Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Human Studies 3/2023

07-07-2023 | Theoretical / Philosophical Paper

The Eidetics of the Unimaginable. What a Phenomenologist can Learn from Ethnomethodology

Author: Christian Ferencz-Flatz

Published in: Human Studies | Issue 3/2023

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

This paper discusses the phenomenological method’s reliance on imaginative procedures in view of ethnomethodological research. While ethnomethodology has often been seen in continuity with Alfred Schütz’ phenomenological sociology, it mainly parts ways with phenomenology by stressing that the decisive details structuring mutual understanding (gestures, bodily expressions, or the myriad trifles that regulate casual conversation) are „not imaginable, but can only be found out”. This paper reflects from a phenomenological perspective on what such a claim entails by first delineating this line of criticism from other objections raised against the use of imaginative procedures in phenomenology and by showing how this line of questioning departs from the core philosophical debates concerning imaginabilitiy and unimaginability in the Kantian tradition. Further on, the paper offers an in-depth interpretation of the aforementioned ethnomethodological claim in order not only to outline its methodological implications for phenomenology, but also to show that it involves possible key insights for understanding interaction, which phenomenology needs to take into account despite its eidetic scope.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
Following up on these arguments, it would have been interesting to also explore the extent to which imaginative procedures come to be used by authors like Garfinkel or Sacks as well in their own ethnomethodological work in ways akin to phenomenology. But while this would be an interesting addition to my present reflection here, it is a different paper altogether.
 
2
See for this also DeSantis, 2011, Ferencz-Flatz, 2011 and Summa, 2022.
 
3
For a more extended treatment of this issue, see Ferencz-Flatz, 2018.
 
4
The racist undertone of this example, which uses cultural stereotypes to make a point about differences in apperception, is of course difficult to overhear.
 
5
This latter illustration might not appear as “overtly fictitious”. It looks like an example that could be real, but might just as well be merely hypothetical, while its use of the present tense suggests the latter – and this is precisely the point at stake here. For in speaking about imaginability, I am not interested primarily in the use of outlandish, impossible, or improbable examples, as they are employed frequently by analytic philosophers and also to some extent in phenomenology, but rather about the possibility of plainly accessing the concrete details of social interactions via mere made up examples. In other words, when speaking about fantasy here, I am specifically using the term in a phenomenological sense, as referring to experiences that are not lived through directly, but reconstructed imaginatively regardless of how prosaic they are. In a phenomenological perspective it is in principle indifferent whether the concrete example under scrutiny is fictional or not, for as long as it can plausibly pass as an account of concrete experience it will not lose anything by being merely fictional. According to Husserl, a phenomenological demonstration does not rest upon the factuality of its starting example. Instead, the main point of my argument here is to show that such an assumption poses some serious difficulties, which should be reflected from a phenomenological perspective.
 
6
See for this especially Kramer and Wilcock, 1999, Wolff, 2006 and Tengelyi, 2012.
 
7
See for this Psathas, 1999, 2009, and 2012, as well as Hammerslay 2019. In his later work, Garfinkel also showed a strong interest for Husserl, Gurwitsch and Merleau-Ponty, see for instance Garfinkel, 2021 or Garfinkel, 2022. Tellingly, Garfinkel himself qualifies his reading of these authors as a “mis-reading” directed at “discovering the phenomena of embodied practices that compose as its production and analyzability the miraculous familiarity of the ordinary society” (Garfinkel, 2022: 76).
 
8
For a more extended analysis of the following, see especially Meerbote, 1981, Makkreel, 1984, Makkreel, 1990, and Kneller, 2009.
 
9
See for this also Ferencz-Flatz, 2018: 190f.
 
10
Garfinkel, 2002: 96.
 
11
Garfinkel, 2002: 96.
 
12
See, for instance, Livingston, 1987: 10f. See also Garfinkel, 2002: 265-282 and Garfinkel and Livingston, 2003.
 
13
See for this Garfinkel, 1996: 35f. and Garfinkel, 2002: 169f. See also Bergmann and Meyer, 2021. Nonethelless some allusions to phenomenology can be found in this context as well, see for instance Garfinkel and Livingston, 2003: 27.
 
14
Garfinkel, 2002: 96.
 
15
Thus, Garfinkel’s account of ethnomethodological descriptors, which are “only available to the search for and recognition of their sense and relevance when they are consulted from within the in-course on-site practices that the analyst is competent with” (Garfinkel, 2022: 73) has overt analogies to Heidegger’s understanding of “formal indication” in phenomenology (see Heidegger 2004: 42 f.).
 
16
These limitations of the imaginative procedure come to play symptomatically in Husserl’s account of practical possibilities. In the initial manuscript of his Ideas II, Husserl starts out by claiming that fantasy enactments are sufficient for a subject to assess what they actually can or cannot do, for instance lifting a weight. The fact that such fantasy assessements are so often erroneous, however, forces him to revise this claim. In doing so, he implicitly acknowledges that our actual behaviors in real situations are unimaginable in advance be it only because they presuppose a mode of consciousness that is impossible to intuitively experience in advance in the form of full-active awareness. Insofar as much of what occurs to us, of what we do, perceive and react to in a situation is not consciously at hand and evades the sort of noticeability, which conditions what we can tell of and describe with regard to that situation, it is also not available for voluntary reproduction. As a consequence, situational experience as a whole remains “not imaginable” in the sense of inaccessible to both imaginative foresight and reconstruction. For a more detailed account of this, see Ferencz-Flatz, 2012.
 
17
On the other hand, Sacks himself of course also frequently uses hypothetical and typical examples.
 
18
For a more extensive discussions of the “naturalization of consciousness,” see, for instance, Zahavi, 2004 and, 2013.
 
19
With regard to Husserl’s view concerning “phenomenological experiments,” see Ferencz-Flatz, 2018.
 
20
Nonetheless, one may argue that such fertilization still involves a necessary empirical foundation for phenomenological research in the perspective of genetic phenomenology at the very least.
 
Literature
go back to reference Adorno, T. W. (2013). Against epistemology: A metacritique. (W. Domingo, Trans.). Polity Press. Adorno, T. W. (2013). Against epistemology: A metacritique. (W. Domingo, Trans.). Polity Press.
go back to reference Aldea, A. S. (2019). Imagination and its critical dimension. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy, 17, 204–224.CrossRef Aldea, A. S. (2019). Imagination and its critical dimension. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy, 17, 204–224.CrossRef
go back to reference Aldea, A. S., & Jansen, J. (2020). We have only just begun: On the reach of the imagination and the depths of conscious life. Husserl Studies, 36(2), 205–211.CrossRef Aldea, A. S., & Jansen, J. (2020). We have only just begun: On the reach of the imagination and the depths of conscious life. Husserl Studies, 36(2), 205–211.CrossRef
go back to reference Bergmann, J., & Meyer, C. (2021). Reflexivity, indexicality, accountability. Zur theoretisch-programmatischen Grundlegung der Ethnomethodologie. In: J. Bergmann & C. Meyer (Eds.)., Ethnomethodologie reloaded. Neue Werkinterpretationen und Theoriebeiträge zu Harold Garfinkels Program (pp. 37–56). transcript. Bergmann, J., & Meyer, C. (2021). Reflexivity, indexicality, accountability. Zur theoretisch-programmatischen Grundlegung der Ethnomethodologie. In: J. Bergmann & C. Meyer (Eds.)., Ethnomethodologie reloaded. Neue Werkinterpretationen und Theoriebeiträge zu Harold Garfinkels Program (pp. 37–56). transcript.
go back to reference DeSantis, D. (2011). On Husserlian eidetic variation and its duplicity: “Contingency-variation” or “similarity-variation”? Alter, 19, 65–81.CrossRef DeSantis, D. (2011). On Husserlian eidetic variation and its duplicity: “Contingency-variation” or “similarity-variation”? Alter, 19, 65–81.CrossRef
go back to reference Ehrenberg, S. (2019). Foregrounding the imagination: Re-reflecting on dancers’ engagement with video self-recordings. In: S. Grant, J. McNeilly-Renaudie, & M. Wagner (Eds.). Performance phenomenology: To the thing itself (pp. 133–163). Springer. Ehrenberg, S. (2019). Foregrounding the imagination: Re-reflecting on dancers’ engagement with video self-recordings. In: S. Grant, J. McNeilly-Renaudie, & M. Wagner (Eds.). Performance phenomenology: To the thing itself (pp. 133–163). Springer.
go back to reference Ferencz-Flatz, C. (2011). Das Beispiel bei Husserl. Tijdschrift voor Filosofie, 73(2), 261–286. Ferencz-Flatz, C. (2011). Das Beispiel bei Husserl. Tijdschrift voor Filosofie, 73(2), 261–286.
go back to reference Ferencz-Flatz, C. (2012). Können und Quasi-Tun: Zum Bewusstsein praktischer Möglichkeiten bei Husserl. Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, 66(2), 248–269.CrossRef Ferencz-Flatz, C. (2012). Können und Quasi-Tun: Zum Bewusstsein praktischer Möglichkeiten bei Husserl. Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, 66(2), 248–269.CrossRef
go back to reference Ferencz-Flatz, C. (2018). Das Experiment bei Husserl. Zum Verhältnis von Empirie und Eidetik in der Phänomenologie. Philosophisches Jahrbuch, 125(2), 170–198.CrossRef Ferencz-Flatz, C. (2018). Das Experiment bei Husserl. Zum Verhältnis von Empirie und Eidetik in der Phänomenologie. Philosophisches Jahrbuch, 125(2), 170–198.CrossRef
go back to reference Gallagher, S., & Rucińska, Z. (2021). Prospecting performance: Rehearsal and the nature of imagination. Synthese, 199, 4523–4541.CrossRef Gallagher, S., & Rucińska, Z. (2021). Prospecting performance: Rehearsal and the nature of imagination. Synthese, 199, 4523–4541.CrossRef
go back to reference Garfinkel, H. (1996). Studies in Ethnomethodology. Polity Press. Garfinkel, H. (1996). Studies in Ethnomethodology. Polity Press.
go back to reference Garfinkel, H. (2002). Ethnomethodology’s program. Working out Durkheim’s aphorism. Rowman & Littlefield. Garfinkel, H. (2002). Ethnomethodology’s program. Working out Durkheim’s aphorism. Rowman & Littlefield.
go back to reference Garfinkel, H. (2021). Ethnomethodological misreading of Aron Gurwitsch on the phenomenal field. Human Studies, 44(1), 19–42.CrossRef Garfinkel, H. (2021). Ethnomethodological misreading of Aron Gurwitsch on the phenomenal field. Human Studies, 44(1), 19–42.CrossRef
go back to reference Garfinkel, H. (2022). Studies of work in the sciences. Routledge. Garfinkel, H. (2022). Studies of work in the sciences. Routledge.
go back to reference Garfinkel, H., & Livingston, E. (2003). Phenomenal field properties of order in formatted queues and their neglected standing in the current situation of inquiry. Visual Studies, 18(1), 21–28.CrossRef Garfinkel, H., & Livingston, E. (2003). Phenomenal field properties of order in formatted queues and their neglected standing in the current situation of inquiry. Visual Studies, 18(1), 21–28.CrossRef
go back to reference Geniusas, S. (2022). Phenomenology of productive imagination: Embodiment, Language, Subjectivity. ibidem Press. Geniusas, S. (2022). Phenomenology of productive imagination: Embodiment, Language, Subjectivity. ibidem Press.
go back to reference Gill, M. J. (2020). Phenomenology as qualitative methodology. In: M. Järvinen & N. Mik-Meyer (Eds.), Qualitative Analysis: Eight approaches (pp. 73–94). Sage. Gill, M. J. (2020). Phenomenology as qualitative methodology. In: M. Järvinen & N. Mik-Meyer (Eds.), Qualitative Analysis: Eight approaches (pp. 73–94). Sage.
go back to reference Goode, D. (2007). Playing with my dog Katie. An ethnomethodological study of dog-human interaction. Purdue University Press. Goode, D. (2007). Playing with my dog Katie. An ethnomethodological study of dog-human interaction. Purdue University Press.
go back to reference Hammersley, M. (2019). Alfred Schutz and ethnomethodology: Origins and departures. History of the Human Sciences, 32(2), 59–75.CrossRef Hammersley, M. (2019). Alfred Schutz and ethnomethodology: Origins and departures. History of the Human Sciences, 32(2), 59–75.CrossRef
go back to reference Heidegger, M. (2000). Towards the definition of philosophy (T. Sadler, Trans.). Athlone. Heidegger, M. (2000). Towards the definition of philosophy (T. Sadler, Trans.). Athlone.
go back to reference Heidegger, M. (2012). Basic problems of phenomenology (S. Campbell, Trans.). Athlone. Heidegger, M. (2012). Basic problems of phenomenology (S. Campbell, Trans.). Athlone.
go back to reference Husserl, E. (1973). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem nachlass. Zweiter Teil: 1921-1928. Martinus Nijhoff.CrossRef Husserl, E. (1973). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem nachlass. Zweiter Teil: 1921-1928. Martinus Nijhoff.CrossRef
go back to reference Husserl, E. (1977). Cartesian Meditations. An introduction to phenomenology (D. Cairns, Trans.). Kluwer. Husserl, E. (1977). Cartesian Meditations. An introduction to phenomenology (D. Cairns, Trans.). Kluwer.
go back to reference Husserl, E. (1983). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy. First book: General introduction to a pure phenomenology (F. Kersten, Trans.). Martinus Nijhoff. Husserl, E. (1983). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy. First book: General introduction to a pure phenomenology (F. Kersten, Trans.). Martinus Nijhoff.
go back to reference Husserl, E. (2001). Logical investigations (II vol.) (J.N. Findlay, Trans.). Routledge. Husserl, E. (2001). Logical investigations (II vol.) (J.N. Findlay, Trans.). Routledge.
go back to reference Husserl, E. (2008). Die Lebenswelt. Auslegungen der vorgegebenen Welt und ihrer Konstitution. Texte aus dem nachlass (1916–1937). Springer. Husserl, E. (2008). Die Lebenswelt. Auslegungen der vorgegebenen Welt und ihrer Konstitution. Texte aus dem nachlass (1916–1937). Springer.
go back to reference Kant, I. (2000). Critique of the power of judgment (P. Guyer & E. Matthews, Trans.) Cambridge University Press. Kant, I. (2000). Critique of the power of judgment (P. Guyer & E. Matthews, Trans.) Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Kant, I. (1999). Critique of pure reason (Paul Guyer & A.W. Wood, Trans.) Cambridge University Press. Kant, I. (1999). Critique of pure reason (Paul Guyer & A.W. Wood, Trans.) Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Kind, A., & Badura, C. (Eds.) (2021). Epistemic uses of the imagination. Routledge. Kind, A., & Badura, C. (Eds.) (2021). Epistemic uses of the imagination. Routledge.
go back to reference Kneller, J. (2009). Kant and the power of imagination. Cambridge University Press. Kneller, J. (2009). Kant and the power of imagination. Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Kramer, A., & Wilcock, E. (1999). A preserve for professional philosophers’ Adornos Husserl-Dissertation 1934–37 und ihr Oxforder Kontext. Deutsche Vierteljahrsschrift für Literaturwissenschaft und Geistesgeschichte 73(1), 115-161. Kramer, A., & Wilcock, E. (1999). A preserve for professional philosophers’ Adornos Husserl-Dissertation 1934–37 und ihr Oxforder Kontext. Deutsche Vierteljahrsschrift für Literaturwissenschaft und Geistesgeschichte 73(1), 115-161.
go back to reference Livingston, E. (1987). Making sense of ethnomethodology. Routledge. Livingston, E. (1987). Making sense of ethnomethodology. Routledge.
go back to reference Lohmar, D. (2005). Die phänomenologische Methode der Wesensschau und ihre Präzisierung als eidetische Variation. Phänomenologische Forschungen 2005, 65-92. Lohmar, D. (2005). Die phänomenologische Methode der Wesensschau und ihre Präzisierung als eidetische Variation. Phänomenologische Forschungen 2005, 65-92.
go back to reference Makkreel, R. (1984). Imagination and temporality in Kant’s theory of the sublime. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 42(3), 303–315. Makkreel, R. (1984). Imagination and temporality in Kant’s theory of the sublime. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 42(3), 303–315.
go back to reference Makkreel, R. (1990). Imagination and interpretation in Kant: The hermeneutical import of the critique of judgment. University of Chicago Press. Makkreel, R. (1990). Imagination and interpretation in Kant: The hermeneutical import of the critique of judgment. University of Chicago Press.
go back to reference Myers, J. (2021). The epistemic status of imagination. Philosophical Studies, 178, 3251–3270.CrossRef Myers, J. (2021). The epistemic status of imagination. Philosophical Studies, 178, 3251–3270.CrossRef
go back to reference Psathas, G. (1999). On the study of human action: Schutz and Garfinkel on social science. In L. Embree (Ed.), Schutzian Social Science (pp. 47–68). Kluwer.CrossRef Psathas, G. (1999). On the study of human action: Schutz and Garfinkel on social science. In L. Embree (Ed.), Schutzian Social Science (pp. 47–68). Kluwer.CrossRef
go back to reference Psathas, G. (2009). The correspondence of Alfred Schutz and Harold Garfinkel: What was the “Terra Incognita” and the “Treasure Island”. In: H. Nasu, L. Embree, G. Psathas, & I. Srubar (Eds.), Alfred Schutz and His Intellectual Partners (pp. 401–434). UVK. Psathas, G. (2009). The correspondence of Alfred Schutz and Harold Garfinkel: What was the “Terra Incognita” and the “Treasure Island”. In: H. Nasu, L. Embree, G. Psathas, & I. Srubar (Eds.), Alfred Schutz and His Intellectual Partners (pp. 401–434). UVK.
go back to reference Psathas, G. (2012). On Garfinkel and Schutz: Contacts and influence. Schutzian Research, 4, 23–31.CrossRef Psathas, G. (2012). On Garfinkel and Schutz: Contacts and influence. Schutzian Research, 4, 23–31.CrossRef
go back to reference Sacks, H. (1992). Lectures in conversation. Volume i, II. Wiley-Blackwell. Sacks, H. (1992). Lectures in conversation. Volume i, II. Wiley-Blackwell.
go back to reference Summa, M. (2022). On the functions of examples in critical philosophy: Kant and Husserl. In: A.S. Aldea, D. Carr, and S. Heinämaa (Eds.), Phenomenology as Critique. Why Method Matters (pp. 25–43). Routledge. Summa, M. (2022). On the functions of examples in critical philosophy: Kant and Husserl. In: A.S. Aldea, D. Carr, and S. Heinämaa (Eds.), Phenomenology as Critique. Why Method Matters (pp. 25–43). Routledge.
go back to reference Tengelyi, L. (2012). Negative Dialektik als geistige Erfahrung? Zu Adornos Auseinandersetzung mit Phänomenologie und Ontologie. Phänomenologische Forschungen 2012, 47–65. Tengelyi, L. (2012). Negative Dialektik als geistige Erfahrung? Zu Adornos Auseinandersetzung mit Phänomenologie und Ontologie. Phänomenologische Forschungen 2012, 47–65.
go back to reference Wolff, E. (2006). From phenomenology to critical theory: The Genesis of Adorno’s critical theory from his reading of Husserl. Philosophy and Social Criticism, 32(5), 555–572.CrossRef Wolff, E. (2006). From phenomenology to critical theory: The Genesis of Adorno’s critical theory from his reading of Husserl. Philosophy and Social Criticism, 32(5), 555–572.CrossRef
go back to reference Zahavi, D. (2004). Phenomenology and the project of naturalization. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3, 331–347.CrossRef Zahavi, D. (2004). Phenomenology and the project of naturalization. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3, 331–347.CrossRef
go back to reference Zahavi, D. (2013). Naturalized phenomenology: A desideratum or a category mistake? In: Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 72: Phenomenology and Naturalism, 23–42. Zahavi, D. (2013). Naturalized phenomenology: A desideratum or a category mistake? In: Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 72: Phenomenology and Naturalism, 23–42.
Metadata
Title
The Eidetics of the Unimaginable. What a Phenomenologist can Learn from Ethnomethodology
Author
Christian Ferencz-Flatz
Publication date
07-07-2023
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Human Studies / Issue 3/2023
Print ISSN: 0163-8548
Electronic ISSN: 1572-851X
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-023-09680-8

Other articles of this Issue 3/2023

Human Studies 3/2023 Go to the issue

Theoretical / Philosophical Paper

The Victim

Premium Partner