Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Social Choice and Welfare 1/2021

18-06-2020 | Original Paper

Neutral freedom and freedom as control

Author: Itai Sher

Published in: Social Choice and Welfare | Issue 1/2021

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

I present a model of freedom as control. Control is measured by the preferences of a decision-maker, or judge, who values flexibility and is neutral towards outcomes ex ante. Formally, I explore the consequences of adding a neutrality axiom to the Dekel et al. (Econometrica 69(4):891–934, 2001) axioms for preference for flexibility. I characterize the consensus of all neutral judges about which choice situations embody more freedom. The theory extends the freedom ranking literature to situations where agents have imperfect control, as modeled by choices among lotteries. In a voting context, the consensus of neutral judges coincides with Banzhaf power.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Appendix
Available only for authorised users
Footnotes
1
To say that we should be neutral about the value of alternatives is not to say that no value judgments are involved. See Sect. 3.3. Neutrality is conditioned on certain normative presuppositions.
 
2
In his work on measuring freedom, Carter (1999) emphasizes the distinction between the value of specific freedoms and value of overall freedom, and proposes a measure of overall freedom that abstracts from the values of specific freedoms.
 
3
Sen (1985, 1991) also discussed the relation of freedom to flexibility.
 
4
This is an exaggeration.
 
5
The version of the axioms I present here are slightly different than that presented in Dekel et al. (2001). The monotonicity axiom is the same as in Dekel et al. (2001), but the continuity and independence axioms differ. The independence axiom of Dekel et al. (2001) differs in that (1) it is formulated with respect to strict preference and (2) it contains only the \(\Rightarrow\) direction of Axiom 4 below. In conjunction, the axioms presented here characterize the same preferences as the axioms in Dekel et al. (2001). The reason for the difference is that my main result, Theorem 1, appeals to a representation theorem for preference for flexibility with incomplete preferences due to Kochov (2007) and Galaabaatar (2010), and so I use the versions of independence and monotonicity used in those papers. The differences only matter when preferences are incomplete.
 
6
The formulation of the axiom is different than in Dekel et al. (2001). See footnote 6.
 
7
The theorem continues to hold despite the slightly different formulation of the axioms. See footnote 6.
 
8
The representation (3) is not unique—multiple probability measures p correspond to the same preferences \(\preccurlyeq\). Dekel et al. (2001) restrict attention to a subset of utility functions U satisfying certain normalizations and thereby attain a unique representation. Uniqueness is not important for my purposes.
 
9
This example previously appeared in Sher (2018a).
 
10
I mention this last fact just to emphasize that in Scenarios A and B below, if the agent goes to prison, it will be the same prison in both scenarios.
 
11
In this example we identify the options c and s with the degenerate lotteries that put probability one on each of these two options.
 
12
It is not entirely obvious because one might say that both menus allow no freedom, and so are equivalent in that sense. A counterargument would be that bliss is much more choiceworthy than suffering; there are many more situations in which an agent would or should choose bliss rather than suffering if given the choice. Moreover, even if one accepts that the singleton menus \(\left\{ \textit{suffering}\right\}\) and \(\left\{ \textit{bliss}\right\}\) are equivalent in terms of freedom in that they allow no freedom, one might not accept the stronger implication of neutrality that it is equivalent in terms of freedom to interchange suffering and bliss in every menu. In arguing against the cardinality order of Pattanaik and Xu (1990), Sen (1990) argues similarly that the choiceworthiness of alternatives is relevant to the freedom allowed by a menu.
 
13
Sher (2015) is an earlier working paper version of the current paper. The weakenings of the neutrality axiom can be found in Sect. 6 of that version. The paper can be found at https://​drive.​google.​com/​file/​d/​18ORLZcVTlKnGHYy​nSNLvGkkfYmoRJkG​Q/​view?​usp=​sharing.
 
14
Nehring and Puppe (2008) also applies the attribute approach to freedom of choice.
 
15
Sher (2018a) does not explicitly consider applying neutrality within each category of freedom; the paper focuses rather on assigning different values to different freedoms (either in the same or in different categories). The approach would however be consistent with applying neutrality within categories.
 
16
For example, consider the 27 possible ways of assigning the utilities \(-1,0,\) and 2 to the different candidates allowing that different candidates may be assigned the same utility. If each of these 27 assignments is viewed as equiprobable, that would amount to a different situation of symmetric uncertainty.
 
17
For the formal definition of what it means to take a weighted average of menus, see (2) in Sect. 2.2, and the discussion surrounding (2).
 
18
Let us consider two particular neutral judges who disagree about these two menus. When neutral judge 1’s specific preferences are realized, judge 1 assigns utility 1 to one alternative and utility 0 to the other two alternatives. For each of the three alternatives, there is a \(\frac{1}{3}\) probability that judge 1 will assign utility 1 to that alterntative. When neutral judge 2’s specific preferences are realized, judge 2 assigns utility 0 to one alternative and utility 1 to the other two alternatives. For each of the three alternatives, there is a \(\frac{1}{3}\) probability that neutral judge 2 will assign utility 0 to that alternative. Judge 1 attains an expected utility of \(\frac{2}{3}\) from having access to \(M_1\) and an expected utility of \(\frac{7}{9}\) from having access to \(M_2\). So judge 1 prefers \(M_2\). Judge 2 attains an expected utility of 1 from having access to \(M_1\) and an expected utility of \(\frac{8}{9}\) from having access to \(M_2\). So judge 2 prefers \(M_1\). Judge 1 and judge 2 disagree.
 
19
See in particular Sect. 3.2 and Corollary 1.
 
20
The repetitions occur because each of the two lotteries contain only two distinct probabilities—in this case 0 and 1. If one of the two lotteries contained three distinct probabilities, as in the menu \(M=\left\{ \left( 1,0,0\right) ,\left( \frac{1}{2},\frac{1}{3},\frac{1}{6}\right) \right\}\), there would be no repetitions.
 
21
Some red points on the right hand side can be arrived at in multiple ways. This is a general feature which is not particular to the menu in this example because for any menu M and all \(\ell \in M\), \(\frac{1}{n!} \sum _{\pi \in \Pi } \ell ^\pi = \left( \frac{1}{n},\frac{1}{n},\ldots ,\frac{1}{n}\right)\).
 
22
It follows that if one rejects some comparison made by the symmetry order, one must reject one of the axioms characterizing freedom.
 
23
The symmetry order is referred to as the grading order in Sher (2015).
 
24
The cardinality order ranks one deterministic menu above another if and only if the former contains more elements.
 
25
A preorder \(\preccurlyeq\) is a reflexive and transitive relation.
 
26
A preorder \(\preccurlyeq _0\) is coarser than a preorder \(\preccurlyeq _1\) if for all \(M,M' \in {\mathscr {M}}, M' \preccurlyeq _0 M \Rightarrow M' \preccurlyeq _1 M\).
 
27
For example, if \(M_2\) contains two lotteries and \(M_3\) contains three lotteries, but the convex hull of \(M_3\) is a proper subset of the convex hull of \(M_2\), then \(M_2\) allows more freedom than \(M_3\) according to the symmetry order.
 
28
\(z \le z'\) means that for all i, \(z_i \le z'_i\).
 
29
In the case that the voting mechanism is deterministic (i.e., \(\alpha (z) \in \{0,1\}, \forall z\)) , it is obvious that (9) represents the probability of being pivotal. In the Appendix, I explain why we can also regard (9) as the probability of being pivotal in stochastic mechanisms.
 
30
In Sher (2018a), I present a general framework for evaluating freedom in games.
 
31
In this paper, I have assumed that a menu is a closed set of lotteries over alternatives. In (12), I allow all subsets of \(\left[ 0,1\right]\). If I had here restricted to closed subsets of \(\left[ 0,1\right]\), the \(\sup\) in (12) could be replaced by \(\max\).
 
32
The critical thing here is not the menus contain two lotteries, but rather that the lotteries in the menus are over two outcomes.
 
33
Strictly speaking the condition is that all expected utility maximizers prefer P to Q given any prior beliefs.
 
34
Since the preordered flexibility axioms imply that a menu is indifferent to its convex hull, nothing substantive would change if we substituted the set of randomized strategies for the set of pure strategies \(\Sigma\) used in the above construction.
 
35
See Sect. 6.
 
36
Specifically, only the \(\Leftarrow\) direction employs the separating hyperplane theorem. If \(S\left( M\right) \not \subseteq S\left( M'\right)\), then there exists \(\ell \in S\left( M\right) {\setminus } S\left( M'\right)\), and then the strong separating hyperplane theorem implies that \(\ell\) and \(G(M')\) can be strongly separated.
 
37
It is straightforward to confirm that when \(p^\pi\) is defined in this way, then \(p^\pi\) indeed belongs to \(\Delta ^*\left( U\right)\).
 
Literature
go back to reference Arrow KJ (1995) A note on freedom and flexibility. Choice, welfare and development: a festschrift in honour of Amartya K. Sen, 7–15 Arrow KJ (1995) A note on freedom and flexibility. Choice, welfare and development: a festschrift in honour of Amartya K. Sen, 7–15
go back to reference Banzhaf JF (1964) Weighted voting doesn’t work: a mathematical analysis. Rutgers Law Rev 19:317–343 Banzhaf JF (1964) Weighted voting doesn’t work: a mathematical analysis. Rutgers Law Rev 19:317–343
go back to reference Banzhaf JF (1968) One man, 3.312 votes: a mathematical analysis of the electoral college. Villanova Law Rev 13:304–332 Banzhaf JF (1968) One man, 3.312 votes: a mathematical analysis of the electoral college. Villanova Law Rev 13:304–332
go back to reference Barbera S, Bossert W, Pattanaik PK (2004) Ranking sets of objects. In: Barbera S, Hammond P, Seidl C (eds) Handbook of utility theory, vol 2. Springer, Berlin, pp 893–977CrossRef Barbera S, Bossert W, Pattanaik PK (2004) Ranking sets of objects. In: Barbera S, Hammond P, Seidl C (eds) Handbook of utility theory, vol 2. Springer, Berlin, pp 893–977CrossRef
go back to reference Blackwell D (1951) Comparison of experiments. In: Neyman J (ed) Proceedings of the second Berkeley symposium on mathematical statistics and probability. University of California Press, California, pp 93–102 Blackwell D (1951) Comparison of experiments. In: Neyman J (ed) Proceedings of the second Berkeley symposium on mathematical statistics and probability. University of California Press, California, pp 93–102
go back to reference Blackwell D (1953) Equivalent comparisons of experiments. Ann Math Stat 24:265–272CrossRef Blackwell D (1953) Equivalent comparisons of experiments. Ann Math Stat 24:265–272CrossRef
go back to reference Dekel E, Lipman BL, Rustichini A (2001) Representing preferences with a unique subjective state space. Econometrica 69(4):891–934CrossRef Dekel E, Lipman BL, Rustichini A (2001) Representing preferences with a unique subjective state space. Econometrica 69(4):891–934CrossRef
go back to reference Dubey P, Shapley LS (1979) Mathematical properties of the Banzhaf power index. Math Oper Res 4(2):99–131CrossRef Dubey P, Shapley LS (1979) Mathematical properties of the Banzhaf power index. Math Oper Res 4(2):99–131CrossRef
go back to reference Felsenthal D, Machover M (1998) The measurement of voting power. Edward Elgar, UKCrossRef Felsenthal D, Machover M (1998) The measurement of voting power. Edward Elgar, UKCrossRef
go back to reference Galaabaatar T (2010) Menu choice without completeness. Unpublished manuscript Galaabaatar T (2010) Menu choice without completeness. Unpublished manuscript
go back to reference Kochov A (2007) Subjective states without the completeness axiom. Unpublished Manuscript, University of Rochester Kochov A (2007) Subjective states without the completeness axiom. Unpublished Manuscript, University of Rochester
go back to reference Kreps DM (1979) A representation theorem for “preference for flexibility”. Econometrica 47:565–577CrossRef Kreps DM (1979) A representation theorem for “preference for flexibility”. Econometrica 47:565–577CrossRef
go back to reference Nehring K (1999) Preference for flexibility in a Savage framework. Econometrica 67(1):101–119CrossRef Nehring K (1999) Preference for flexibility in a Savage framework. Econometrica 67(1):101–119CrossRef
go back to reference Nehring K, Puppe C (2002) A theory of diversity. Econometrica 70(3):1155–1198CrossRef Nehring K, Puppe C (2002) A theory of diversity. Econometrica 70(3):1155–1198CrossRef
go back to reference Nehring K, Puppe C (2008) Diversity and the metric of opportunity. Working paper Nehring K, Puppe C (2008) Diversity and the metric of opportunity. Working paper
go back to reference Pattanaik PK, Xu Y (1990) On ranking opportunity sets in terms of freedom of choice. Recherches Économiques de Louvain/Louvain Econ Rev 56(3–4):383–390 Pattanaik PK, Xu Y (1990) On ranking opportunity sets in terms of freedom of choice. Recherches Économiques de Louvain/Louvain Econ Rev 56(3–4):383–390
go back to reference Pattanaik PK, Xu Y (1998) On preference and freedom. Theor Decis 44(2):173–198CrossRef Pattanaik PK, Xu Y (1998) On preference and freedom. Theor Decis 44(2):173–198CrossRef
go back to reference Sen A (1985) Commodities and capabilities. North-Holland Sen A (1985) Commodities and capabilities. North-Holland
go back to reference Sen A (1990) Welfare, freedom and social choice: a reply. Recherches Économiques de Louvain/Louvain Econ Rev 56(3–4):451–485 Sen A (1990) Welfare, freedom and social choice: a reply. Recherches Économiques de Louvain/Louvain Econ Rev 56(3–4):451–485
go back to reference Sen A (1993) Markets and freedoms: achievements and limitations of the market mechanism in promoting individual freedoms. Oxford Economic Papers, pp 519–541 Sen A (1993) Markets and freedoms: achievements and limitations of the market mechanism in promoting individual freedoms. Oxford Economic Papers, pp 519–541
go back to reference Sher I (2018a) Evaluating allocations of freedom. Econ J 128(612):F65–F94CrossRef Sher I (2018a) Evaluating allocations of freedom. Econ J 128(612):F65–F94CrossRef
Metadata
Title
Neutral freedom and freedom as control
Author
Itai Sher
Publication date
18-06-2020
Publisher
Springer Berlin Heidelberg
Published in
Social Choice and Welfare / Issue 1/2021
Print ISSN: 0176-1714
Electronic ISSN: 1432-217X
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-020-01267-x

Other articles of this Issue 1/2021

Social Choice and Welfare 1/2021 Go to the issue