Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Minds and Machines 1/2018

03-10-2017

The Brain as an Input–Output Model of the World

Author: Oron Shagrir

Published in: Minds and Machines | Issue 1/2018

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

An underlying assumption in computational approaches in cognitive and brain sciences is that the nervous system is an input–output model of the world: Its input–output functions mirror certain relations in the target domains. I argue that the input–output modelling assumption plays distinct methodological and explanatory roles. Methodologically, input–output modelling serves to discover the computed function from environmental cues. Explanatorily, input–output modelling serves to account for the appropriateness of the computed function to the explanandum information-processing task. I compare very briefly the modelling explanation to mechanistic and optimality explanations, noting that in both cases the explanations can be seen as complementary rather than contrastive or competing.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 390 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe




 

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
See, e.g., Frigg and Hartmann (2017), Weisberg (2013).
 
2
See Swoyer (1991) for a general discussion about the relation between modelling and surrogative reasoning. See Grush (2004) for a discussion about modelling and surrogative reasoning in the brain.
 
3
Less-than-isomorphism characterizations are in terms of partial isomorphism (French and Ladyman 1999; Da Costa and French 2003), homomorphism (Bartels 2006), and similarity (Giere 2004).
 
4
The inputs and outputs need not be peripheral to the brain. In some examples discussed below we talk about sub-systems whose inputs are received and/or their outputs are projected to other parts of the nervous system. The inputs and outputs are very often (magnitude) values of certain properties such as voltages.
 
5
The term input–output representation is coined by Ramsey (2007: 68–77), who associates it with task analysis.
 
6
See also Gallistel and King: "Representations are functioning homomorphisms. They require structure-preserving mappings (homomorphisms) from states of the world (the represented system) to symbols in the brain (the representing system). These mappings preserve aspects of the formal structure of the world" (2009: x).
 
7
See, e.g., Suárez (2010).
 
8
Thus Griffiths et al. (2008) say that the big computational question that underlies the Bayesian approach is "How does the mind build rich, abstract, veridical models of the world given only the sparse and noisy data that we observe through our senses?". See also Clark (2015), who further emphasizes the central role of generative models in the hypothesis that the brain is a prediction machine.
 
9
We can say that truth-preserving is just a special case of the morphism relation.
 
10
See the reviews by Robinson (1968, 1989) and the one by Leigh and Zee (2006).
 
11
See also Goldman et al. (2002).
 
12
To keep things simpler, I will use here the terms distance and position interchangeably. New (horizontal) position is evaluated on the basis of the distance from the previous position.
 
13
Note that in Fig. 3 the term E stands for both the representing (output) neural activity and the represented eye position. Similarly the term Ė stands for both the representing (input) neural activity and the represented eye velocity. This presentation is customary in neuroscience. This sort of presentation underscores (again) the modelling assumption, as it is apparent that the integration relation holds in both representing and represented domains.
 
14
This ability is achieved by different animals. A well-known example is the desert ant (Cataglyphis fortis) that returns home after an outward travel of hundreds of meters.
 
15
See Mittelstaedt and Mittelstaedt (1982), Collett and Collett (2000), Etienne and Jeffery (2004), Conklin and Eliasmith (2005), McNaughton et al. (2006) and Gallistel and King (2009).
 
16
It has been more recently suggested that path integration in rats is computed by the grid cells located in the dorsolateral medial entorhinal cortex (dMEC) (Hafting et al. 2005).
 
17
See also Kaplan and Craver (2011), Piccinini and Craver (2011), Miłkowski (2013) and Boone and Piccinini (2016).
 
18
They also point out that a "full-blown" mechanistic explanation need not specify the entire properties of the mechanism. It should specify the entire properties that are relevant to the explanandum phenomenon; in some cases (e.g., computational explanations) these properties might all be abstract (e.g., medium-independent) properties (Boone and Piccinini 2016).
 
19
There is tension, however, about what counts as a computational explanation. Kaplan seems to claim that computational explanations in neuroscience are adequate to the extent that they describe relevant mechanisms (see also Piccinini 2015; Miłkowski 2013). We suggest that computational explanations of information-processing phenomena also involve a modelling, non-mechanistic, component (Bechtel and Shagrir 2015; Shagrir and Bechtel 2017).
 
20
Chirimuuta argues that this minimality conflicts with the more chauvinistic statements about the dominance of mechanistic explanations. Talking about the normalization model, she says that “my key claim is that the use of the term ‘normalization’ in neuroscience retains much of its original mathematical-engineering sense. It indicates a mathematical operation—a computation—not a biological mechanism”, and that this model “departs fully from the model-to-mechanism mapping framework that has been proposed as the criterion for explanatory success” (Chirimuuta 2014); she refers here to Kaplan’s model-to-mechanism mapping (3M) requirement (Kaplan 2011; Kaplan and Craver 2011). For a reply see Kaplan (2017) who argues that the implementation of the normalization equation (in different species) is an essential part of the explanation.
 
21
Colin Klein suggested that we might be dealing here with different why questions.
 
22
A similar question arises for the different algorithms that support the same function, which is why using one algorithm rather than another.
 
23
Marr writes:
Up to now I have studiously avoided using the word edge, preferring instead to discuss the detection of intensity changes and their representation by using oriented zero-crossing segments. The reason is that the term edge has a partly physical meaning—it makes us think of a real physical boundary, for example—and all we have discussed so far are the zero values of a set of roughly band-pass second-derivative filters. We have no right to call these edges, or, if we do have a right, then we must say so and why (1982: 68).
 
Literature
go back to reference Andersen, R. A., Essick, G. K., & Siegel, R. M. (1985). Encoding of spatial location by posterior parietal neurons. Science, 230, 456–458.CrossRef Andersen, R. A., Essick, G. K., & Siegel, R. M. (1985). Encoding of spatial location by posterior parietal neurons. Science, 230, 456–458.CrossRef
go back to reference Bartels, A. (2006). Defending the structural concept of representation. THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, 21, 7–19.MathSciNetMATH Bartels, A. (2006). Defending the structural concept of representation. THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, 21, 7–19.MathSciNetMATH
go back to reference Bassett, J. P., & Taube, J. S. (2001). Neural correlates for angular head velocity in the rat dorsal tegmental nucleus. Journal of Neuroscience, 21, 5740–5751. Bassett, J. P., & Taube, J. S. (2001). Neural correlates for angular head velocity in the rat dorsal tegmental nucleus. Journal of Neuroscience, 21, 5740–5751.
go back to reference Bechtel, W. (2012). Understanding endogenously active mechanisms: A scientific and philosophical challenge. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2, 233–248.CrossRef Bechtel, W. (2012). Understanding endogenously active mechanisms: A scientific and philosophical challenge. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2, 233–248.CrossRef
go back to reference Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
go back to reference Bechtel, W., & Shagrir, O. (2015). The non-redundant contributions of Marr’s three levels of analysis for explaining information-processing mechanisms. Topics in Cognitive Science, 7, 312–322.CrossRef Bechtel, W., & Shagrir, O. (2015). The non-redundant contributions of Marr’s three levels of analysis for explaining information-processing mechanisms. Topics in Cognitive Science, 7, 312–322.CrossRef
go back to reference Boone, W., & Piccinini, G. (2016). Mechanistic abstraction. Philosophy of Science, 83, 686–697.CrossRef Boone, W., & Piccinini, G. (2016). Mechanistic abstraction. Philosophy of Science, 83, 686–697.CrossRef
go back to reference Cannon, S. C., & Robinson, D. (1987). Loss of the neural integrator of the oculomotor system from brain stem lesions in monkey. Journal of Neurophysiology, 57, 1383–1409.CrossRef Cannon, S. C., & Robinson, D. (1987). Loss of the neural integrator of the oculomotor system from brain stem lesions in monkey. Journal of Neurophysiology, 57, 1383–1409.CrossRef
go back to reference Carandini, M., & Heeger, D. J. (2012). Normalization as a canonical neural computation. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 13, 51–62.CrossRef Carandini, M., & Heeger, D. J. (2012). Normalization as a canonical neural computation. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 13, 51–62.CrossRef
go back to reference Chirimuuta, M. (2014). Minimal models and canonical neural computations: The distinctness of computational explanation in neuroscience. Synthese, 191, 127–153.CrossRef Chirimuuta, M. (2014). Minimal models and canonical neural computations: The distinctness of computational explanation in neuroscience. Synthese, 191, 127–153.CrossRef
go back to reference Churchland, P. M. (2007). Neurophilosophy at work. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Churchland, P. M. (2007). Neurophilosophy at work. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Clark, A. (2015). Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Clark, A. (2015). Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Collett, M., & Collett, T. S. (2000). How do insects use path integration for their navigation? Biological Cybernetics, 83, 245–259.CrossRef Collett, M., & Collett, T. S. (2000). How do insects use path integration for their navigation? Biological Cybernetics, 83, 245–259.CrossRef
go back to reference Conklin, J., & Eliasmith, C. (2005). Controlled attractor network model of path integration in the rat. Journal of Computational Neuroscience, 18, 183–203.MathSciNetCrossRef Conklin, J., & Eliasmith, C. (2005). Controlled attractor network model of path integration in the rat. Journal of Computational Neuroscience, 18, 183–203.MathSciNetCrossRef
go back to reference Cummins, R. (1989). Meaning and mental representation. Cambridge: MIT Press. Cummins, R. (1989). Meaning and mental representation. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Da Costa, N. C. A., & French, S. (2003). Science and partial truth: A unitary understanding of models and scientific reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Da Costa, N. C. A., & French, S. (2003). Science and partial truth: A unitary understanding of models and scientific reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Dayan, P., & Abbott, L. F. (2001). Theoretical neuroscience: Computational and mathematical modeling of neural systems. Cambridge: MIT Press.MATH Dayan, P., & Abbott, L. F. (2001). Theoretical neuroscience: Computational and mathematical modeling of neural systems. Cambridge: MIT Press.MATH
go back to reference Eliasmith, C., & Anderson, C. H. (2003). Neural engineering: Computation, representation and dynamics in neurobiological systems. Cambridge: MIT Press. Eliasmith, C., & Anderson, C. H. (2003). Neural engineering: Computation, representation and dynamics in neurobiological systems. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Etienne, A. S., & Jeffery, K. J. (2004). Path integration in mammals. Hippocampus, 14, 180–192.CrossRef Etienne, A. S., & Jeffery, K. J. (2004). Path integration in mammals. Hippocampus, 14, 180–192.CrossRef
go back to reference Fodor, J. A. (1994). The elm and the expert: Mentalese and its semantics. Cambridge: MIT Press. Fodor, J. A. (1994). The elm and the expert: Mentalese and its semantics. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference French, S., & Ladyman, J. (1999). Reinflating the semantic approach. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 13, 103–121.MathSciNetCrossRefMATH French, S., & Ladyman, J. (1999). Reinflating the semantic approach. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 13, 103–121.MathSciNetCrossRefMATH
go back to reference Gallistel, C. R., & King, A. (2009). Memory and the computational brain: Why cognitive science will transform neuroscience. New York: Blackwell/Wiley.CrossRef Gallistel, C. R., & King, A. (2009). Memory and the computational brain: Why cognitive science will transform neuroscience. New York: Blackwell/Wiley.CrossRef
go back to reference Giere, R. N. (2004). How models are used to represent reality. Philosophy of Science, 71, 742–752.CrossRef Giere, R. N. (2004). How models are used to represent reality. Philosophy of Science, 71, 742–752.CrossRef
go back to reference Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, S342–S353.CrossRef Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, S342–S353.CrossRef
go back to reference Glimcher, P. W. (1999). Oculomotor control. In R. A. Wilson & F. C. Kiel (Eds.), MIT encyclopedia of cognitive science (pp. 618–620). Cambridge: MIT Press. Glimcher, P. W. (1999). Oculomotor control. In R. A. Wilson & F. C. Kiel (Eds.), MIT encyclopedia of cognitive science (pp. 618–620). Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Goldman, M. S., Kaneko, C. R., Major, G., Aksay, E., Tank, D. W., & Seung, H. S. (2002). Linear regression of eye velocity on eye position and head velocity suggests a common oculomotor neural integrator. Journal of Neurophysiology, 88, 659–665.CrossRef Goldman, M. S., Kaneko, C. R., Major, G., Aksay, E., Tank, D. W., & Seung, H. S. (2002). Linear regression of eye velocity on eye position and head velocity suggests a common oculomotor neural integrator. Journal of Neurophysiology, 88, 659–665.CrossRef
go back to reference Griffiths, T. L., Kemp, C., & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2008). Bayesian models of cognition. In R. Sun (Ed.), The Cambridge handbook of computational cognitive modeling (pp. 59–100). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Griffiths, T. L., Kemp, C., & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2008). Bayesian models of cognition. In R. Sun (Ed.), The Cambridge handbook of computational cognitive modeling (pp. 59–100). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Grush, R. (2001). The semantic challenge to computational neuroscience. In P. Machamer, R. Grush, & P. McLaughlin (Eds.), Theory and method in the neurosciences (pp. 155–172). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. Grush, R. (2001). The semantic challenge to computational neuroscience. In P. Machamer, R. Grush, & P. McLaughlin (Eds.), Theory and method in the neurosciences (pp. 155–172). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
go back to reference Grush, R. (2004). The emulation theory of representation: Motor control, imagery, and perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27, 377–442. Grush, R. (2004). The emulation theory of representation: Motor control, imagery, and perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27, 377–442.
go back to reference Hafting, T., Fyhn, M., Molden, S., Moser, M.-B., & Moser, E. I. (2005). Microstructure of a spatial map in the entorhinal cortex. Nature, 436, 801–806.CrossRef Hafting, T., Fyhn, M., Molden, S., Moser, M.-B., & Moser, E. I. (2005). Microstructure of a spatial map in the entorhinal cortex. Nature, 436, 801–806.CrossRef
go back to reference Haugeland, J. (1981). Semantic engines: An introduction to mind design. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Mind design: Philosophy, psychology, and artificial intelligence (pp. 1–34). Cambridge: MIT Press. Haugeland, J. (1981). Semantic engines: An introduction to mind design. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Mind design: Philosophy, psychology, and artificial intelligence (pp. 1–34). Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Heeger, D. J. (1992). Normalization of cell responses in cat striate cortex. Visual Neuroscience, 9, 181–197.CrossRef Heeger, D. J. (1992). Normalization of cell responses in cat striate cortex. Visual Neuroscience, 9, 181–197.CrossRef
go back to reference Hubel, D. H., & Wiesel, T. N. (1962). Receptive fields, binocular interaction and functional architecture in the cat’s visual cortex. The Journal of Physiology, 160, 106–154.CrossRef Hubel, D. H., & Wiesel, T. N. (1962). Receptive fields, binocular interaction and functional architecture in the cat’s visual cortex. The Journal of Physiology, 160, 106–154.CrossRef
go back to reference Kaplan, D. M. (2011). Explanation and description in computational neuroscience. Synthese, 183, 339–373.CrossRef Kaplan, D. M. (2011). Explanation and description in computational neuroscience. Synthese, 183, 339–373.CrossRef
go back to reference Kaplan, D. M. (2017). Neural computation, multiple realizability, and the prospects for mechanistic explanation. In Kaplan, D. M. (Ed.), Explanation and integration in mind and brain science. Oxford University Press (forthcoming). Kaplan, D. M. (2017). Neural computation, multiple realizability, and the prospects for mechanistic explanation. In Kaplan, D. M. (Ed.), Explanation and integration in mind and brain science. Oxford University Press (forthcoming).
go back to reference Kaplan, D. M., & Craver, C. F. (2011). The explanatory force of dynamical and mathematical models in neuroscience : A mechanistic perspective. Philosophy of Science, 78, 601–627.MathSciNetCrossRef Kaplan, D. M., & Craver, C. F. (2011). The explanatory force of dynamical and mathematical models in neuroscience : A mechanistic perspective. Philosophy of Science, 78, 601–627.MathSciNetCrossRef
go back to reference Leigh, R. J., & Zee, D. S. (2006). The neurology of eye movements (4th ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. Leigh, R. J., & Zee, D. S. (2006). The neurology of eye movements (4th ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Marr, D. C. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. New York: Freeman. Marr, D. C. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. New York: Freeman.
go back to reference Marr, D. C., & Hildreth, E. C. (1980). Theory of edge detection. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 207, 187–217.CrossRef Marr, D. C., & Hildreth, E. C. (1980). Theory of edge detection. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 207, 187–217.CrossRef
go back to reference McNaughton, B. L., Battaglia, F. P., Jensen, O., Moser, E. I., & Moser, M.-B. (2006). Path integration and the neural basis of the ‘cognitive map’. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 7, 663–678.CrossRef McNaughton, B. L., Battaglia, F. P., Jensen, O., Moser, E. I., & Moser, M.-B. (2006). Path integration and the neural basis of the ‘cognitive map’. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 7, 663–678.CrossRef
go back to reference Miłkowski, M. (2013). Explaining the computational mind. Cambridge: MIT Press. Miłkowski, M. (2013). Explaining the computational mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Mittelstaedt, H., & Mittelstaedt, M.-L. (1982). Homing by path integration. In F. Papi & H. G. Wallraff (Eds.), Avian navigation (pp. 290–297). Berlin: Springer.CrossRef Mittelstaedt, H., & Mittelstaedt, M.-L. (1982). Homing by path integration. In F. Papi & H. G. Wallraff (Eds.), Avian navigation (pp. 290–297). Berlin: Springer.CrossRef
go back to reference O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2009). The role of representation in computation. Cognitive Processing, 10, 53–62.CrossRef O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2009). The role of representation in computation. Cognitive Processing, 10, 53–62.CrossRef
go back to reference O’Keefe, J., & Nadel, L. (1978). The hippocampus as a cognitive map. Oxford: Clarendon Press. O’Keefe, J., & Nadel, L. (1978). The hippocampus as a cognitive map. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
go back to reference Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical computation: A mechanistic account. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefMATH Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical computation: A mechanistic account. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefMATH
go back to reference Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. F. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183, 283–311.CrossRef Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. F. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183, 283–311.CrossRef
go back to reference Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cognition: Toward a foundation for cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT Press. Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cognition: Toward a foundation for cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Ramsey, W. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Ramsey, W. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Robinson, D. A. (1968). The oculomotor control system: A review. Proceedings of the IEEE, 56, 1032–1049.CrossRef Robinson, D. A. (1968). The oculomotor control system: A review. Proceedings of the IEEE, 56, 1032–1049.CrossRef
go back to reference Robinson, D. A. (1989). Integrating with neurons. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 12, 33–45.CrossRef Robinson, D. A. (1989). Integrating with neurons. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 12, 33–45.CrossRef
go back to reference Ryder, D. (2004). SINBAD neurosemantics: A theory of mental representation. Mind and Language, 19, 211–240.CrossRef Ryder, D. (2004). SINBAD neurosemantics: A theory of mental representation. Mind and Language, 19, 211–240.CrossRef
go back to reference Seung, H. S. (1998). Continuous attractors and oculomotor control. Neural Networks, 11, 1253–1258.CrossRef Seung, H. S. (1998). Continuous attractors and oculomotor control. Neural Networks, 11, 1253–1258.CrossRef
go back to reference Shagrir, O. (2012). Structural representations and the brain. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63, 519–545.CrossRef Shagrir, O. (2012). Structural representations and the brain. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63, 519–545.CrossRef
go back to reference Shagrir, O., & Bechtel, W. (2017). Marr’s computational level and delineating phenomena. In Kaplan, D. M. (Ed.), Integrating mind and brain science: Mechanistic perspectives and beyond. Oxford University Press (forthcoming). Shagrir, O., & Bechtel, W. (2017). Marr’s computational level and delineating phenomena. In Kaplan, D. M. (Ed.), Integrating mind and brain science: Mechanistic perspectives and beyond. Oxford University Press (forthcoming).
go back to reference Shapiro, L. A. (2016). Mechanism or bust? Explanation in psychology. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science (forthcoming). Shapiro, L. A. (2016). Mechanism or bust? Explanation in psychology. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science (forthcoming).
go back to reference Sharp, P. E., Tinkelman, A., & Cho, J. (2001). Angular velocity and head direction signals recorded from the dorsal tegmental nucleus of Gudden in the rat: Implications for path integration in the head direction cell circuit. Behavioral Neuroscience, 115, 571–588.CrossRef Sharp, P. E., Tinkelman, A., & Cho, J. (2001). Angular velocity and head direction signals recorded from the dorsal tegmental nucleus of Gudden in the rat: Implications for path integration in the head direction cell circuit. Behavioral Neuroscience, 115, 571–588.CrossRef
go back to reference Suárez, M. (2010). Scientific representation. Philosophy Compass, 5, 91–101.CrossRef Suárez, M. (2010). Scientific representation. Philosophy Compass, 5, 91–101.CrossRef
go back to reference Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford University Press. Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Zipser, D., & Andersen, R. A. (1988). A back-propagation programmed network that simulates response properties of a subset of posterior parietal neurons. Nature, 331, 679–684.CrossRef Zipser, D., & Andersen, R. A. (1988). A back-propagation programmed network that simulates response properties of a subset of posterior parietal neurons. Nature, 331, 679–684.CrossRef
Metadata
Title
The Brain as an Input–Output Model of the World
Author
Oron Shagrir
Publication date
03-10-2017
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Minds and Machines / Issue 1/2018
Print ISSN: 0924-6495
Electronic ISSN: 1572-8641
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-017-9443-4

Other articles of this Issue 1/2018

Minds and Machines 1/2018 Go to the issue

Premium Partner