Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Public Choice 3-4/2022

29-06-2019

Identity and off-diagonals: how permanent winning coalitions destroy democratic governance

Authors: Peter J. Boettke, Henry A. Thompson

Published in: Public Choice | Issue 3-4/2022

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

The growing preoccupation with identity within public discourse raises important questions concerning its effects on democratic governance. Building on the work of James M. Buchanan, we hope to show that (1) the logic of identity politics raises costs to political cooperation, (2) the phenomenon of identity politics flows from the larger rents associated with the identity group formation and (3) that the rent race has deleterious consequences, i.e., the subversion of democratic governance. The incentives of coalitions to define themselves along identity-related lines threatens democratic governance by enabling the formation of permanent winning coalitions. Without the ability to move between groups and take part in democratic governance, individuals who compose the permanent losing coalitions may choose to defect entirely, immersing the system in tribal violence.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
Elinor Ostrom (2010, pp. 664–665) makes a similar argument in which she states that rather than “nudging”, she is concerned with enhancing the individual capabilities of agents and asking whether institutions are helping or hindering individuals in their innovativeness, learning, adapting, trustworthiness and cooperation within and between groups.
 
2
It is important to note that the analysis is not game-theoretic, the competing coalitions are not making decisions simultaneously. Rather, the framework concerns the decision calculus when either coalition A has the majority or coalition B has the majority regarding policy decisions.
 
3
The generality principle is defined by Buchanan and Congleton (1998, p. xi) as a rule that ensures that “political actions apply to all persons independently of membership in a dominant coalition or an effective interest group. The generality principle is violated to the extent that political action is overtly discriminatory in the sense that the effects, positive or negative, depend on personalized identification”.
 
4
It is important to remember that the relative valuations to each coalition of the excludable government services remain symmetrical.
 
5
Pie-in-the-sky promises are not credible. Rabushka and Shepsle (1972, p. 82) quote Sartori (1966, p. 158), who asserts that “Somebody is always prepared to offer more for less, and the bluff cannot be seen”, which clearly is not the case. Competing coalitions may engage in outbidding, but the more comprehensive and extreme the promises become, the less credible they are to coalition members.
 
6
Stable ideological or religious coalitions certainly are possible because they might include more individuals with similar policy interests. However, in order for our theory to apply, the winning ideological or religious coalition must be sufficiently “different” (socially distant or polarized) from the losers so as to reduce defection or infiltration between the groups. In other words, the costs of a Protestant becoming a Catholic (as in the case of Ireland) or the costs of switching membership from the Whites to the Bolshevik Reds (as in the case of the Red terror in Russia) must be high enough so as to inhibit switching sides and subsequent rent dissipation.
 
7
This analysis is somewhat similar to that of Hardin (1995, pp. 50–52) in which a Prisoner’s Dilemma game, after the effective mobilization of large political coalitions, can tip into a coordination game. While Buchanan and Congleton simply utilize a payoff matrix rather than a 2 × 2 game, the notion of tipping into a “new” scenario is helpful here.
 
8
Esteban and Ray (2011) do find that polarization is an important factor in a broad range of violent conflicts, but they argue that their finding is contingent on whether the goods over which conflict arises are relatively more or less public or private in nature. Public good conflict entails more polarization, and private good conflict implies more fractionalization. That observation is not necessarily in conflict with the analysis of this paper as their assumption that different groups prefer different combinations of public goods is not functionally distinct from excludable private goods.
 
9
Collier and Hoeffler (2004) find that while polarization is insignificant with respect to predicting civil war, they do find that the existence of one dominant ethnic group doubles the risk of conflict.
 
10
Buchanan’s willingness to challenge the conventional manner in which economists model human decision-making is a consistent theme throughout his work, see his “What Should Economists Do” (Buchanan 1964) as well as his Cost and Choice (Buchanan [1969] 1999).
 
11
This conception contrasts sharply with the politics of identity and attempts to build coalitions along fixed or fundamental aspects of identity. While Buchanan ([1978] 1999) does not specifically address the politics of identity in “Natural and Artifactual Man”, he does express reservations about emphasizing the non-voluntary and natural characteristics of man, those same characteristics to which political entrepreneurs may turn in attempts to shore up coalition instability.
 
12
Of course, any number of rules might limit the tyranny of a stable majority, including a constitutional takings clause similar to that in the US Constitution’s Fifth Amendment, a system of civil law, a bill of rights, or even a diverse set of publicly funded educational institutions. Those are, however, merely stop-gap solutions that do not address the root cause: broad government discretion that facilitates the threat of a stable majority.
 
Literature
go back to reference Akerlof, G. A., & Kranton, R. E. (2000). Economics and identity. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 115(3), 715–753.CrossRef Akerlof, G. A., & Kranton, R. E. (2000). Economics and identity. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 115(3), 715–753.CrossRef
go back to reference Arrow, K., & Maskin, E. ([1951] 2012). Social choice and individual values. New Haven: Yale University Press. Arrow, K., & Maskin, E. ([1951] 2012). Social choice and individual values. New Haven: Yale University Press.
go back to reference Barzel, Y. (2000). Property rights and the evolution of the state. Economics of Governance, 1, 25–51. Barzel, Y. (2000). Property rights and the evolution of the state. Economics of Governance, 1, 25–51.
go back to reference Becker, G. S. (1976). The economic approach to human behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRef Becker, G. S. (1976). The economic approach to human behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Berggren, N. (2012). Time for behavioral political economy? An analysis of articles in behavioral economics. Review of Austrian Economics, 25(3), 199–221.CrossRef Berggren, N. (2012). Time for behavioral political economy? An analysis of articles in behavioral economics. Review of Austrian Economics, 25(3), 199–221.CrossRef
go back to reference Bernholz, P. (1974). Logrolling, Arrow-paradox and decision rules—A generalization. Kyklos, 27(1), 49–62.CrossRef Bernholz, P. (1974). Logrolling, Arrow-paradox and decision rules—A generalization. Kyklos, 27(1), 49–62.CrossRef
go back to reference Bernholz, P. (1976). Liberalism, logrolling, and cyclical group preferences. Kyklos, 29(1), 26–38.CrossRef Bernholz, P. (1976). Liberalism, logrolling, and cyclical group preferences. Kyklos, 29(1), 26–38.CrossRef
go back to reference Bernholz, P. (1977). Dominant interest groups and powerless parties. Kyklos, 30, 411–420.CrossRef Bernholz, P. (1977). Dominant interest groups and powerless parties. Kyklos, 30, 411–420.CrossRef
go back to reference Bernholz, P. (1978). On the stability of logrolling outcomes in stochastic games. Public Choice, 33(3), 65–82.CrossRef Bernholz, P. (1978). On the stability of logrolling outcomes in stochastic games. Public Choice, 33(3), 65–82.CrossRef
go back to reference Bernholz, P. (2017). Totalitarianism, terrorism, and supreme values. Cham: Springer.CrossRef Bernholz, P. (2017). Totalitarianism, terrorism, and supreme values. Cham: Springer.CrossRef
go back to reference Birnir, J. K. (2006). Ethnicity and electoral politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Birnir, J. K. (2006). Ethnicity and electoral politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Boettke, P. J. (2014). What should classical liberal political economists do? Constitutional Political Economy, 25(1), 110–124.CrossRef Boettke, P. J. (2014). What should classical liberal political economists do? Constitutional Political Economy, 25(1), 110–124.CrossRef
go back to reference Boettke, P. J. (2018). The assumption of heterogeneity in political economy. StoriaLibera, 4(7), 221–232. Boettke, P. J. (2018). The assumption of heterogeneity in political economy. StoriaLibera, 4(7), 221–232.
go back to reference Boettke, P. J., & Candela, R. A. (2017). Rational choice as if the choosers were human. In M. Altman (Ed.), Handbook of behavioral economics and smart decision-making: Rational decision making within the bounds of reason. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. Boettke, P. J., & Candela, R. A. (2017). Rational choice as if the choosers were human. In M. Altman (Ed.), Handbook of behavioral economics and smart decision-making: Rational decision making within the bounds of reason. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
go back to reference Boettke, P. J., & Coyne, C. J. (2009). Context matters: Institutions and entrepreneurship. Foundations and Trends in Entrepreneurship, 5(3), 135–209.CrossRef Boettke, P. J., & Coyne, C. J. (2009). Context matters: Institutions and entrepreneurship. Foundations and Trends in Entrepreneurship, 5(3), 135–209.CrossRef
go back to reference Buchanan, J. M. (1954). Social choice, democracy, and free markets. Journal of Political Economy, 62(2), 114–123.CrossRef Buchanan, J. M. (1954). Social choice, democracy, and free markets. Journal of Political Economy, 62(2), 114–123.CrossRef
go back to reference Buchanan, J. M. (1964). What should economists do? Southern Economic Journal, 30(3), 213–222.CrossRef Buchanan, J. M. (1964). What should economists do? Southern Economic Journal, 30(3), 213–222.CrossRef
go back to reference Buchanan, J. M. ([1969] 1999). The collected works of James M. Buchanan, volume 6: Cost and choice: An inquiry in economic theory. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, Inc. Buchanan, J. M. ([1969] 1999). The collected works of James M. Buchanan, volume 6: Cost and choice: An inquiry in economic theory. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, Inc.
go back to reference Buchanan, J. M. ([1978] 1999). Natural and artifactual man. In The collected works of James M. Buchanan, volume 1: The logical foundations of constitutional liberty. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, Inc. Buchanan, J. M. ([1978] 1999). Natural and artifactual man. In The collected works of James M. Buchanan, volume 1: The logical foundations of constitutional liberty. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, Inc.
go back to reference Buchanan, J. M., & Congleton, R. D. (1998). The collected works of James M. Buchanan, volume 11: Politics by principle, not interest. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, Inc.CrossRef Buchanan, J. M., & Congleton, R. D. (1998). The collected works of James M. Buchanan, volume 11: Politics by principle, not interest. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, Inc.CrossRef
go back to reference Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. ([1962] 1999). The collected works of James M. Buchanan, volume 3: The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of a constitutional democracy. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, Inc. Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. ([1962] 1999). The collected works of James M. Buchanan, volume 3: The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of a constitutional democracy. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, Inc.
go back to reference Butterworth, R. L. (1971). A research note on the size of winning coalitions. The American Political Science Review, 65(3), 741–748.CrossRef Butterworth, R. L. (1971). A research note on the size of winning coalitions. The American Political Science Review, 65(3), 741–748.CrossRef
go back to reference Caplan, B. (2001). Rational ignorance versus rational irrationality. Kyklos, 54, 3–26.CrossRef Caplan, B. (2001). Rational ignorance versus rational irrationality. Kyklos, 54, 3–26.CrossRef
go back to reference Carvalho, J. P. (2016). Identity-based organizations. American Economic Review: Papers and Proceedings, 106(5), 410–414.CrossRef Carvalho, J. P. (2016). Identity-based organizations. American Economic Review: Papers and Proceedings, 106(5), 410–414.CrossRef
go back to reference Caselli, F., & Coleman, W. J., II. (2013). On the theory of ethnic conflict. Journal of the European Economic Association, 11(1), 161–192.CrossRef Caselli, F., & Coleman, W. J., II. (2013). On the theory of ethnic conflict. Journal of the European Economic Association, 11(1), 161–192.CrossRef
go back to reference Collier, P., & Hoeffler, A. (2004). Greed and grievance in civil war. Oxford Economic Papers, 56(4), 563–595.CrossRef Collier, P., & Hoeffler, A. (2004). Greed and grievance in civil war. Oxford Economic Papers, 56(4), 563–595.CrossRef
go back to reference Congleton, R. D., & Tollison, R. D. (1999). The stability inducing propensities of very unstable coalitions: Avoiding the downward spiral of majoritarian rent-seeking. European Journal of Political Economy, 15(2), 193–205.CrossRef Congleton, R. D., & Tollison, R. D. (1999). The stability inducing propensities of very unstable coalitions: Avoiding the downward spiral of majoritarian rent-seeking. European Journal of Political Economy, 15(2), 193–205.CrossRef
go back to reference Coyne, C. J. (2015). Lobotomizing the defense brain. Review of Austrian Economics, 28(4), 371–396.CrossRef Coyne, C. J. (2015). Lobotomizing the defense brain. Review of Austrian Economics, 28(4), 371–396.CrossRef
go back to reference de Tocqueville, A. ([1835] 2010). Democracy in America. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, Inc. de Tocqueville, A. ([1835] 2010). Democracy in America. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, Inc.
go back to reference Esteban, J., & Ray, D. (2008). Polarization, fractionalization and conflict. Journal of Peace Research, 45(2), 163–182.CrossRef Esteban, J., & Ray, D. (2008). Polarization, fractionalization and conflict. Journal of Peace Research, 45(2), 163–182.CrossRef
go back to reference Esteban, J., & Ray, D. (2011). Linking conflict to inequality and polarization. American Economic Review, 101(4), 1345–1374.CrossRef Esteban, J., & Ray, D. (2011). Linking conflict to inequality and polarization. American Economic Review, 101(4), 1345–1374.CrossRef
go back to reference Esteban, J., & Schneider, G. (2008). Polarization and conflict: Theoretical and empirical issues. Journal of Peace Research, 45(2), 131–141.CrossRef Esteban, J., & Schneider, G. (2008). Polarization and conflict: Theoretical and empirical issues. Journal of Peace Research, 45(2), 131–141.CrossRef
go back to reference Fang, H., & Loury, G. C. (2005). ‘Dysfunctional identities’ can be rational. American Economic Review, 95(2), 103–111.CrossRef Fang, H., & Loury, G. C. (2005). ‘Dysfunctional identities’ can be rational. American Economic Review, 95(2), 103–111.CrossRef
go back to reference Frohlich, N. (1975). The instability of minimum winning coalitions. The American Political Science Review, 69(3), 943–946.CrossRef Frohlich, N. (1975). The instability of minimum winning coalitions. The American Political Science Review, 69(3), 943–946.CrossRef
go back to reference Fukuyama, F. (2018). Identity: The demand for dignity and the politics of resentment. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux. Fukuyama, F. (2018). Identity: The demand for dignity and the politics of resentment. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
go back to reference Gentzkow, M. (2016). Polarization in 2016. Whitepaper. Gentzkow, M. (2016). Polarization in 2016. Whitepaper.
go back to reference Gentzkow, M., Shapiro, J. M., & Taddy, M. (2019). Measuring polarization in high-dimensional data: Method and application to congressional speech. In NBER Working Paper Series No. 22423. Gentzkow, M., Shapiro, J. M., & Taddy, M. (2019). Measuring polarization in high-dimensional data: Method and application to congressional speech. In NBER Working Paper Series No. 22423.
go back to reference Glaeser, E. L., & Shleifer, A. (2002). The Curley effect: The economics of shaping the electorate. Journal of Law Economics and Organization, 21(1), 1–19.CrossRef Glaeser, E. L., & Shleifer, A. (2002). The Curley effect: The economics of shaping the electorate. Journal of Law Economics and Organization, 21(1), 1–19.CrossRef
go back to reference Haefele, E. T. (1970). Coalitions, minority representation, and vote-trading probabilities. Public Choice, 8(1), 75–90.CrossRef Haefele, E. T. (1970). Coalitions, minority representation, and vote-trading probabilities. Public Choice, 8(1), 75–90.CrossRef
go back to reference Hamilton, A., Madison, J., & Jay, J. ([1788] 1983). Federalist No. 10. In J. E. Cooke (Ed.), The Federalist. Middletown: Wesleyan University Press. Hamilton, A., Madison, J., & Jay, J. ([1788] 1983). Federalist No. 10. In J. E. Cooke (Ed.), The Federalist. Middletown: Wesleyan University Press.
go back to reference Hamlin, A., & Jennings, C. (2004). Group formation and political conflict: Instrumental and expressive approaches. Public Choice, 118(2), 413–435.CrossRef Hamlin, A., & Jennings, C. (2004). Group formation and political conflict: Instrumental and expressive approaches. Public Choice, 118(2), 413–435.CrossRef
go back to reference Hamlin, A., & Jennings, C. (2011). Expressive political behavior: Foundations, scope and implications. British Journal of Political Science, 41(4), 883–906.CrossRef Hamlin, A., & Jennings, C. (2011). Expressive political behavior: Foundations, scope and implications. British Journal of Political Science, 41(4), 883–906.CrossRef
go back to reference Hardin, R. (1995). One for all: The logic of group conflict. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Hardin, R. (1995). One for all: The logic of group conflict. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
go back to reference Hillman, A. L. (2010). Expressive behavior in economics and politics. European Journal of Political Economy, 26(4), 403–418.CrossRef Hillman, A. L. (2010). Expressive behavior in economics and politics. European Journal of Political Economy, 26(4), 403–418.CrossRef
go back to reference Hillman, A. L., Metsuyanim, K., & Potrafke, N. (2015a). Democracy with group identity. European Journal of Political Economy, 40, 274–287.CrossRef Hillman, A. L., Metsuyanim, K., & Potrafke, N. (2015a). Democracy with group identity. European Journal of Political Economy, 40, 274–287.CrossRef
go back to reference Hillman, A. L., Metsuyanim, K., & Potrafke, N. (2015b). Clan-based democracy. In Proceedings of CESifo Conference on Behavioral Political Economy (pp. 1–38). Venice: CESifo Venice Summer Institute. Hillman, A. L., Metsuyanim, K., & Potrafke, N. (2015b). Clan-based democracy. In Proceedings of CESifo Conference on Behavioral Political Economy (pp. 1–38). Venice: CESifo Venice Summer Institute.
go back to reference Horowitz, D. L. (1985). Ethnic groups in conflict. Berkley: University of California Press. Horowitz, D. L. (1985). Ethnic groups in conflict. Berkley: University of California Press.
go back to reference Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux. Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
go back to reference Kliemt, H. (1986). The veil of insignificance. European Journal of Political Economy, 2(3), 333–344.CrossRef Kliemt, H. (1986). The veil of insignificance. European Journal of Political Economy, 2(3), 333–344.CrossRef
go back to reference Kranton, R. E., Pease, P., Sanders, S., & Huttel, S. (2013). Identity, group conflict, and social preferences. Working paper. Kranton, R. E., Pease, P., Sanders, S., & Huttel, S. (2013). Identity, group conflict, and social preferences. Working paper.
go back to reference Kuran, T. (1995). Private truths, public lies: The social consequences of preference falsification. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Kuran, T. (1995). Private truths, public lies: The social consequences of preference falsification. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Leeson, P. T. (2005). Endogenizing fractionalization. Journal of Institutional Economics, 1(1), 75–98.CrossRef Leeson, P. T. (2005). Endogenizing fractionalization. Journal of Institutional Economics, 1(1), 75–98.CrossRef
go back to reference Mill, J. S. ([1859] 2001). On liberty. Kitchener: Batoche Books. Mill, J. S. ([1859] 2001). On liberty. Kitchener: Batoche Books.
go back to reference Montalvo, J. G., & Reynal-Querol, M. (2005). Ethnic polarization, potential conflict, and civil wars. American Economic Review, 95(3), 796–816.CrossRef Montalvo, J. G., & Reynal-Querol, M. (2005). Ethnic polarization, potential conflict, and civil wars. American Economic Review, 95(3), 796–816.CrossRef
go back to reference Munger, M. (2018). James Buchanan’s political philosophy. Review of Austrian Economics, 31(2), 151–167.CrossRef Munger, M. (2018). James Buchanan’s political philosophy. Review of Austrian Economics, 31(2), 151–167.CrossRef
go back to reference Olson, M. (1965). The logic of collective action: Public goods and the theory of groups. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Olson, M. (1965). The logic of collective action: Public goods and the theory of groups. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Olson, M. (1993). Dictatorship, democracy, and development. The American Political Science Review, 87(3), 567–576.CrossRef Olson, M. (1993). Dictatorship, democracy, and development. The American Political Science Review, 87(3), 567–576.CrossRef
go back to reference Ostrom, E. (1990). Governing the commons: The evolution of institutions for collective action. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Ostrom, E. (1990). Governing the commons: The evolution of institutions for collective action. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Ostrom, V. (1997). The meaning of democracy and the vulnerability of democracies. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.CrossRef Ostrom, V. (1997). The meaning of democracy and the vulnerability of democracies. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Ostrom, E. (1998). A behavioral approach to the rational choice theory of collective action. American Political Science Review, 92(1), 1–22.CrossRef Ostrom, E. (1998). A behavioral approach to the rational choice theory of collective action. American Political Science Review, 92(1), 1–22.CrossRef
go back to reference Ostrom, E. (2010). Beyond markets and states: Polycentric governance of complex economic systems. American Economic Review, 100(3), 641–672.CrossRef Ostrom, E. (2010). Beyond markets and states: Polycentric governance of complex economic systems. American Economic Review, 100(3), 641–672.CrossRef
go back to reference Pradelski, B., & Carvalho, J. P. (2018). Identity and underrepresentation. Working Paper. Pradelski, B., & Carvalho, J. P. (2018). Identity and underrepresentation. Working Paper.
go back to reference Rabushka, A., & Shepsle, K. A. (1972). Politics in plural societies: A theory of democratic instability. Columbus: Charles E. Merrill Publishing Company. Rabushka, A., & Shepsle, K. A. (1972). Politics in plural societies: A theory of democratic instability. Columbus: Charles E. Merrill Publishing Company.
go back to reference Riker, W. H. (1962). The theory of political coalitions. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. Riker, W. H. (1962). The theory of political coalitions. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.
go back to reference Sartori, G. (1966). European political parties: The case of polarized pluralism. In J. LaPalombara & M. Weiner (Eds.), Political parties and political development. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Sartori, G. (1966). European political parties: The case of polarized pluralism. In J. LaPalombara & M. Weiner (Eds.), Political parties and political development. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
go back to reference Schnellenbach, J., & Schubert, C. (2014). Behavioral political economy: A survey. CESifo Working Paper No. 4988 (pp. 1–54). Munich: Center for Economic Studies & Ifo Institute. Schnellenbach, J., & Schubert, C. (2014). Behavioral political economy: A survey. CESifo Working Paper No. 4988 (pp. 1–54). Munich: Center for Economic Studies & Ifo Institute.
go back to reference Schuessler, A. A. (2000). Expressive voting. Rationality and Society, 12(1), 87–119.CrossRef Schuessler, A. A. (2000). Expressive voting. Rationality and Society, 12(1), 87–119.CrossRef
go back to reference Shayo, M. (2009). A model of social identity with an application to political economy: Nation, class, and redistribution. American Political Science Review, 103(2), 147–174.CrossRef Shayo, M. (2009). A model of social identity with an application to political economy: Nation, class, and redistribution. American Political Science Review, 103(2), 147–174.CrossRef
go back to reference Shayo, M., & Harel, A. (2012). Non-consequentialist voting. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 81(1), 299–313.CrossRef Shayo, M., & Harel, A. (2012). Non-consequentialist voting. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 81(1), 299–313.CrossRef
go back to reference Shepsle, K. A. (1974a). On the size of winning coalitions: Minimum winning coalitions reconsidered: A rejoinder to Butterworth’s ‘comment’. The American Political Science Review, 68(2), 522–524.CrossRef Shepsle, K. A. (1974a). On the size of winning coalitions: Minimum winning coalitions reconsidered: A rejoinder to Butterworth’s ‘comment’. The American Political Science Review, 68(2), 522–524.CrossRef
go back to reference Shepsle, K. A. (1974b). On the size of winning coalitions. The American Political Science Review, 68(2), 505–518.CrossRef Shepsle, K. A. (1974b). On the size of winning coalitions. The American Political Science Review, 68(2), 505–518.CrossRef
go back to reference Shepsle, K. A., & Weingast, B. R. (1981). Structure-induced equilibrium and legislative choice. Public Choice, 37(3), 503–519.CrossRef Shepsle, K. A., & Weingast, B. R. (1981). Structure-induced equilibrium and legislative choice. Public Choice, 37(3), 503–519.CrossRef
go back to reference Shepsle, K. A., & Weingast, B. R. (2012). Why so much stability? Majority voting, legislative institutions, and Gordon Tullock. Public Choice, 152(1–2), 83–95.CrossRef Shepsle, K. A., & Weingast, B. R. (2012). Why so much stability? Majority voting, legislative institutions, and Gordon Tullock. Public Choice, 152(1–2), 83–95.CrossRef
go back to reference Sowell, T. (1981). Markets and minorities. New York: Basic Books. Sowell, T. (1981). Markets and minorities. New York: Basic Books.
go back to reference Thaler, R. H. (1994). The winner’s curse: Paradoxes and anomalies of economic life. New York: Princeton University Press. Thaler, R. H. (1994). The winner’s curse: Paradoxes and anomalies of economic life. New York: Princeton University Press.
go back to reference Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. R. (2003). Libertarian paternalism. In Papers and Proceedings of the One Hundred Fifteenth Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association (vol. 93, no. 2, pp. 174–179). Washington, D.C.: American Economic Association. Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. R. (2003). Libertarian paternalism. In Papers and Proceedings of the One Hundred Fifteenth Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association (vol. 93, no. 2, pp. 174–179). Washington, D.C.: American Economic Association.
go back to reference Thompson, C. B. (1998). John Adams and the spirit of liberty. Lawrence: University of Press Kansas. Thompson, C. B. (1998). John Adams and the spirit of liberty. Lawrence: University of Press Kansas.
go back to reference Tullock, G., & Brennan, G. (1981). Why so much stability. Public Choice, 37(2), 189–204.CrossRef Tullock, G., & Brennan, G. (1981). Why so much stability. Public Choice, 37(2), 189–204.CrossRef
go back to reference Wagner, R. E. (1966). Pressure groups and political entrepreneurs: A review article. Papers on Non-Market Decision Making, 1, 161–170. Wagner, R. E. (1966). Pressure groups and political entrepreneurs: A review article. Papers on Non-Market Decision Making, 1, 161–170.
go back to reference Wagner, R. (2017). James M. Buchanan and liberal political economy: A rational reconstruction. Lanham: Lexington. Wagner, R. (2017). James M. Buchanan and liberal political economy: A rational reconstruction. Lanham: Lexington.
Metadata
Title
Identity and off-diagonals: how permanent winning coalitions destroy democratic governance
Authors
Peter J. Boettke
Henry A. Thompson
Publication date
29-06-2019
Publisher
Springer US
Published in
Public Choice / Issue 3-4/2022
Print ISSN: 0048-5829
Electronic ISSN: 1573-7101
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00683-7

Other articles of this Issue 3-4/2022

Public Choice 3-4/2022 Go to the issue

Premium Partner