Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Social Choice and Welfare 2-3/2005

01-12-2005 | Original Paper

The news of the death of welfare economics is greatly exaggerated

Authors: Marc Fleurbaey, Philippe Mongin

Published in: Social Choice and Welfare | Issue 2-3/2005

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

The paper reexamines the controversy about Bergson–Samuelson social welfare functions (BSFs) that took place between welfare economists and social choice theorists as a consequence of Arrow’s (1951) impossibility theorem. The 1970’s witnessed a new version of the theorem that was meant to establish that BSFs “make interpersonal comparisons of utility or are dictatorial.” Against this, Samuelson reasserted the existence of well-behaved “ordinalist” BSFs and generally denied the relevance of Arrovian impossibilities to welfare economics. The paper formalizes and reassesses each camp’s arguments. While being also critical of Samuelson’s, it eventually endorses his conclusion that welfare economics was left untouched by the controversy. It draws some connections of BSFs with contemporary normative economics.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
On the Compensation Principle, see Chipman and Moore (1978). More recent investigations include Gravel (2001) and Suzumura (1999).
 
2
This statement is borrowed from Pollak (1979, p. 76). Parks (1976) has a different formulation in terms of utility values.
 
3
As a matter of attribution, it appears that Kemp and Ng on the one hand, Parks on the other worked independently and simultaneously, while Pollak was stimulated by the former’s work and did not initially know of the latter’s. The argument in Kemp and Ng involved an irrelevant topological framework, and had many loose ends. Pollak extracted the neat Theorem 2 from this jumble. Parks had already reached Theorem 2, but his paper is terse, and does not draw the connections with Theorem 1 in the same useful way as Pollak does.
 
4
Arrow (1963, ch. VI) initiated the study of economic domains in social choice theory, but full proofs had to await the 1980’s. For a survey, see Le Breton and Weymark (1996).
 
5
Turning May’s characterization into an Arrovian theorem, Sen (1970, p. 73) proves that no F can satisfy the universal domain condition, neutrality, positive responsiveness (an interprofile condition which is related to (WP)), and anonymity (which is a strong denial of (D)). This may be the first impossibility theorem involving neutrality in its premisses.
 
6
Blackorby et al. (1984) diagrammatic analysis of social choice uses a similar argument. See also Blackorby et al. (1990).
 
7
It is not always the case that the maximal domain should be selected when there is no reason to select any particular domain. For a discussion in the context of choice functions, see Sen (1971, 1982, p. 48–49) and Mongin (2000, p. 92–93).
 
8
Sadly, Little’s (1999, p. 17–18) late retraction does not show that he has taken advantage of the intervening clarifications.
 
9
See also Samuelson’s rebuttal of Lange and Fisher: “Lange, Fisher, and others have contended that measurable utility, while superfluous from the standpoint of positivistic behavioristic description, is necessary for the purpose of a normative science of welfare economics... It is well to point out that this is not at all necessary” (1947, p. 173).
 
10
A function \(U_{i} \in \mathbb{R}^{X}\) represents R i on X if, for all x, yX, xR i y iff U i (x)≥U i (y). The vector-valued function \(U = {\left( {U_{i} } \right)}_{{i \in N}}\) is said to represent \({\left( {R_{i} } \right)}_{{i \in N}}\) when U i represents R i for each i.
 
11
This formula can be found in Arrow’s comment of Samuelson (1983, p. 22).
 
12
Compare this statement with Pazner and Schmeidler (1978, p. 679).
 
13
We read no further advance in Bergson’s (1976) latest retrospective paper.
 
14
This text was regarded by Samuelson as an authoritative restatement of the new welfare economics; see his preface.
 
15
The proof of Theorems 1 f and 2 f from Theorems 1 and 2 uses the fact that the latter remain true when \({\user1{\mathcal{D}}}^{F}\) is restricted to the set of those orderings on X which can be represented by a utility function. Fishburn (1970, p. 27–28) states that there exists U i representing R i if and only if P i is order-dense on the quotient of X by the indifference relation I i .
 
16
Interestingly, Hammond (1976) derives (UN) f from (UI) f and a weaker form of neutrality. He proves a variant of Theorem 4 stated below.
 
17
We choose this particular condition because it is simple and can be satisfied on economic domains. Bordes et al. (1996) investigate more basic conditions, and so does Weymark (1998).
 
18
It is well-known that on relevant economic domains, (PI) f follows from (WP) f and a continuity condition (see, e.g., Suzumura, 2001).
 
19
Compare this technical analysis with Roberts’ (1980) and d’Aspremont’s (1985). In ways slightly different from ours, they tighten the links between Arrow’s multi-profile theorem and his followers’ single-profile version.
 
20
Blackorby et al. (1990, p. 283) reach a similar conclusion.
 
21
For clarity of Fig. 4, the two pairs of allocations (x, y) and (z, w) use different amounts of resources, but it is easy to adapt the example to a case without free disposal.
 
22
Similarly, consider again the economic example of the distribution of Ω among n individuals. Suppose alternatives are redescribed in this way:
$$\widehat{x} = {\left( {x_{1} , \ldots ,x_{n} ,\Omega ,U_{1} * {\left( {x_{1} } \right)}, \ldots ,U_{n} * {\left( {x_{n} } \right)}} \right)}.$$
If one believes that E* is the proper ethical criterion for this example, then one must admit that \(\widehat{x}\) contains all the relevant information. But it still holds that individual i weakly prefers \(\widehat{x}\) to \(\widehat{y}\) if and only if x i R i y i . Therefore (I) applied to individual preferences over \(\widehat{x}\), \(\widehat{y}\) is just the same as (I) applied to the initial x, y, and is just as restrictive and questionable.
 
23
See, e.g.:“I shall argue that the Arrow result is much more of a contribution to the infant discipline of mathematical politics than to the traditional mathematical theory of welfare economics” (Samuelson 1967, p. 168).
 
24
Samuelson is justified in attributing to Bergson a rejection of independence. However, Bergson’s (1954, p. 244–245; see also 1966, p. 75–76) criticism relied on the concept of need, and virtually ignored the point that Samuelson is making here, i.e., that individual preferences about third allocations are relevant in the evaluation of two allocations.
 
25
Pollak’s conclusion coincides with Samuelson’s, but the main argument he provides is oddly the ineffective Bergsonian one “that the Bergson–Samuelson social welfare function reflects the judgments of an ethical observer” (1979, p. 86).
 
26
In a stronger version called “independence of irrelevant preferences”, Mayston requires only the intersection of B i (x, y) with a reference path Z crossing all indifference curves to be the same in \({\overrightarrow{R}}\) and \({\overrightarrow{{R^{\prime } }}} \).
 
27
Similarly, Fleurbaey and Maniquet (1996) were not aware of either Hansson, Mayston or Pazner when they proposed in their turn to weaken the independence condition.
 
28
See Mongin (1999, 2002).
 
29
Witness this remarkable statement: “I now feel... that the austerity imposed by this condition is stricter than desirable; in many situations we do have information on preferences for nonfeasible alternatives. It can certainly be argued that when available this information should be used in social choice... The potential usefulness of irrelevant alternatives is that they may permit empirically meaningful interpersonal comparisons” (Arrow 1967, p. 19, our emphasis).
 
30
Studies of tax issues in Fleurbaey and Maniquet (2002a,b) and Fleurbaey (2005) exemplify both this kind of heuristics and some of its preliminary results.
 
Literature
go back to reference Arrow KJ (1963) Social choice and individual values. Wiley, New York (2nd revised ed.; 1st ed. 1951) Arrow KJ (1963) Social choice and individual values. Wiley, New York (2nd revised ed.; 1st ed. 1951)
go back to reference Arrow KJ (1967) Public and private values. In: Hook S (ed) Human values and economic policy. New York University Press, New York Arrow KJ (1967) Public and private values. In: Hook S (ed) Human values and economic policy. New York University Press, New York
go back to reference Arrow KJ (1983) Contributions to welfare economics. In: Brown EC, Solow RM (eds) Paul Samuelson and modern economic theory. McGraw-Hill, New York Arrow KJ (1983) Contributions to welfare economics. In: Brown EC, Solow RM (eds) Paul Samuelson and modern economic theory. McGraw-Hill, New York
go back to reference Atkinson A (2001) The strange disappearance of welfare economics. Kyklos 54:193–206 Atkinson A (2001) The strange disappearance of welfare economics. Kyklos 54:193–206
go back to reference Bergson (Burk) A (1938) A reformulation of certain aspects of welfare economics. Q J Econ 52:310–334 Bergson (Burk) A (1938) A reformulation of certain aspects of welfare economics. Q J Econ 52:310–334
go back to reference Bergson A (1954) On the concept of social welfare. Q J Econ 68:233–252 Bergson A (1954) On the concept of social welfare. Q J Econ 68:233–252
go back to reference Bergson A (1966) Essays in normative economics. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Bergson A (1966) Essays in normative economics. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA
go back to reference Bergson A (1976) Social choice and welfare economics under representative government. J Public Econ 6:171–190CrossRef Bergson A (1976) Social choice and welfare economics under representative government. J Public Econ 6:171–190CrossRef
go back to reference Blackorby C, Donaldson D, Weymark J (1984) Social choice theory with interpersonal utility comparisons: a diagrammatic introduction. Int Econ Rev 25:327–356 Blackorby C, Donaldson D, Weymark J (1984) Social choice theory with interpersonal utility comparisons: a diagrammatic introduction. Int Econ Rev 25:327–356
go back to reference Blackorby C, Donaldson D, Weymark J (1990) A welfarist proof of Arrow’ theorem. Rech Econ Louvain 56:259–286 Blackorby C, Donaldson D, Weymark J (1990) A welfarist proof of Arrow’ theorem. Rech Econ Louvain 56:259–286
go back to reference Bordes G, Hammond PJ, Le Breton M (1996) Social welfare functionals on restricted domains and in economic environments, mimeo, Stanford University Bordes G, Hammond PJ, Le Breton M (1996) Social welfare functionals on restricted domains and in economic environments, mimeo, Stanford University
go back to reference Chipman JS, Moore JC (1978) The new welfare economics, 1939–1974. Int Econ Rev 19:547–584 Chipman JS, Moore JC (1978) The new welfare economics, 1939–1974. Int Econ Rev 19:547–584
go back to reference d’Aspremont C (1985) Axioms for social welfare orderings. In: Hurwicz L, Schmeidler D, Sonnenschein H (eds) Social goals and social organization. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge d’Aspremont C (1985) Axioms for social welfare orderings. In: Hurwicz L, Schmeidler D, Sonnenschein H (eds) Social goals and social organization. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
go back to reference Deaton AS, Muellbauer J (1980) Economics and consumer behaviour. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Deaton AS, Muellbauer J (1980) Economics and consumer behaviour. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
go back to reference de Van Graaf J (1957) Theoretical welfare economics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge de Van Graaf J (1957) Theoretical welfare economics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
go back to reference Fishburn PC (1970) Utility theory for decision making. Wiley, New York Fishburn PC (1970) Utility theory for decision making. Wiley, New York
go back to reference Fishburn PC (1973) The theory of social choice. Princeton University Press, Princeton Fishburn PC (1973) The theory of social choice. Princeton University Press, Princeton
go back to reference Fleurbaey M (2003) On the informational basis of social choice. Soc Choice Welf 21:347–384CrossRef Fleurbaey M (2003) On the informational basis of social choice. Soc Choice Welf 21:347–384CrossRef
go back to reference Fleurbaey M (2005) Health, wealth and fairness. J Public Econ Theory 7:253–284CrossRef Fleurbaey M (2005) Health, wealth and fairness. J Public Econ Theory 7:253–284CrossRef
go back to reference Fleurbaey M, Hammond PJ (2004) Interpersonally comparable utility. In: Barbera S, Hammond PJ, Seidl C (eds) Handbook of utility theory, vol. 2: extensions. Kluwer, Boston Fleurbaey M, Hammond PJ (2004) Interpersonally comparable utility. In: Barbera S, Hammond PJ, Seidl C (eds) Handbook of utility theory, vol. 2: extensions. Kluwer, Boston
go back to reference Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (1996) Utilitarianism versus fairness in welfare economics, forthcoming. In: Salles M, Weymark JA (eds) Justice, political liberalism and utilitarianism: themes from Harsanyi and Rawls. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (1996) Utilitarianism versus fairness in welfare economics, forthcoming. In: Salles M, Weymark JA (eds) Justice, political liberalism and utilitarianism: themes from Harsanyi and Rawls. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
go back to reference Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (2001) Fair social orderings, mimeo, U. of Pau and U. of Namur Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (2001) Fair social orderings, mimeo, U. of Pau and U. of Namur
go back to reference Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (2002a) Help the low-skilled or let the hard-working thrive? A study of fairness in income taxation, mimeo, U. of Pau and U. of Namur Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (2002a) Help the low-skilled or let the hard-working thrive? A study of fairness in income taxation, mimeo, U. of Pau and U. of Namur
go back to reference Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (2002b) Fair income tax, forthcoming in Rev Econ Studies Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (2002b) Fair income tax, forthcoming in Rev Econ Studies
go back to reference Gravel N (2001) On the difficulty of combining actual and potential criteria for an increase in social welfare. Econ Theory 17:163–180 Gravel N (2001) On the difficulty of combining actual and potential criteria for an increase in social welfare. Econ Theory 17:163–180
go back to reference Hammond PJ (1976) Why ethical measures of inequality need interpersonal comparisons. Theory Dec 7:263–274CrossRef Hammond PJ (1976) Why ethical measures of inequality need interpersonal comparisons. Theory Dec 7:263–274CrossRef
go back to reference Hansson B (1973) The independence condition in the theory of social choice. Theory Decis 4:25–49CrossRef Hansson B (1973) The independence condition in the theory of social choice. Theory Decis 4:25–49CrossRef
go back to reference Kemp MC, Ng YK (1976) On the existence of social welfare functions, social orderings and social decision functions. Economica 43:59–66 Kemp MC, Ng YK (1976) On the existence of social welfare functions, social orderings and social decision functions. Economica 43:59–66
go back to reference Kemp MC, Ng YK (1977) More on social welfare functions: the incompatibility of individualism and ordinalism. Economica 44:89–90 Kemp MC, Ng YK (1977) More on social welfare functions: the incompatibility of individualism and ordinalism. Economica 44:89–90
go back to reference Kemp MC, Ng YK (1982) The incompatibility of individualism and ordinalism. Math Soc Sci 3:33–37CrossRef Kemp MC, Ng YK (1982) The incompatibility of individualism and ordinalism. Math Soc Sci 3:33–37CrossRef
go back to reference Kemp MC, Ng YK (1983) Individualistic social welfare functions under ordinalism: a reply to Mayston. Math Soc Sci 4:305–307CrossRef Kemp MC, Ng YK (1983) Individualistic social welfare functions under ordinalism: a reply to Mayston. Math Soc Sci 4:305–307CrossRef
go back to reference Kemp MC, Ng YK (1987) Arrow’s independence condition and the Bergson–Samuelson tradition. In: Feiwel GE (ed) Arrow and the foundations of the theory of economic policy. New York University Press, New York Kemp MC, Ng YK (1987) Arrow’s independence condition and the Bergson–Samuelson tradition. In: Feiwel GE (ed) Arrow and the foundations of the theory of economic policy. New York University Press, New York
go back to reference Le Breton M, Weymark JA (1996) An introduction to Arrovian social welfare functions on economic and political domains. In: Schofield NJ (ed) Collective decision-making: social choice and political economy. Kluwer, Dordrecht Le Breton M, Weymark JA (1996) An introduction to Arrovian social welfare functions on economic and political domains. In: Schofield NJ (ed) Collective decision-making: social choice and political economy. Kluwer, Dordrecht
go back to reference Little IMD (1952) Social choice and individual values. J Polit Econ 60:422–432CrossRef Little IMD (1952) Social choice and individual values. J Polit Econ 60:422–432CrossRef
go back to reference Little IMD (1999) Collections and recollections: economic papers and their provenance. Clarendon Press, Oxford Little IMD (1999) Collections and recollections: economic papers and their provenance. Clarendon Press, Oxford
go back to reference May KO (1952) A set of independent necessary and sufficient conditions for simple majority decisions. Econometrica 20:680–684 May KO (1952) A set of independent necessary and sufficient conditions for simple majority decisions. Econometrica 20:680–684
go back to reference Mayston DJ (1974) The idea of social choice. Macmillan, London Mayston DJ (1974) The idea of social choice. Macmillan, London
go back to reference Mayston DJ (1979) Where did prescriptive welfare economics go wrong? In: Currie DA, Peters W (eds) Contemporary economic analysis, Proc. AUTE Conference, vol. 2. Croom Helm, London Mayston DJ (1979) Where did prescriptive welfare economics go wrong? In: Currie DA, Peters W (eds) Contemporary economic analysis, Proc. AUTE Conference, vol. 2. Croom Helm, London
go back to reference Mayston DJ (1982) The generation of a social welfare function under ordinal preferences. Math Soc Sci 3:109–129CrossRef Mayston DJ (1982) The generation of a social welfare function under ordinal preferences. Math Soc Sci 3:109–129CrossRef
go back to reference Mongin P (1999) Normes et jugements de valeur en économie normative. Soc Sci Inf 34:521–553 Mongin P (1999) Normes et jugements de valeur en économie normative. Soc Sci Inf 34:521–553
go back to reference Mongin P (2002) Is there progress in normative economics? In: Boehm S, Gehrke C, Kurz HD (eds) Is there progress in economics? Knowledge, truth and the history of economic thought. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham Mongin P (2002) Is there progress in normative economics? In: Boehm S, Gehrke C, Kurz HD (eds) Is there progress in economics? Knowledge, truth and the history of economic thought. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham
go back to reference Parks R (1976) An impossibility theorem for fixed preferences: a dictatorial Bergson–Samuelson welfare function. Rev Econ Stud 43:447–450 Parks R (1976) An impossibility theorem for fixed preferences: a dictatorial Bergson–Samuelson welfare function. Rev Econ Stud 43:447–450
go back to reference Pazner E (1979) Equity, nonfeasible alternatives and social choice: a reconsideration of the concept of social welfare. In: Laffont JJ (ed) Aggregation and revelation of preferences. North-Holland, Amsterdam Pazner E (1979) Equity, nonfeasible alternatives and social choice: a reconsideration of the concept of social welfare. In: Laffont JJ (ed) Aggregation and revelation of preferences. North-Holland, Amsterdam
go back to reference Pazner E, Schmeidler D (1978) Egalitarian equivalent allocations: a new concept of economic equity. Q J Econ 92:671–687 Pazner E, Schmeidler D (1978) Egalitarian equivalent allocations: a new concept of economic equity. Q J Econ 92:671–687
go back to reference Pollak RW (1979) Bergson–Samuelson socialWelfare functions and the theory of social choice. Q J Econ 93:73–90 Pollak RW (1979) Bergson–Samuelson socialWelfare functions and the theory of social choice. Q J Econ 93:73–90
go back to reference Roberts KWS (1980) Social choice theory: the single and multi-profile approaches. Rev Econ Stud 47:441–450 Roberts KWS (1980) Social choice theory: the single and multi-profile approaches. Rev Econ Stud 47:441–450
go back to reference Samuelson PA (1947) Foundations of economic analysis. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Samuelson PA (1947) Foundations of economic analysis. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA
go back to reference Samuelson PA (1967) Arrow’s mathematical politics. In Hook S (ed) Human values and economic policy. New York University Press, New York Samuelson PA (1967) Arrow’s mathematical politics. In Hook S (ed) Human values and economic policy. New York University Press, New York
go back to reference Samuelson PA (1977) Reaffirming the existence of ‘Reasonable’ Bergson–Samuelson social welfare functions. Economica 44:81–88 Samuelson PA (1977) Reaffirming the existence of ‘Reasonable’ Bergson–Samuelson social welfare functions. Economica 44:81–88
go back to reference Samuelson PA (1981) Bergsonian welfare economics. In: Rosefielde S (ed) Economic welfare and the economics of Soviet Socialism: essays in honor of Abram Bergson. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Samuelson PA (1981) Bergsonian welfare economics. In: Rosefielde S (ed) Economic welfare and the economics of Soviet Socialism: essays in honor of Abram Bergson. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
go back to reference Samuelson PA (1987) Sparks from Arrow’s Anvil. In: Feiwel GE (ed) Arrow and the foundations of the theory of economic policy. New York University Press, New York Samuelson PA (1987) Sparks from Arrow’s Anvil. In: Feiwel GE (ed) Arrow and the foundations of the theory of economic policy. New York University Press, New York
go back to reference Sen AK (1970) Collective choice and social welfare. Holden Day, San Francisco Sen AK (1970) Collective choice and social welfare. Holden Day, San Francisco
go back to reference Sen AK (1971) Choice functions and revealed preference. Rev Econ Stud 38:307–317 (reprinted in Sen (1982)) Sen AK (1971) Choice functions and revealed preference. Rev Econ Stud 38:307–317 (reprinted in Sen (1982))
go back to reference Sen AK (1972) Interpersonal aggregation and partial comparability. Econometrica 38:393–409 (reprinted in Sen (1982)) Sen AK (1972) Interpersonal aggregation and partial comparability. Econometrica 38:393–409 (reprinted in Sen (1982))
go back to reference Sen AK (1977) On weights and measures: informational constraints in social welfare analysis. Econometrica 45:1539–1572 (reprinted in Sen (1982)) Sen AK (1977) On weights and measures: informational constraints in social welfare analysis. Econometrica 45:1539–1572 (reprinted in Sen (1982))
go back to reference Sen AK (1982) Choice, welfare and measurement. Blackwell, Oxford Sen AK (1982) Choice, welfare and measurement. Blackwell, Oxford
go back to reference Sen AK (1986) Social choice theory. In: Arrow KJ, Intriligator MD (eds) Handbook of mathematical economics, vol. 3. North-Holland, Amsterdam Sen AK (1986) Social choice theory. In: Arrow KJ, Intriligator MD (eds) Handbook of mathematical economics, vol. 3. North-Holland, Amsterdam
go back to reference Suzumura K (1999) Paretian welfare judgments and Bergsonian social choice. Econ J 109:204–220CrossRef Suzumura K (1999) Paretian welfare judgments and Bergsonian social choice. Econ J 109:204–220CrossRef
Metadata
Title
The news of the death of welfare economics is greatly exaggerated
Authors
Marc Fleurbaey
Philippe Mongin
Publication date
01-12-2005
Publisher
Springer-Verlag
Published in
Social Choice and Welfare / Issue 2-3/2005
Print ISSN: 0176-1714
Electronic ISSN: 1432-217X
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-005-0010-1

Other articles of this Issue 2-3/2005

Social Choice and Welfare 2-3/2005 Go to the issue

Premium Partner