Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Public Choice 1-2/2019

07-04-2018

Weak rationalizability and Arrovian impossibility theorems for responsive social choice

Author: John Duggan

Published in: Public Choice | Issue 1-2/2019

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

This paper provides representation theorems for choice functions satisfying weak rationality conditions: a choice function satisfies \(\alpha\) if and only if it can be expressed as the union of intersections of maximal sets of a fixed collection of acyclic relations, and a choice function satisfies \(\gamma\) if and only if it consists of the maximal elements of a relation that can depend on the feasible set in a particular, well-behaved way. Other rationality conditions are investigated, and these results are applied to deduce impossibility theorems for social choice functions satisfying weak rationality conditions along with positive responsiveness conditions. For example, under standard assumptions on the set of alternatives and domain of preferences, if a social choice function satisfies Pareto optimality, independence of irrelevant alternatives, a positive responsiveness condition for revealed social preferences, and a new rationality condition \(\delta ^{*}\) (a strengthening of \(\gamma\)), then some individual must have near dictatorial power.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
Equivalently, B is a linear order if \(R_{B}\) is transitive and anti-symmetric; it is a weak order if \(R_{B}\) is transitive; it is a quasiorder if \(R_{B}\) is negatively transitive; and it is a suborder if \(R_{B}\) is negatively acyclic, in the sense that there do not exist a natural number k and alternatives \(x_{1},\ldots ,x_{k} \in X\) such that \(\lnot x_{j} R_{B} x_{j+1}\) for all \(j <k\) and \(\lnot x_{k}R_{B}x_{1}\).
 
2
See Duggan (2013) for a review of the related literature and for general results on the uncovered set.
 
3
The result is also shown in Theorem 1 of Schwartz (1976). He assumes the collection of feasible sets consists of the nonempty, finite subsets of alternatives, and he defines a condition W1 that is equivalent to the conjunction of \(\alpha\) and \(\gamma\).
 
4
The axiom of Aizerman and Malishevski (1981) requires the opposite inclusion as well, so that \(C(Y)=C(Z)\), but this holds in the presence of \(\alpha\). Condition W5 of Schwartz (1976) suffers from a typo: \(\not \subseteq\) should be \(\subseteq\). See Weymark (1983) for a discussion of why condition \(\phi\) must be applied with some restriction on the size of feasible sets.
 
5
To verify that \(\beta '\) implies \(\beta\), consider \(Y,Z \in {\mathcal {X}}\) and assume \(Y \subseteq Z\) and \(C(Y) \cap C(Z) \ne \emptyset\). In particular, \(C(Z) \cap Y \ne \emptyset\), so \(\beta '\) implies \(C(Y) \subseteq C(Y \cup Z)=C(Z)\), as required.
 
6
Sen’s (1971) Theorem T.8 shows that the conjunction of \(\alpha\) and \(\beta\) is equivalent to the weak congruence axiom, which is equivalent to rationalizability by a weak order, which is equivalent to ACA; see Proposition 3.
 
7
The term “pseudo-relation” is not my own: it appears in the overhead slides of a seminar at Caltech, collected in Aizerman et al. (1991). The term “pseudo-rationalizability” is used differently than by Moulin (1985).
 
8
Mas-Colell and Sonnenschein (1972) assume that if some individual is indifferent between x and y and then this becomes a strict preference, then this is sufficient to break a social tie, and if some individual has a strict preference and then this becomes indifference, again a social tie is broken. In contrast, the antecedent of r-Tie break condition requires a strict preference reversal, making the axiom considerably weaker.
 
Literature
go back to reference Aizerman, M., & Malishevski, A. (1981). General theory of best variants choice: Some aspects. IEEE Transactions on Automatic Control, 26, 1030–1040.CrossRef Aizerman, M., & Malishevski, A. (1981). General theory of best variants choice: Some aspects. IEEE Transactions on Automatic Control, 26, 1030–1040.CrossRef
go back to reference Aizerman, M., Vol’skiy, V., & Litvakov, M. (1991). Notes about theory of pseudo-criteria and binary pseudo-relations and their application to the theory of choice and voting. Caltech working paper #766. Aizerman, M., Vol’skiy, V., & Litvakov, M. (1991). Notes about theory of pseudo-criteria and binary pseudo-relations and their application to the theory of choice and voting. Caltech working paper #766.
go back to reference Arrow, K. (1959). Rational choice functions and orderings. Economica, 26, 121–127.CrossRef Arrow, K. (1959). Rational choice functions and orderings. Economica, 26, 121–127.CrossRef
go back to reference Arrow, K. (1963). Social choice and individual values (2nd ed.). New Haven: Cowles Foundation. Arrow, K. (1963). Social choice and individual values (2nd ed.). New Haven: Cowles Foundation.
go back to reference Blair, D., Bordes, G., Kelly, J., & Suzumura, K. (1976). Impossibility theorems without collective rationality. Journal of Economic Theory, 13, 361–379.CrossRef Blair, D., Bordes, G., Kelly, J., & Suzumura, K. (1976). Impossibility theorems without collective rationality. Journal of Economic Theory, 13, 361–379.CrossRef
go back to reference Bordes, G. (1983). On the possibility of reasonable consistent majoritarian choice: Some positive results. Journal of Economic Theory, 31, 122–132.CrossRef Bordes, G. (1983). On the possibility of reasonable consistent majoritarian choice: Some positive results. Journal of Economic Theory, 31, 122–132.CrossRef
go back to reference Chernoff, H. (1954) Rational selection of decision functions. Econometrica, 22, 422–443.CrossRef Chernoff, H. (1954) Rational selection of decision functions. Econometrica, 22, 422–443.CrossRef
go back to reference Denicolò, V. (1985). Independent social choice correspondences are dictatorial. Economics Letters, 19, 9–12.CrossRef Denicolò, V. (1985). Independent social choice correspondences are dictatorial. Economics Letters, 19, 9–12.CrossRef
go back to reference Duggan, J. (2007). A systematic approach to the construction of non-empty choice sets. Social Choice and Welfare, 28, 491–506.CrossRef Duggan, J. (2007). A systematic approach to the construction of non-empty choice sets. Social Choice and Welfare, 28, 491–506.CrossRef
go back to reference Duggan, J. (2013). Uncovered sets. Social Choice and Welfare, 41, 489–535.CrossRef Duggan, J. (2013). Uncovered sets. Social Choice and Welfare, 41, 489–535.CrossRef
go back to reference Duggan, J. (2016). Limits of acyclic voting. Journal of Economic Theory, 163, 658–683.CrossRef Duggan, J. (2016). Limits of acyclic voting. Journal of Economic Theory, 163, 658–683.CrossRef
go back to reference Fishburn, P. (1975). Semiorders and choice functions. Econometrica, 43, 5–6. Fishburn, P. (1975). Semiorders and choice functions. Econometrica, 43, 5–6.
go back to reference Gibbard, A. (1969). Social choice and the arrow conditions. Discussion paper, Department of Philosophy, University of Michigan. Gibbard, A. (1969). Social choice and the arrow conditions. Discussion paper, Department of Philosophy, University of Michigan.
go back to reference Gibbard, A. (2014). Social choice and the arrow conditions. Economics and Philosophy, 30, 269–284.CrossRef Gibbard, A. (2014). Social choice and the arrow conditions. Economics and Philosophy, 30, 269–284.CrossRef
go back to reference Gillies, D. (1959). Solutions to general non-zero-sum games. In A. Tucker, & R. Luce (Eds.), Contributions to the theory of games IV, Annals of mathematical studies (Vol. 40). Princeton: Princeton University Press. Gillies, D. (1959). Solutions to general non-zero-sum games. In A. Tucker, & R. Luce (Eds.), Contributions to the theory of games IV, Annals of mathematical studies (Vol. 40). Princeton: Princeton University Press.
go back to reference Hansson, B. (1969). Voting and group decision functions. Synthese, 20, 526–537.CrossRef Hansson, B. (1969). Voting and group decision functions. Synthese, 20, 526–537.CrossRef
go back to reference Horan, S., Osborne, M., & Sanver, R. (2017). Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: A generalization of May’s theorem to many alternatives. Unpublished paper. Horan, S., Osborne, M., & Sanver, R. (2017). Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: A generalization of May’s theorem to many alternatives. Unpublished paper.
go back to reference Houthakker, H. (1950). Revealed preference and the utility function. Economica, 17, 159–174.CrossRef Houthakker, H. (1950). Revealed preference and the utility function. Economica, 17, 159–174.CrossRef
go back to reference Jamison, D., & Lau, L. (1973). Semiorders and the theory of choice. Econometrica, 41, 901–912.CrossRef Jamison, D., & Lau, L. (1973). Semiorders and the theory of choice. Econometrica, 41, 901–912.CrossRef
go back to reference Mas-Colell, A., & Sonnenschein, H. (1972). General possibility theorems for group decisions. Review of Economic Studies, 39, 185–192.CrossRef Mas-Colell, A., & Sonnenschein, H. (1972). General possibility theorems for group decisions. Review of Economic Studies, 39, 185–192.CrossRef
go back to reference May, K. (1952). A set of independent necessary and sufficient conditions for simple majority decision. Econometrica, 20, 680–684.CrossRef May, K. (1952). A set of independent necessary and sufficient conditions for simple majority decision. Econometrica, 20, 680–684.CrossRef
go back to reference McKelvey, R. (1986). Covering, dominance, and institution-free properties of social choice. American Journal of Political Science, 30, 283–314.CrossRef McKelvey, R. (1986). Covering, dominance, and institution-free properties of social choice. American Journal of Political Science, 30, 283–314.CrossRef
go back to reference Moulin, H. (1985). Choice functions over a finite set: A summary. Social Choice and Welfare, 2, 147–160.CrossRef Moulin, H. (1985). Choice functions over a finite set: A summary. Social Choice and Welfare, 2, 147–160.CrossRef
go back to reference Plott, C. (1973). Path independence, rationality, and social choice. Econometrica, 41, 1075–1091.CrossRef Plott, C. (1973). Path independence, rationality, and social choice. Econometrica, 41, 1075–1091.CrossRef
go back to reference Samuelson, P. (1938). A note on the pure theory of consumer’s behavior. Economica, 5, 61–71.CrossRef Samuelson, P. (1938). A note on the pure theory of consumer’s behavior. Economica, 5, 61–71.CrossRef
go back to reference Schwartz, T. (1976). Choice functions, ‘rationality’ conditions, and variations on the weak axiom of revealed preference. Journal of Economic Theory, 13, 414–427.CrossRef Schwartz, T. (1976). Choice functions, ‘rationality’ conditions, and variations on the weak axiom of revealed preference. Journal of Economic Theory, 13, 414–427.CrossRef
go back to reference Schwartz, T. (1986). The logic of collective choice. New York: Columbia. Schwartz, T. (1986). The logic of collective choice. New York: Columbia.
go back to reference Sen, A. (1971) Choice functions and revealed preference. The Review of Economic Studies, 38, 307–317.CrossRef Sen, A. (1971) Choice functions and revealed preference. The Review of Economic Studies, 38, 307–317.CrossRef
go back to reference Weymark, J. (1983). Quasitransitive rationalization and the superset property. Mathematical Social Sciences, 6, 105–108.CrossRef Weymark, J. (1983). Quasitransitive rationalization and the superset property. Mathematical Social Sciences, 6, 105–108.CrossRef
Metadata
Title
Weak rationalizability and Arrovian impossibility theorems for responsive social choice
Author
John Duggan
Publication date
07-04-2018
Publisher
Springer US
Published in
Public Choice / Issue 1-2/2019
Print ISSN: 0048-5829
Electronic ISSN: 1573-7101
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-018-0528-2

Other articles of this Issue 1-2/2019

Public Choice 1-2/2019 Go to the issue