Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Minds and Machines 1/2018

21-06-2017

Still Autonomous After All

Author: Andrew Knoll

Published in: Minds and Machines | Issue 1/2018

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Recent mechanistic philosophers (in particular, Boone and Piccinini in Synthese 193(5):1287–1321, 2016) have argued that the cognitive sciences are not autonomous from neuroscience proper. I clarify two senses of autonomy–metaphysical and epistemic—and argue that cognitive science is still autonomous in both senses. Moreover, mechanistic explanation of cognitive phenomena is not therefore an alternative to the view that cognitive science is autonomous of neuroscience. If anything, it’s a way of characterizing just how cognitive processes are implemented by neural mechanisms.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 390 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe




 

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
Note that this is a claim about explanatory efficacy, not existence. If you’re so inclined to draw ontological conclusions from explanatory considerations, you are welcome to do so. If you think such an ontological program is misguided, I won’t contradict you here. We have enough to worry about without getting bogged down in ontological disputes per se.
 
2
There’s been lots of recent interest lately on the explanatory usefulness of representations, in particular whether representations with intentional content—or inherent aboutness or correctness conditions—buy you any explanatory work at all. For negative views, (see Stich 1983; Chomsky 2000; Collins 2007; Egan 2010; Ramsey 2007; Orlandi 2014), inter alia. Georges Rey and myself (Knoll and Rey in press) and Tyler Burge (2010), all erstwhile defenders of the explanatory efficacy of intentional content, concede that some cognitive explanations do not appeal to intentional contents.
 
3
See Woodward (2010) for an overview of how such factors feature in biological explanation.
 
4
Cf. Burge (2010).
 
5
Hale and Reiss (2008, pp. 154–56); Knoll (under review).
 
6
I’ll leave it to the metaphysicians to figure out whether the properties still exist.
 
7
Pace Polger and Shapiro (2016), who argue in favor both of the autonomy of psychology and a type-identity theory of its states (see, in particular, Chap. 10).
 
8
Indeed, Piccinini and Craver (2011, p. 284. n. 2; pp. 288–89) claim as much.
 
9
I’d argue that he is wrong to suppose that such place cell activity has representational content in any explanatorily useful sense. But, I’ll not do so now. The current point is that even if we grant that this activity has representational content, it doesn’t undermine the metaphysical autonomy thesis.
 
10
The quick argument is that a content like ‘sun’ can function to token a false belief that the sun revolves around the earth, but can also function to token a true belief that the earth revolves around the sun. So, ‘sun’ must be individuated independently of its functional role in cognition.
 
11
Fodor’s treatment of atomic representations generally extends to other entities posited by cognitive scientists. For example, there’s reason to think (Hale and Reiss 2008, chap. 5–7) that the distinctive features (e.g., [+velar], [−voice]) posited as mental states by generative phonology are individuated independently of their functional roles. See further discussion of such distinctive features below.
 
12
See Pietroski and Rey (1995) for an account of ceteris paribus laws along these lines.
 
13
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this possibility.
 
Literature
go back to reference Bechtel, W. (2016). Investigating neural representations: the tale of place cells. Synthese, 193(5), 1287–1321.CrossRef Bechtel, W. (2016). Investigating neural representations: the tale of place cells. Synthese, 193(5), 1287–1321.CrossRef
go back to reference Boone, W., & Piccinini, G. (2016). The cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese, 193(5), 1509–1534.CrossRef Boone, W., & Piccinini, G. (2016). The cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese, 193(5), 1509–1534.CrossRef
go back to reference Carruthers, P. (2015). The centered mind: What the science of working memory shows us about the nature of human thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Carruthers, P. (2015). The centered mind: What the science of working memory shows us about the nature of human thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Chomsky, N. (2000). New horizons in the study of language and mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Chomsky, N. (2000). New horizons in the study of language and mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Chomsky, N. (2002). On nature and language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Chomsky, N. (2002). On nature and language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Collins, J. (2007). Meta-scientific Eliminativism: A reconsideration of Chomsky’s review of Skinner’s verbal behavior. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(4), 625–658.CrossRef Collins, J. (2007). Meta-scientific Eliminativism: A reconsideration of Chomsky’s review of Skinner’s verbal behavior. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(4), 625–658.CrossRef
go back to reference Egan, F. (2010). Computational models: a modest role for content. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41(3), 253–259.CrossRef Egan, F. (2010). Computational models: a modest role for content. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41(3), 253–259.CrossRef
go back to reference Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28(2), 97–115.CrossRef Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28(2), 97–115.CrossRef
go back to reference Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press. Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Fodor, J. (1997). Special sciences: Still autonomous after all these years. Noûs, 31, 149–163.CrossRef Fodor, J. (1997). Special sciences: Still autonomous after all these years. Noûs, 31, 149–163.CrossRef
go back to reference Fodor, J. A. (1998). Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Fodor, J. A. (1998). Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Fodor, J. A. (2000). The mind doesn’t work that way: The scope and limits of computational psychology. Cambridge: MIT Press. Fodor, J. A. (2000). The mind doesn’t work that way: The scope and limits of computational psychology. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Hale, M., & Reiss, C. (2008). The phonological enterprise. Cambridge: Oxford University Press. Hale, M., & Reiss, C. (2008). The phonological enterprise. Cambridge: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Hornstein, N. (2005). “Chomsky’s natural philosophy” forward to Chomsky, N. rules and representations. New York: Columbia University Press. Hornstein, N. (2005). “Chomsky’s natural philosophy” forward to Chomsky, N. rules and representations. New York: Columbia University Press.
go back to reference Idsardi, W. (2006). A simple proof that optimality theory is computationally intractable. Linguistic Inquiry, 37, 271–275.CrossRef Idsardi, W. (2006). A simple proof that optimality theory is computationally intractable. Linguistic Inquiry, 37, 271–275.CrossRef
go back to reference Jones, M., & Love, B. C. (2011). Bayesian fundamentalism or enlightenment? On the explanatory status and theoretical contributions of Bayesian models of cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34(4), 169–188.CrossRef Jones, M., & Love, B. C. (2011). Bayesian fundamentalism or enlightenment? On the explanatory status and theoretical contributions of Bayesian models of cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34(4), 169–188.CrossRef
go back to reference Knoll, A. (under review). Intentional content in phonology. Knoll, A. (under review). Intentional content in phonology.
go back to reference Knoll, A., & Rey, G. (in press). Arthropod intentionality? In K. Andrews & J. Beck (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of animal minds. Abingdon: Routledge. Knoll, A., & Rey, G. (in press). Arthropod intentionality? In K. Andrews & J. Beck (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of animal minds. Abingdon: Routledge.
go back to reference Lidz, J., Pietroski, P., Hunter, T., & Halberda, J. (2011). Interface transparency and the psychosemantics of most. Natural Language Semantics, 19(3), 227–256.CrossRef Lidz, J., Pietroski, P., Hunter, T., & Halberda, J. (2011). Interface transparency and the psychosemantics of most. Natural Language Semantics, 19(3), 227–256.CrossRef
go back to reference Menzel, R. (2012). The honeybee as a model for understanding the basis of cognition. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 13, 758–768.CrossRef Menzel, R. (2012). The honeybee as a model for understanding the basis of cognition. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 13, 758–768.CrossRef
go back to reference Orlandi, N. (2014). The innocent eye: Why vision is not a cognitive process. New York: OUP.CrossRef Orlandi, N. (2014). The innocent eye: Why vision is not a cognitive process. New York: OUP.CrossRef
go back to reference Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183(3), 283–311.CrossRef Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183(3), 283–311.CrossRef
go back to reference Piccinini, G., & Maley, C. J. (2014). The metaphysics of mind and the multiple sources of multiple realization. In M. Sprevak & J. Kallestrup (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of mind (pp. 125–152). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRef Piccinini, G., & Maley, C. J. (2014). The metaphysics of mind and the multiple sources of multiple realization. In M. Sprevak & J. Kallestrup (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of mind (pp. 125–152). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRef
go back to reference Pietroski, P., Lidz, J., Hunter, T., & Halberda, J. (2009). The meaning of ‘most’: Semantics, numerosity and psychology. Mind and Language, 24(5), 554–585.CrossRef Pietroski, P., Lidz, J., Hunter, T., & Halberda, J. (2009). The meaning of ‘most’: Semantics, numerosity and psychology. Mind and Language, 24(5), 554–585.CrossRef
go back to reference Pietroski, P., Lidz, J., Hunter, T., & Halberda, J. (2011). Seeing what you mean, mostly. Syntax and Semantics, 37, 181–218.CrossRef Pietroski, P., Lidz, J., Hunter, T., & Halberda, J. (2011). Seeing what you mean, mostly. Syntax and Semantics, 37, 181–218.CrossRef
go back to reference Pietroski, P., & Rey, G. (1995). When other things aren’t equal: Saving ceteris paribus laws from vacuity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46(1), 81–110.MathSciNetCrossRefMATH Pietroski, P., & Rey, G. (1995). When other things aren’t equal: Saving ceteris paribus laws from vacuity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46(1), 81–110.MathSciNetCrossRefMATH
go back to reference Poeppel, D., Idsardi, W. J., & van Wassenhove, V. (2008). Speech perception at the interface of neurobiology and linguistics. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 363(1493), 1071–1086.CrossRef Poeppel, D., Idsardi, W. J., & van Wassenhove, V. (2008). Speech perception at the interface of neurobiology and linguistics. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 363(1493), 1071–1086.CrossRef
go back to reference Polger, T. W., & Shapiro, L. A. (2016). The multiple realization book. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Polger, T. W., & Shapiro, L. A. (2016). The multiple realization book. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Putnam, H. (1975). Philosophy and our mental life. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Mind, language and reality: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 291–303). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Putnam, H. (1975). Philosophy and our mental life. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Mind, language and reality: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 291–303). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Ramsey, W. M. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Ramsey, W. M. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Stich, S. P. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge: MIT Press. Stich, S. P. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Woodward, J. (2010). Causation in biology: Stability, specificity, and the choice of levels of explanation. Biology and Philosophy, 25, 287.CrossRef Woodward, J. (2010). Causation in biology: Stability, specificity, and the choice of levels of explanation. Biology and Philosophy, 25, 287.CrossRef
go back to reference Prince, A., & Smolensky, P. (2004). Optimality theory: Constraint interaction in generative grammar. New York: Wiley.CrossRef Prince, A., & Smolensky, P. (2004). Optimality theory: Constraint interaction in generative grammar. New York: Wiley.CrossRef
Metadata
Title
Still Autonomous After All
Author
Andrew Knoll
Publication date
21-06-2017
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Minds and Machines / Issue 1/2018
Print ISSN: 0924-6495
Electronic ISSN: 1572-8641
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-017-9440-7

Other articles of this Issue 1/2018

Minds and Machines 1/2018 Go to the issue

Premium Partner