normative judgment that a particular player deserves to be selected? It is not clear. Our prediction of a selection may turn out to be false without it being any less true that the player deserved to be selected. There may be a confusion here about a prediction being true (fulfilled) and it being the right prediction to make. The facts adduced are equally adequate to its being the right prediction to make and the player deserving selection (except that for the prediction we must assume additionally that the selector is aiming at selecting the most deserving player, and has access to the same information we do). In this sense of being the correct prediction, then, there does not seem to be a difference in logical type between this and the normative judgment. Also, whether this is the correct prediction is a fact about the prediction and is true or false when the prediction is made and depends on the evidence available when the prediction is made, and only indirectly about the event predicted, which may in fact never come about.
 
2
Thus, “deductively valid” is not another way of saying “analytic” or vice versa, and some arguments that are not deductively valid are nonetheless analytic, on this meaning of ‘analytic.’ This distinction is itself fraught with problems that I do not intend to discuss here. For a discussion see Hamby (2012). There is one comment that I would like to make though: I think that we are supposed to read the procedure of checking subjunctively, that is to say, an argument is analytic if, were you to check the backing, you would ipso facto check the conclusion. It does not, then, cease to be analytic because you may have already checked the backing [as Hamby (2012) seems to suggest], for it is still the case that checking the backing would involve checking the conclusion. When Toulmin (1958, p. 117) says that even such an argument “may slip… into the substantial class” he is not saying that, because checking the backing may be in the past, what he has just given as an analytic argument is not really analytic at all; rather, he is saying that when backing involves facts about the past, the conclusion must also be about the past if the argument is to be analytic, and if it is about the present it is substantial. Toulmin does not say that it is a problem that the checking is in the past, but that the facts checked are in the past. Just as we can check what is true now (e.g., by looking) we can check what was true in the past (e.g., by consulting written records). The checking itself is always subjunctively construed.
So, an argument whose backing involves facts about the past is still analytic if the conclusion is about the past, but is not when the conclusion is about the present, because what we have been (or would be) checking is a fact about the past and not the present. Since facts about the past and facts about the present are of different logical types such an argument must be substantial for Toulmin. Toulmin (1958, p. 117) says that the conclusion of this substantial argument is a presumption that something is true now. The time at which the checking is carried out is irrelevant, and, in fact, it need not actually be carried out—we can tell that an argument is analytic without actually checking the backing but by seeing that checking the backing involves checking the conclusion on the basis of their semantic content.
 
3
It is true, though, that there is no formal test for absurdity. It is presumed that this is something we can just “see,” or can be made to see once analysis has unmasked “disguised nonsense,” to use Wittgenstein's phrase.
 
4
See Botting (2014) for further discussion of how this issue has generally been mangled in argumentation theory.
 
5
Phenomenalism is not the only possible response: the others are transcendentalism and scepticism.
 
6
On Ayer’s account, our justification for using it, or for using a principle of induction at all, is that it has worked in the past (Ayer 1946, p. 18), while Reichenbach (1938) sets out to prove the conditional that induction will lead to the truth if anything will. Toulmin’s own comments on the justification of induction at pp. 217–221 are rather puzzling. I suspect that he makes the equivocation mentioned in footnote 1 between making a true prediction and making a correct prediction. A prediction may be the correct one to make when one has gathered all the evidence currently available and drawn inferences from it in the correct way. But what we really want to know is whether our predictions reliably turn out to be true. If induction did not lead to truth then it would not be justified in the sense at issue. The same goes for warrants, I might add.
 
7
Interestingly, Reichenbach (1938, pp. 64–67) does provide a way of making sense of, e.g., theological claims, by using his idea of a coordinative definition. A claim, for example, that cats are divine, is coordinated to some property of cats that inspires awe in its worshippers. The theological term “divine” has empirical criteria of application, and every action that follows upon the belief that a particular cat is divine follows also on the belief that the cat has the coordinated empirical property. This seems to mean that we can reason from cats being divine, but does not mean that we can argue to it, that is to say, establish it as a conclusion. In other words, it does not show that cats are actually divine, which is what interests us here.
 
8
In particular, by concatenating our inductions. See Reichenbach (1938), and especially his discussion of the cubical world in §14 and §15 for a probabilistic justification of belief in the external world. Statements about the external world can be given a weight, and this independently of any single inductive argument for the statement, though dependently of inductive arguments as a whole.
 
9
This can be seen in Reichenbach, where in the end it seems to be because it is not possible not to act—we must act and consequently must take our best wager as the basis of our action—that induction is vindicated. Since the action that follows on our best wager is the same as what would follow if we knew the proposition to be true, we can even co-ordinate truth with our best wager.
 
Literature
go back to reference Ayer, A.J. 1936. Language, truth and logic, 2nd ed. London: Gollancz. Ayer, A.J. 1936. Language, truth and logic, 2nd ed. London: Gollancz.
go back to reference Castañeda, H.N. 1960. On a proposed revolution in logic. Philosophy of Science 27(3): 279–292.CrossRef Castañeda, H.N. 1960. On a proposed revolution in logic. Philosophy of Science 27(3): 279–292.CrossRef
go back to reference van Eemeren, F.H., R. Grootendorst, F.S. Snoeck Henkemans, et al. 2009. Fundamentals of argumentation theory. New York and London: Routledge. van Eemeren, F.H., R. Grootendorst, F.S. Snoeck Henkemans, et al. 2009. Fundamentals of argumentation theory. New York and London: Routledge.
go back to reference Hamby, B. 2012. Toulmin’s “analytic argument”. Informal Logic 32(1): 116–131.CrossRef Hamby, B. 2012. Toulmin’s “analytic argument”. Informal Logic 32(1): 116–131.CrossRef
go back to reference Hempel, C.G., and P. Oppenheim. 1948. Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science 15(2): 135–175.CrossRef Hempel, C.G., and P. Oppenheim. 1948. Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science 15(2): 135–175.CrossRef
go back to reference Holth, P. 2001. The persistence of category mistakes in psychology. Behavior and Philosophy 29: 203–219. Holth, P. 2001. The persistence of category mistakes in psychology. Behavior and Philosophy 29: 203–219.
go back to reference von Mises, R. 1956. Positivism: A Study in Human Understanding. U.S.A: G. Braziller. von Mises, R. 1956. Positivism: A Study in Human Understanding. U.S.A: G. Braziller.
go back to reference Reichenbach, H. 1938. Experience and prediction. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Reichenbach, H. 1938. Experience and prediction. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
go back to reference Ryle, G. 1938. Categories. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 38: 189–206.CrossRef Ryle, G. 1938. Categories. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 38: 189–206.CrossRef
go back to reference Salmon, W. 1981. Rational prediction. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32(2): 115–125.CrossRef Salmon, W. 1981. Rational prediction. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32(2): 115–125.CrossRef
go back to reference Toulmin, S.E. 1958. The uses of argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Toulmin, S.E. 1958. The uses of argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Metadata
Title
Toulmin’s Logical Types
Author
David Botting
Publication date
08-10-2016
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Argumentation / Issue 2/2017
Print ISSN: 0920-427X
Electronic ISSN: 1572-8374
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-016-9414-6

Other articles of this Issue 2/2017

Argumentation 2/2017 Go to the issue