Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Public Choice 1-2/2019

24-02-2018

Reflections on Arrow’s theorem and voting rules

Author: Nicholas R. Miller

Published in: Public Choice | Issue 1-2/2019

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

These reflections, written in honor of Kenneth Arrow, sketch out how one political scientist thinks about Arrow’s theorem and its implications for voting rules. The basic claim is that Arrow’s theorem means that all real-world voting rules are problematic in two quite specific ways—namely, they can be neither ‘strategyproof’ nor ‘spoilerproof’. However, Condorcet’s pairwise version of majority rule, while not a fully specified voting rule because of the cyclical majorities problem, is itself both strategyproof and spoilerproof. Moreover, the cycling problem seems to occur only rarely in practice.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
Harvard students did not actually register for classes until the end of second week of the semester, so it was customary to shop around for courses during the first week or so.
 
2
I was not entirely self-taught; in 1969 I took a seminar on Formal Models in Politics taught by the newly arrived and very junior assistant professors Michael Leiserson and Robert Axelrod—probably one of the first such political science courses taught anywhere outside of Rochester.
 
3
For a catalog of problematic (or ‘paradoxical’) features of many voting rules, see Felsenthal (2012).
 
4
Thus I define a voting rule as incorporating tie-breaking and similar mechanisms, though I will avoid the problem of ties in these reflections. I also acknowledge that this definition excludes approval and range voting as voting rules, since they do not operate on ballot profiles as defined in the Arrovian setup.
 
5
Of course, many distinct voting rules—for example, plurality rule, the Borda rule, Instant Runoff Voting (IRV), and so on—are equivalent to majority rule in the special case of two alternatives.
 
6
The Borda rule satisfies all of these conditions except IIA. Another definition of neutrality (e.g., Sen 1970, p. 72) is stronger in the multi-alternative case and itself implies IIA. However, the Borda rule is neutral in the commonsensical way defined above, even though it violates IIA.
 
7
Since I state Arrow’s theorem in terms of preference aggregation rules, I (like Penn 2015) treat transitivity of social preference as an independent condition. On the other hand, I take the domain of a preference aggregation rule to be all logically possible ballot profiles, so I do not treat Arrow’s ‘universal domain’ condition as an independent condition.
 
8
Arrow’s conditions can be weakened further in various ways; for an accessible survey, see Penn (2015).
 
9
This point is illustrated forcefully in a working paper by Dougherty and Heckelman (2017). They generate large samples of simulated three-alternative ballot profiles with varying numbers of voters derived from an ‘impartial culture’, an ‘impartial anonymous culture’, and ANES thermometer scores for candidates in several US presidential elections with significant third-party candidates. They then apply seven common preference aggregation rules (plurality, anti-plurality, Hare/IRV, Nanson, Borda, Copeland and pairwise majority rule) to those profiles and determine how frequently each rule violates one or more of Arrow’s (1963) conditions. With very few exceptions, at most one condition is violated at each profile and the culprit is either IIA or transitivity. More specifically, majority rule occasionally violates transitivity, while the other rules frequently violate IIA.
 
10
The letter writer in fact advocated the use of IRV, which indeed comes closer to meeting requirements (2) and (3) than ordinary plurality rule does, but does not fully meet them and, moreover, fails to meet one other requirement (non-negative responsiveness) that plurality rule does meet.
 
11
Indeed, even if honest ballot rankings imply a clear majority rule winner, it may be open to one or more voters to ‘contrive a (top) cycle’ by misrepresenting their preferences over other alternatives, which may then be resolved in a way favorable to their honest preferences.
 
12
The susceptibility of US elections to ‘spoilers’ (such as Nader in 2000) is the dominant and recurring complaint in William Poundstone’s book on Gaming the Vote: Why Elections Aren’t Fair (2008). In more formal social choice theory, ‘strategic candidacy’ (e.g., Dutta et al. 2001) and ‘independence of clones’ (Tideman 1987) pertain to related problems.
 
13
However, these two problematic features may tend to counteract one another; in any case, that is true with respect to plurality rule (Dowding and Van Hees 2008).
 
14
In particular, the notorious McKelvey (1976, 1979) ‘global cycling theorem’ pertaining to majority rule over a space of two or more dimensions does not imply that a cycle exists (or is even likely to exist) over a small set of arbitrarily selected points in the space.
 
Literature
go back to reference Achen, C. H., & Bartels, L. M. (2016). Democracy for realists: Why elections do not produce responsive government. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef Achen, C. H., & Bartels, L. M. (2016). Democracy for realists: Why elections do not produce responsive government. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Arrow, K. A. (1951). Social choice and individual values. New York, NY: Wiley. Arrow, K. A. (1951). Social choice and individual values. New York, NY: Wiley.
go back to reference Arrow, K. A. (1963). Social choice and individual values (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Wiley. Arrow, K. A. (1963). Social choice and individual values (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Wiley.
go back to reference Barberá, S. (1980). Pivotal voters: A new proof of Arrow’s theorem. Economics Letters, 6(1), 13–16.CrossRef Barberá, S. (1980). Pivotal voters: A new proof of Arrow’s theorem. Economics Letters, 6(1), 13–16.CrossRef
go back to reference Black, D. (1948). On the rationale of group decision-making. Journal of Political Economy, 56(1), 23–34.CrossRef Black, D. (1948). On the rationale of group decision-making. Journal of Political Economy, 56(1), 23–34.CrossRef
go back to reference Black, D. (1958). The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Black, D. (1958). The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Borda, J.-C. de ([1784] 1995). Mémoire sur les élections au scrutin. Translation in I. McLean & A. B. Urken (Eds.), Classics of social choice (pp. 83–89). Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press. Borda, J.-C. de ([1784] 1995). Mémoire sur les élections au scrutin. Translation in I. McLean & A. B. Urken (Eds.), Classics of social choice (pp. 83–89). Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
go back to reference Bordes, G., & Tideman, N. (1991). Independence of irrelevant alternatives in the theory of voting. Theory and Decision, 30(2), 163–186.CrossRef Bordes, G., & Tideman, N. (1991). Independence of irrelevant alternatives in the theory of voting. Theory and Decision, 30(2), 163–186.CrossRef
go back to reference Chamberlin, J. R., Cohen, J. L., & Coombs, C. H. (1984). Social choice observed: Five presidential elections of the American Psychological Association. Journal of Politics, 46(2), 479–502.CrossRef Chamberlin, J. R., Cohen, J. L., & Coombs, C. H. (1984). Social choice observed: Five presidential elections of the American Psychological Association. Journal of Politics, 46(2), 479–502.CrossRef
go back to reference Condorcet, Marquis de ([1785] 1995). Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des decisions rendues à la pluralité des voix. Translation in I. McLean & A. B. Urken (Eds.), Classics of social choice (pp. 91–112). Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1995. Condorcet, Marquis de ([1785] 1995). Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des decisions rendues à la pluralité des voix. Translation in I. McLean & A. B. Urken (Eds.), Classics of social choice (pp. 91–112). Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1995.
go back to reference Dahl, R. A., & Lindbloom, C. E. (1953). Politics, economics, and welfare. New York, NY: Harper and Row. Dahl, R. A., & Lindbloom, C. E. (1953). Politics, economics, and welfare. New York, NY: Harper and Row.
go back to reference Dasgupta, P., & Maskin, E. (2008). On the robustness of majority rule. Journal of the European Economic Association, 6(5), 949–973.CrossRef Dasgupta, P., & Maskin, E. (2008). On the robustness of majority rule. Journal of the European Economic Association, 6(5), 949–973.CrossRef
go back to reference Dodgson, C. ([1876] 1995). A method of taking votes on more than two issues. Reprinted in I. McLean & A. B. Urken (Eds.), Classics of social choice (pp. 288–297). Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1995. Dodgson, C. ([1876] 1995). A method of taking votes on more than two issues. Reprinted in I. McLean & A. B. Urken (Eds.), Classics of social choice (pp. 288–297). Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1995.
go back to reference Dougherty, K. L., & Heckelman, J. C. (2017). The probability of violating Arrow’s conditions. Working paper, Department of Political Science, University of Georgia. Dougherty, K. L., & Heckelman, J. C. (2017). The probability of violating Arrow’s conditions. Working paper, Department of Political Science, University of Georgia.
go back to reference Dowding, K., & Van Hees, M. (2008). In praise of manipulation. British Journal of Political Science, 38(1), 1–15.CrossRef Dowding, K., & Van Hees, M. (2008). In praise of manipulation. British Journal of Political Science, 38(1), 1–15.CrossRef
go back to reference Dutta, B., Jackson, M. O., & Le Breton, M. (2001). Strategic candidacy and voting procedures. Econometrica, 69(4), 1013–1037.CrossRef Dutta, B., Jackson, M. O., & Le Breton, M. (2001). Strategic candidacy and voting procedures. Econometrica, 69(4), 1013–1037.CrossRef
go back to reference Feld, S. L., & Grofman, B. (1986). Partial single-peakedness: An extension and clarification. Public Choice, 51(1), 71–80.CrossRef Feld, S. L., & Grofman, B. (1986). Partial single-peakedness: An extension and clarification. Public Choice, 51(1), 71–80.CrossRef
go back to reference Feld, S. L., & Grofman, B. (1988). Ideological consistency as a collective phenomenon. American Political Science Review, 82(3), 773–788.CrossRef Feld, S. L., & Grofman, B. (1988). Ideological consistency as a collective phenomenon. American Political Science Review, 82(3), 773–788.CrossRef
go back to reference Feld, S. L., & Grofman, B. (1992). Who’s afraid of the big bad cycle? Evidence from 36 elections. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 4(2), 231–237.CrossRef Feld, S. L., & Grofman, B. (1992). Who’s afraid of the big bad cycle? Evidence from 36 elections. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 4(2), 231–237.CrossRef
go back to reference Felsenthal, D. S. (2012). Review of paradoxes afflicting procedures for electing a single candidate. In D. S. Felsenthal & M. Machover (Eds.), Electoral systems: Paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures (pp. 19–91). Heidelberg: Springer.CrossRef Felsenthal, D. S. (2012). Review of paradoxes afflicting procedures for electing a single candidate. In D. S. Felsenthal & M. Machover (Eds.), Electoral systems: Paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures (pp. 19–91). Heidelberg: Springer.CrossRef
go back to reference Fey, M. (2014). A straightforward proof of Arrow’s theorem. Economics Bulletin, 34(3), 1792–1797. Fey, M. (2014). A straightforward proof of Arrow’s theorem. Economics Bulletin, 34(3), 1792–1797.
go back to reference Geanakoplos, J. (2005). Three brief proofs of Arrow’s impossibility theorem. Economic Theory, 26(1), 211–215.CrossRef Geanakoplos, J. (2005). Three brief proofs of Arrow’s impossibility theorem. Economic Theory, 26(1), 211–215.CrossRef
go back to reference Gehrlein, W. V. (2006). Condorcet’s paradox. Berlin: Springer. Gehrlein, W. V. (2006). Condorcet’s paradox. Berlin: Springer.
go back to reference Gehrlein, W. V., & Lepelley, D. (2011). Voting paradoxes and group coherence. Berlin: Springer.CrossRef Gehrlein, W. V., & Lepelley, D. (2011). Voting paradoxes and group coherence. Berlin: Springer.CrossRef
go back to reference Gibbard, A. (1973). Manipulation of voting schemes: A general result. Econometrica, 41(4), 587–601.CrossRef Gibbard, A. (1973). Manipulation of voting schemes: A general result. Econometrica, 41(4), 587–601.CrossRef
go back to reference Mackie, G. (2003). Democracy defended. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Mackie, G. (2003). Democracy defended. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Maskin, E., & Sen, A. (2014). The Arrow impossibility theorem. New York, NY: Columbia University Press. ReviewCrossRef Maskin, E., & Sen, A. (2014). The Arrow impossibility theorem. New York, NY: Columbia University Press. ReviewCrossRef
go back to reference Maskin, E. & Sen, A. (2017). A new electoral system? In The New York Review of Books (pp. 8–10). Maskin, E. & Sen, A. (2017). A new electoral system? In The New York Review of Books (pp. 8–10).
go back to reference May, K. O. (1952). A set of independent necessary and sufficient conditions for simple majority decision. Econometrica, 20(4), 680–684.CrossRef May, K. O. (1952). A set of independent necessary and sufficient conditions for simple majority decision. Econometrica, 20(4), 680–684.CrossRef
go back to reference McKelvey, R. D. (1976). Intransitivities in multidimensional voting models and some implications for agenda control. Journal of Economic Theory, 12(3), 472–482.CrossRef McKelvey, R. D. (1976). Intransitivities in multidimensional voting models and some implications for agenda control. Journal of Economic Theory, 12(3), 472–482.CrossRef
go back to reference McKelvey, R. D. (1979). General conditions for global intransitivities in formal voting models. Econometrica, 47(5), 1085–1112.CrossRef McKelvey, R. D. (1979). General conditions for global intransitivities in formal voting models. Econometrica, 47(5), 1085–1112.CrossRef
go back to reference McLean, I. (1995). Independence of irrelevant alternatives before Arrow. Mathematical Social Sciences., 30(2), 107–126.CrossRef McLean, I. (1995). Independence of irrelevant alternatives before Arrow. Mathematical Social Sciences., 30(2), 107–126.CrossRef
go back to reference McLean, I. (2003). The reasonableness of independence: A conversation from Condorcet and Borda to the present day. Nuffield College Politics Working Paper 2003-W6, University of Oxford. McLean, I. (2003). The reasonableness of independence: A conversation from Condorcet and Borda to the present day. Nuffield College Politics Working Paper 2003-W6, University of Oxford.
go back to reference Muller, E., & Satterthwaite, M. A. (1977). The equivalence of strong positive association and strategy-proofness. Journal of Economic Theory, 14(2), 412–418.CrossRef Muller, E., & Satterthwaite, M. A. (1977). The equivalence of strong positive association and strategy-proofness. Journal of Economic Theory, 14(2), 412–418.CrossRef
go back to reference Nanson, E. J. ([1882] 1995). Methods of election. Reprinted in I. McLean & A. B. Urken (Eds.), Classics of social choice (pp. 321–359). Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1995. Nanson, E. J. ([1882] 1995). Methods of election. Reprinted in I. McLean & A. B. Urken (Eds.), Classics of social choice (pp. 321–359). Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1995.
go back to reference Penn, E. M. (2015). Arrow’s theorem and its descendants. In J. C. Heckelman & N. R. Miller (Eds.), Handbook of social choice and voting (pp. 237–262). Cheltenham, UK; Northhampton, MA: Edward Elgar.CrossRef Penn, E. M. (2015). Arrow’s theorem and its descendants. In J. C. Heckelman & N. R. Miller (Eds.), Handbook of social choice and voting (pp. 237–262). Cheltenham, UK; Northhampton, MA: Edward Elgar.CrossRef
go back to reference Poundstone, W. (2008). Gaming the vote: Why elections aren’t fair. New York, NY: Hill and Wang. Poundstone, W. (2008). Gaming the vote: Why elections aren’t fair. New York, NY: Hill and Wang.
go back to reference Ray, P. (1973). Independence of irrelevant alternatives. Econometrica, 41(5), 987–991.CrossRef Ray, P. (1973). Independence of irrelevant alternatives. Econometrica, 41(5), 987–991.CrossRef
go back to reference Reny, P. J. (2010). Arrow’s theorem and the Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem: A unified approach. Economics Letters, 70(1), 99–105.CrossRef Reny, P. J. (2010). Arrow’s theorem and the Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem: A unified approach. Economics Letters, 70(1), 99–105.CrossRef
go back to reference Riker, W. H. (1953). Democracy in the United States. New York, NY: Macmillan. Riker, W. H. (1953). Democracy in the United States. New York, NY: Macmillan.
go back to reference Riker, W. H. (1982). Liberalism against populism: A confrontation between the theory of democracy and the theory of social choice. San Francisco, CA: W. H. Freeman and Company. Riker, W. H. (1982). Liberalism against populism: A confrontation between the theory of democracy and the theory of social choice. San Francisco, CA: W. H. Freeman and Company.
go back to reference Samuelson, P. (1967). Arrow’s mathematical politics. In S. Hook (Ed.), Human values and economic policy. New York, NY: New York University Press. Samuelson, P. (1967). Arrow’s mathematical politics. In S. Hook (Ed.), Human values and economic policy. New York, NY: New York University Press.
go back to reference Satterthwaite, M. A. (1975). Strategy-proofness and Arrow’s conditions: Existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions. Journal of Economic Theory, 10(2), 187–217.CrossRef Satterthwaite, M. A. (1975). Strategy-proofness and Arrow’s conditions: Existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions. Journal of Economic Theory, 10(2), 187–217.CrossRef
go back to reference Sen, A. K. (1970). Collective choice and social welfare. San Francisco, CA: Holden-Day Inc. Sen, A. K. (1970). Collective choice and social welfare. San Francisco, CA: Holden-Day Inc.
go back to reference Sen, A. (2014). Arrow and the impossibility theorem. In E. Maskin & A. Sen (Eds.), The Arrow impossibility theorem (pp. 29–55). New York, NY: Columbia University Press. Sen, A. (2014). Arrow and the impossibility theorem. In E. Maskin & A. Sen (Eds.), The Arrow impossibility theorem (pp. 29–55). New York, NY: Columbia University Press.
go back to reference Tideman, T. N. (1987). Independence of clones as a criterion for voting rules. Social Choice and Welfare, 4(3), 185–206.CrossRef Tideman, T. N. (1987). Independence of clones as a criterion for voting rules. Social Choice and Welfare, 4(3), 185–206.CrossRef
go back to reference Tideman, N. (2006). Collective decisions and voting: The potential for public choice. Aldershot: Ashgate. Tideman, N. (2006). Collective decisions and voting: The potential for public choice. Aldershot: Ashgate.
go back to reference Tsetlin, I., Regenwetter, M., & Grofman, B. (2003). The impartial culture maximizes the probability of majority cycles. Social Choice and Welfare, 21(3), 387–398.CrossRef Tsetlin, I., Regenwetter, M., & Grofman, B. (2003). The impartial culture maximizes the probability of majority cycles. Social Choice and Welfare, 21(3), 387–398.CrossRef
Metadata
Title
Reflections on Arrow’s theorem and voting rules
Author
Nicholas R. Miller
Publication date
24-02-2018
Publisher
Springer US
Published in
Public Choice / Issue 1-2/2019
Print ISSN: 0048-5829
Electronic ISSN: 1573-7101
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-018-0524-6

Other articles of this Issue 1-2/2019

Public Choice 1-2/2019 Go to the issue