Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Human Studies 4/2013

01-12-2013 | Theoretical / Philosophical Paper

Tradition

Author: Yaacov Yadgar

Published in: Human Studies | Issue 4/2013

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Noting the prevalence of a misguided suspicion towards tradition, as well as an overt misunderstanding of the very notion of tradition in certain academic circles, this essay seeks to outline some of the basic tenets of an alternative understanding of tradition, based on a ‘sociological’ reading of several major philosophical works. It does so by revisiting and synthesizing some well-known, highly influential conceptual arguments that, taken together, offer a compelling, comprehensive interpretation and understanding of tradition, which manages to avoid and overcome the false dichotomies that have dominated social-scientific thought. The article offers three corresponding analogies that capture the complex nature of tradition: tradition as language, tradition as narrative, and tradition as horizon. It then goes on to discuss the main implications these analogies carry to our understanding of tradition.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
“To return to things themselves [i.e., phenomenology] is to return to that world which precedes knowledge, of which knowledge always speaks, and in relation to which every scientific schematization is an abstract and derivative sign-language, as is geography in relation to the country-side in which we have learnt beforehand what a forest, a prairie or a river is.
[Phenomenology] is absolutely distinct from the idealist return to consciousness, and the [phenomenological] demand for a pure description excludes equally the procedure of analytical reflection on the one hand, and that of scientific explanation on the other. Descartes and particularly Kant detached the subject, or consciousness, by showing that I could not possibly apprehend anything as existing unless I first of all experienced myself as existing in the act of apprehending it. They presented consciousness, the absolute certainty of my existence for myself, as the condition of there being anything at all…; the unity of consciousness in Kant is achieved simultaneously with that of the world. And in Descartes methodical doubt does not deprive us of anything, since the whole world, at least in so far as we experience it, is reinstated in the Cogito, enjoying equal certainty, and simply labeled ‘thought of’ … But the relations between subject and world are not strictly bilateral…” (Merleau-Ponty 2002: ixf.)
 
2
In Mark Bevir’s terminology, this position is especially prevalent among ‘strong empiricists’:
“Empiricists generally argue that people arrive at webs of belief as a result of pure experiences. This would suggest that the historian can explain why people held the beliefs they did by reference to their experiences alone: the historian needs to consider only the circumstances in which people find themselves, not the ways in which they construct or interpret their circumstances through the traditions they inherit” (2000: 30).
 
3
Such as the dialogue on tradition between Mark Bevir and Bruce Frohnen (a debate instigated by Bevir’s work on the history of ideas): Bevir 2000; Frohnen 2001; Bevir 1999.
 
4
The literature here is immense, and cannot be captured in a footnote. Two of the more recent contributions to the field offer an overview of the vastness and heterogeneity of the arguments commonly put under the title of ‘post-secularism,’ and can function as a gateway to the wider field (Mendieta and VanAntwerpen 2011; Calhoun et al. 2011).
 
5
Cookery has been one of the oft-used examples in the ongoing intellectual discourse on tradition, mainly because it manages to capture nicely both the superiority of practice over intellectual knowledge (think of the cook who has learned to cook by standing next to—and accepting the authority of- an experienced master, versus the inexperienced ‘cook’ who is trying to follow a cookbook’s instructions). In a similar vein, cookery can also exemplify my point here: think of all the ways in which a certain cook, who is immersed in a certain culinary culture and practice—i.e., tradition -- would never even think of cooking a certain dish, while those very same ways are the most obvious ways in which another cook, coming from another culinary tradition, would handle the same dish (preparing and serving raw meet dishes in certain kitchens versus the practical impossibility of doing the same in others is just one example that springs to mind in this regard). Needless to say, this is not limited to culinary traditions.
 
6
Interestingly, some of the more vehement opponents of such a codification of tradition into a doctrine – a constitution, in this case – are religious scholars of the Islamic University of Al-Azhar in Egypt. As a recent report notes, leading scholars in Al-Azhar, the most authoritative religious institution in Suni Islam, prefer Egypt’s new constitution to preserve phrasing from the state’s former constitution, which placed the ‘principles’ of sharia as the main source of legislation. This, while hard-line ‘Salafists,’ want the new constitution to declare either ‘the rules of sharia,’ or simply sharia, as the main source of legislation: “Al-Azhar has even blocked a push by Salafists, a puritan strand of Islam that won a quarter of votes in last year’s parliamentary elections, to enshrine al-Azhar itself as the sole authority for interpreting sharia. Secular critics fear that al-Azhar’s current, relatively liberal tendency could change, and see this push as a dangerous step towards creating an Iranian-style theocracy. Many of the university’s own clerics agree, noting that Sunni Islam accepts four rival traditions of law, so denying the notion of a single reference” (The Economist, 6 October, 2012).
 
7
As MacIntyre (1988: 12) puts it:
A tradition is an argument extended through time in which certain fundamental agreements are defined and redefined in terms of two kinds of conflict: those with critics and enemies external to the tradition who reject all or at least parts of those fundamental agreements, and those internal, interpretative debates through which the meaning and rationale of the fundamental agreements come to be expressed and by whose progress a tradition is constituted.
 
8
I am indebted to the anonymous readers of my original manuscript for this rendition of the Gadamerian argument.
 
9
At least according to MacIntyre’s critical reading of Burke and Kuhn and to Gadamer’s criticism of romanticism (MacIntyre 2006: 2–23; MacIntyre 1984: 221–2; Gadamer 1989: 282).
 
Literature
go back to reference Baldacchino, J. (1983). The value-centered historicism of Edmund Burke. Modern Age 27(2), 139–145. Baldacchino, J. (1983). The value-centered historicism of Edmund Burke. Modern Age 27(2), 139–145.
go back to reference Berger, P. L., & Luckmann, T. (1967). The social construction of reality: A treatise in the sociology of knowledge. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday. Berger, P. L., & Luckmann, T. (1967). The social construction of reality: A treatise in the sociology of knowledge. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday.
go back to reference Bernstein, R. J. (1983). Beyond objectivism and relativism: Science, hermeneutics, and praxis. Oxford: B. Blackwell. Bernstein, R. J. (1983). Beyond objectivism and relativism: Science, hermeneutics, and praxis. Oxford: B. Blackwell.
go back to reference Bevir, M. (1999). The logic of the history of ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bevir, M. (1999). The logic of the history of ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Bevir, M. (2000). On tradition. Humanitas XIII, 2, 28–53. Bevir, M. (2000). On tradition. Humanitas XIII, 2, 28–53.
go back to reference Byrne, W. F. (2011). Edmund Burke for our time: Moral imagination, meaning, and politics. DeKalb: Northern Illinois University Press. Byrne, W. F. (2011). Edmund Burke for our time: Moral imagination, meaning, and politics. DeKalb: Northern Illinois University Press.
go back to reference Calhoun, C. J., Juergensmeyer, M., & VanAntwerpen, J. (Eds.). (2011). Rethinking secularism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Calhoun, C. J., Juergensmeyer, M., & VanAntwerpen, J. (Eds.). (2011). Rethinking secularism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Descartes, R. (2008). Meditations on first philosophy (Trans. E. S. Haldane). Central, Hong Kong: Forgotten Books. Descartes, R. (2008). Meditations on first philosophy (Trans. E. S. Haldane). Central, Hong Kong: Forgotten Books.
go back to reference Douglas, M. (1986). How institutions think. New York: Syracuse University Press. Douglas, M. (1986). How institutions think. New York: Syracuse University Press.
go back to reference Eisenstadt, S. N. (1972). Intellectuals and tradition. Daedalus, 101(2), 1–19. Eisenstadt, S. N. (1972). Intellectuals and tradition. Daedalus, 101(2), 1–19.
go back to reference Eisenstadt, S. N. (1973). Tradition, change, and modernity. New York: Wiley. Eisenstadt, S. N. (1973). Tradition, change, and modernity. New York: Wiley.
go back to reference Eliot, T. S. (1920). The sacred wood: Essays on poetry and criticism. London: Methuen & Co. LTD. Eliot, T. S. (1920). The sacred wood: Essays on poetry and criticism. London: Methuen & Co. LTD.
go back to reference Frohnen, B. (2001). Tradition, habit, and social interaction: A response to Mark Bevir. Humanitas XIV, 1, 108–116. Frohnen, B. (2001). Tradition, habit, and social interaction: A response to Mark Bevir. Humanitas XIV, 1, 108–116.
go back to reference Gadamer, H.-G. (1976). Philosophical hermeneutics. Berkeley: University of California Press. Gadamer, H.-G. (1976). Philosophical hermeneutics. Berkeley: University of California Press.
go back to reference Gadamer, H.-G. (1979). The problem of historical consciousness. In P. Rabinow & W. M. Sullivan (Eds.), Interpretive social science: A reader (pp. 103–162). Berkeley: University of California Press. Gadamer, H.-G. (1979). The problem of historical consciousness. In P. Rabinow & W. M. Sullivan (Eds.), Interpretive social science: A reader (pp. 103–162). Berkeley: University of California Press.
go back to reference Gadamer, H.-G. (1989). Truth and method (2nd ed.). New York: Crossroad. Gadamer, H.-G. (1989). Truth and method (2nd ed.). New York: Crossroad.
go back to reference Geertz, C. (1968). Islam observed. Religious development in Morocco and Indonesia. The Terry Lectures v. 37. New Haven: Yale University Press. Geertz, C. (1968). Islam observed. Religious development in Morocco and Indonesia. The Terry Lectures v. 37. New Haven: Yale University Press.
go back to reference Geertz, C. (1973). The interpretation of cultures. Selected essays. New York: Basic Books. Geertz, C. (1973). The interpretation of cultures. Selected essays. New York: Basic Books.
go back to reference Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
go back to reference Kuhn, T. S. (1977). The essential tension: Selected studies in scientific tradition and change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Kuhn, T. S. (1977). The essential tension: Selected studies in scientific tradition and change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
go back to reference Latour, B. (1988). Review of: How institutions think. By Mary Douglas. Contemporary Sociology, 17 (3):383–385. doi:10.2307/2069673. Latour, B. (1988). Review of: How institutions think. By Mary Douglas. Contemporary Sociology, 17 (3):383–385. doi:10.​2307/​2069673.
go back to reference MacIntyre, A. (1984). After virtue: A study in moral theory (2nd ed.). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. MacIntyre, A. (1984). After virtue: A study in moral theory (2nd ed.). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
go back to reference MacIntyre, A. (1988). Whose justice? Which rationality?. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. MacIntyre, A. (1988). Whose justice? Which rationality?. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
go back to reference MacIntyre, A. (1991). Three rival versions of moral enquiry: Encyclopaedia, genealogy, and tradition. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. MacIntyre, A. (1991). Three rival versions of moral enquiry: Encyclopaedia, genealogy, and tradition. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
go back to reference MacIntyre, A. (2006). The tasks of philosophy: Volume 1: Selected essays. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef MacIntyre, A. (2006). The tasks of philosophy: Volume 1: Selected essays. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Mendieta, E., & VanAntwerpen, J. (Eds.). (2011). The power of religion in the public sphere. Columbia: Columbia University Press. Mendieta, E., & VanAntwerpen, J. (Eds.). (2011). The power of religion in the public sphere. Columbia: Columbia University Press.
go back to reference Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002). Phenomenology of perception (Trans. C. Smith). Routledge Classics. London: Routledge. Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002). Phenomenology of perception (Trans. C. Smith). Routledge Classics. London: Routledge.
go back to reference Oakeshott, M. (1962). Rationalism in politics and other essays. New York: Basic Books. Oakeshott, M. (1962). Rationalism in politics and other essays. New York: Basic Books.
go back to reference Polanyi, M. (1946). Science, faith and society. London: Oxford University Press. Polanyi, M. (1946). Science, faith and society. London: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Polanyi, M. (1958). Personal knowledge; Towards a post-critical philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Polanyi, M. (1958). Personal knowledge; Towards a post-critical philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
go back to reference Rabinow, P. (1975). Symbolic domination; Cultural form and historical change in Morocco. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Rabinow, P. (1975). Symbolic domination; Cultural form and historical change in Morocco. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
go back to reference Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
go back to reference Shils, E. (1958). Tradition and liberty: Antinomy and interdependence. Ethics, 68(3), 153–165.CrossRef Shils, E. (1958). Tradition and liberty: Antinomy and interdependence. Ethics, 68(3), 153–165.CrossRef
go back to reference Shils, E. (1981). Tradition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Shils, E. (1981). Tradition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
go back to reference Taylor, C. (1971). Interpretation and the sciences of man. The Review of Metaphysics, 25(1), 3–51. Taylor, C. (1971). Interpretation and the sciences of man. The Review of Metaphysics, 25(1), 3–51.
go back to reference Taylor, C. (1985a). Philosophy and the human sciences, Vol. 2. Philosophical Papers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Taylor, C. (1985a). Philosophy and the human sciences, Vol. 2. Philosophical Papers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Taylor, C. (1985b). Human agency and language, Vol. 1. Philosophical Papers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Taylor, C. (1985b). Human agency and language, Vol. 1. Philosophical Papers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Taylor, C. (1992). The ethics of authenticity. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Taylor, C. (1992). The ethics of authenticity. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Taylor, C. (1995). Philosophical arguments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Taylor, C. (1995). Philosophical arguments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Wittgenstein, L. (1968). Philosophical investigations (3rd ed.). New York: Macmillan. Wittgenstein, L. (1968). Philosophical investigations (3rd ed.). New York: Macmillan.
go back to reference Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On certainty. New York: Harper. Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On certainty. New York: Harper.
Metadata
Title
Tradition
Author
Yaacov Yadgar
Publication date
01-12-2013
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Human Studies / Issue 4/2013
Print ISSN: 0163-8548
Electronic ISSN: 1572-851X
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-013-9294-9

Other articles of this Issue 4/2013

Human Studies 4/2013 Go to the issue