Skip to main content
Top
Published in: Minds and Machines 1/2018

29-05-2017

Towards a Cognitive Neuroscience of Intentionality

Authors: Alex Morgan, Gualtiero Piccinini

Published in: Minds and Machines | Issue 1/2018

Log in

Activate our intelligent search to find suitable subject content or patents.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

We situate the debate on intentionality within the rise of cognitive neuroscience and argue that cognitive neuroscience can explain intentionality. We discuss the explanatory significance of ascribing intentionality to representations. At first, we focus on views that attempt to render such ascriptions naturalistic by construing them in a deflationary or merely pragmatic way. We then contrast these views with staunchly realist views that attempt to naturalize intentionality by developing theories of content for representations in terms of information and biological function. We echo several other philosophers by arguing that these theories over-generalize unless they are constrained by a theory of the functional role of representational vehicles. This leads to a discussion of the functional roles of representations, and how representations might be realized in the brain. We argue that there’s work to be done to identify a distinctively mental kind of representation. We close by sketching a way forward for the project of naturalizing intentionality. This will not be achieved simply by ascribing the content of mental states to generic neural representations, but by identifying specific neural representations that explain the puzzling intentional properties of mental states.

Dont have a licence yet? Then find out more about our products and how to get one now:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 390 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe




 

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Footnotes
1
This strategy underlies a great deal of research in philosophy of mind throughout the late twentieth century; Fodor (1987) makes the strategy explicit.
 
2
For influential philosophical discussions of the mechanistic explanatory paradigm that is widely regarded as the dominant mode of explanation throughout the life sciences, see Bechtel and Richardson (2010), Machamer et al. (2000). For a discussion of how attempts to explain life fit within the mechanistic paradigm, see Bechtel (2011).
 
3
For arguments that computational cognitive neuroscience provides psychological explanations that fit within the mechanistic paradigm, see Bechtel (2008), Kaplan (2011), Piccinini and Craver (2011), Boone and Piccinini (2016).
 
4
The distinction here echoes the distinction between ‘content’ and ‘state’ views of non-conceptual content (Heck 2000).
 
Literature
go back to reference Amit, D. (1989). Modelling brain function: The world of attractor neural networks. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefMATH Amit, D. (1989). Modelling brain function: The world of attractor neural networks. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefMATH
go back to reference Anscombe, E. (1957). Intention. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Anscombe, E. (1957). Intention. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
go back to reference Bechtel, W. (1998). Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist’s challenge in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 22(3), 295–318.CrossRef Bechtel, W. (1998). Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist’s challenge in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 22(3), 295–318.CrossRef
go back to reference Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms. New York: Taylor and Francis. Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms. New York: Taylor and Francis.
go back to reference Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. (2010). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. (2010). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Blakemore, R., & Frankel, R. (1981). Magnetic navigation in bacteria. Scientific American, 6, 58–65.CrossRef Blakemore, R., & Frankel, R. (1981). Magnetic navigation in bacteria. Scientific American, 6, 58–65.CrossRef
go back to reference Block, N. (1986). Advertisement for a semantics for psychology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10, 615–678.CrossRef Block, N. (1986). Advertisement for a semantics for psychology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10, 615–678.CrossRef
go back to reference Boone, W., & Piccinini, G. (2016). The cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese, 193(5), 1509–1534.CrossRef Boone, W., & Piccinini, G. (2016). The cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese, 193(5), 1509–1534.CrossRef
go back to reference Brentano, F. (1874 [1995]). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. London: Routledge. Brentano, F. (1874 [1995]). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. London: Routledge.
go back to reference Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47(1–3), 139–159.CrossRef Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47(1–3), 139–159.CrossRef
go back to reference Chisholm, R. (1955). Sentences about believing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 125–148.CrossRef Chisholm, R. (1955). Sentences about believing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 125–148.CrossRef
go back to reference Chisholm, R. (1957). Perceiving: A philosophical study. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Chisholm, R. (1957). Perceiving: A philosophical study. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
go back to reference Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1992). The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATH Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1992). The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATH
go back to reference Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101(3), 401–431.CrossRef Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101(3), 401–431.CrossRef
go back to reference Craik, K. (1943). The nature of explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Craik, K. (1943). The nature of explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Cummins, R. (1983). The nature of psychological explanation. Cambridge: MIT Press. Cummins, R. (1983). The nature of psychological explanation. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Cummins, R. (1989). Meaning and mental representation. Cambridge: MIT Press. Cummins, R. (1989). Meaning and mental representation. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets, and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets, and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
go back to reference Dennett, D. (1978). Artificial intelligence as philosophy and as psychology. In his ‘Brainstorms’ (pp. 109–126). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Dennett, D. (1978). Artificial intelligence as philosophy and as psychology. In his ‘Brainstorms’ (pp. 109–126). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Denève, S., Duhamel, J.-R., & Pouget, A. (2007). Optimal sensorimotor integration in recurrent cortical networks: A neural implementation of kalman filters. Journal of Neuroscience, 27(21), 5744–5756.CrossRef Denève, S., Duhamel, J.-R., & Pouget, A. (2007). Optimal sensorimotor integration in recurrent cortical networks: A neural implementation of kalman filters. Journal of Neuroscience, 27(21), 5744–5756.CrossRef
go back to reference Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATH Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATH
go back to reference Dretske, F. (1986). Misrepresentation. In R. Bogdan (Ed.), Form, content, and function (pp. 157–173). Oxford: Clarendon. Dretske, F. (1986). Misrepresentation. In R. Bogdan (Ed.), Form, content, and function (pp. 157–173). Oxford: Clarendon.
go back to reference Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Eliasmith, C., & Anderson, C. (2003). Neural engineering: Computation, Representation, and dynamics in neurobiological systems. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Eliasmith, C., & Anderson, C. (2003). Neural engineering: Computation, Representation, and dynamics in neurobiological systems. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. New York, NY: Crowell. Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. New York, NY: Crowell.
go back to reference Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Gallistel, C. (1990). Representations in animal cognition: An introduction. Cognition, 37(1–2), 1–22.CrossRef Gallistel, C. (1990). Representations in animal cognition: An introduction. Cognition, 37(1–2), 1–22.CrossRef
go back to reference Gallistel, C. (2008). Learning and representation. In J. Byrne (Ed.), Learning and memory: A comprehensive reference (pp. 227–242). Amsterdam: Elsevier.CrossRef Gallistel, C. (2008). Learning and representation. In J. Byrne (Ed.), Learning and memory: A comprehensive reference (pp. 227–242). Amsterdam: Elsevier.CrossRef
go back to reference Grush, R. (2003). In defense of some ‘Cartesian’ assumptions concerning the brain and its operation. Biology and Philosophy, 18(1), 53–93.CrossRef Grush, R. (2003). In defense of some ‘Cartesian’ assumptions concerning the brain and its operation. Biology and Philosophy, 18(1), 53–93.CrossRef
go back to reference Grush, R. (2004). The emulation theory of representation: Motor control, imagery, and perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27(3), 377–396. Grush, R. (2004). The emulation theory of representation: Motor control, imagery, and perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27(3), 377–396.
go back to reference Grush, R. (2008). Representation reconsidered by William M. Ramsey, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. Grush, R. (2008). Representation reconsidered by William M. Ramsey, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews.
go back to reference Harman, G. (1970). Sellars’ semantics. The Philosophical Review, 79(3), 404–419.CrossRef Harman, G. (1970). Sellars’ semantics. The Philosophical Review, 79(3), 404–419.CrossRef
go back to reference Harman, G. (1973). Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Harman, G. (1973). Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
go back to reference Harman, G. (1987). (Non-solipsistic) conceptual role semantics. In E. Lepore (Ed.), New directions in semantics. London: Academic Press. Harman, G. (1987). (Non-solipsistic) conceptual role semantics. In E. Lepore (Ed.), New directions in semantics. London: Academic Press.
go back to reference Harman, G. (1988). Wide functionalism. In S. Schiffer & S. Steele (Eds.), Cognition and representation. Boulder: Westview. Harman, G. (1988). Wide functionalism. In S. Schiffer & S. Steele (Eds.), Cognition and representation. Boulder: Westview.
go back to reference Hebb, D. (1949). The organization of behavior: A neuropsychological theory. New York, NY: Wiley. Hebb, D. (1949). The organization of behavior: A neuropsychological theory. New York, NY: Wiley.
go back to reference Heck, R. (2000). Nonconceptual content and the ‘Space of Reasons’. Philosophical Review, 109(4), 483–523.CrossRef Heck, R. (2000). Nonconceptual content and the ‘Space of Reasons’. Philosophical Review, 109(4), 483–523.CrossRef
go back to reference Horgan, T., & Tienson, J. (2002). The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings (pp. 520–933). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Horgan, T., & Tienson, J. (2002). The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings (pp. 520–933). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Isaac, A. (2013). Objective similarity and mental representation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(4), 683–704.CrossRef Isaac, A. (2013). Objective similarity and mental representation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(4), 683–704.CrossRef
go back to reference Jacob, P. (1997). What minds can do: Intentionality in a non-intentional world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Jacob, P. (1997). What minds can do: Intentionality in a non-intentional world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Kaplan, D. (2011). Explanation and description in computational neuroscience. Synthese, 183(3), 339–373.CrossRef Kaplan, D. (2011). Explanation and description in computational neuroscience. Synthese, 183(3), 339–373.CrossRef
go back to reference Kriegel, U. (Ed.). (2013). Phenomenal intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kriegel, U. (Ed.). (2013). Phenomenal intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Kriegel, U. (2016). Brentano’s mature theory of intentionality. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, 4(2), 1–15.CrossRef Kriegel, U. (2016). Brentano’s mature theory of intentionality. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, 4(2), 1–15.CrossRef
go back to reference Loar, B. (1981). Mind and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Loar, B. (1981). Mind and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Loar, B. (2003). Phenomenal intentionality as the basis of mental content. In M. Hahn & B. Ramberg (Eds.), Reflections and replies: Essays on the philosophy of Tyler Burge (pp. 229–258). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Loar, B. (2003). Phenomenal intentionality as the basis of mental content. In M. Hahn & B. Ramberg (Eds.), Reflections and replies: Essays on the philosophy of Tyler Burge (pp. 229–258). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Locke, J. (1824 [1696]). The works of John Locke (Vol. 3, 12th Ed.). Rivington: London. Locke, J. (1824 [1696]). The works of John Locke (Vol. 3, 12th Ed.). Rivington: London.
go back to reference McCulloch, W., & Pitts, W. (1943). A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics, 5, 115–133.MathSciNetCrossRefMATH McCulloch, W., & Pitts, W. (1943). A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics, 5, 115–133.MathSciNetCrossRefMATH
go back to reference Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Millikan, R. (1989). Biosemantics. The Journal of Philosophy, 86(6), 281–297.CrossRef Millikan, R. (1989). Biosemantics. The Journal of Philosophy, 86(6), 281–297.CrossRef
go back to reference Millikan, R. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Millikan, R. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Millikan, R. (2000). Naturalizing intentionality. The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, 9, 83–90. Millikan, R. (2000). Naturalizing intentionality. The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, 9, 83–90.
go back to reference Morgan, A. (2014). Representations gone mental. Synthese, 191(2), 213–244.CrossRef Morgan, A. (2014). Representations gone mental. Synthese, 191(2), 213–244.CrossRef
go back to reference O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2004). Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation. In H. Clapin, P. Staines, & P. Slezac (Eds.), Representation in mind (pp. 1–20). Amsterdam: Elsevier. O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2004). Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation. In H. Clapin, P. Staines, & P. Slezac (Eds.), Representation in mind (pp. 1–20). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
go back to reference Peacocke, C. (1992). A study of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATH Peacocke, C. (1992). A study of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATH
go back to reference Piccinini, G. (2004). The first computational theory of mind and brain: A close look at McMulloch and Pitts’s ‘Calculus of Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity’. Synthese, 141(2), 175–215.MathSciNetCrossRef Piccinini, G. (2004). The first computational theory of mind and brain: A close look at McMulloch and Pitts’s ‘Calculus of Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity’. Synthese, 141(2), 175–215.MathSciNetCrossRef
go back to reference Piccinini, G. (forthcoming). Nonnatural mental representation. In K. Dolega, T. Schlicht, J. Smortchkova (Eds.), What are mental representations? Oxford: Oxford University Press. Piccinini, G. (forthcoming). Nonnatural mental representation. In K. Dolega, T. Schlicht, J. Smortchkova (Eds.), What are mental representations? Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183(3), 283–311.CrossRef Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183(3), 283–311.CrossRef
go back to reference Pietroski, P. (1992). Intentionality and teleological error. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 73(3), 267–282.CrossRef Pietroski, P. (1992). Intentionality and teleological error. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 73(3), 267–282.CrossRef
go back to reference Pylyshyn, Z. (1984). Computation and cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Pylyshyn, Z. (1984). Computation and cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Quine, W. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATH Quine, W. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATH
go back to reference Ramsey, W. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Ramsey, W. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Ramsey, W. (2016). Untangling two questions about mental representation. New Ideas in Psychology, 40, 3–12.CrossRef Ramsey, W. (2016). Untangling two questions about mental representation. New Ideas in Psychology, 40, 3–12.CrossRef
go back to reference Rolls, E. (2007). Memory, attention, and decision-making: A unifying computational neuroscience approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Rolls, E. (2007). Memory, attention, and decision-making: A unifying computational neuroscience approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Ryder, R. (2004). SINBAD neurosemantics: A theory of mental representation. Mind and Language, 19(2), 211–240.CrossRef Ryder, R. (2004). SINBAD neurosemantics: A theory of mental representation. Mind and Language, 19(2), 211–240.CrossRef
go back to reference Samsonovich, A., & McNaughton, B. (1997). Path Integration and cognitive mapping in a continuous attractor neural network model. Journal of Neuroscience, 17(15), 5900–5920. Samsonovich, A., & McNaughton, B. (1997). Path Integration and cognitive mapping in a continuous attractor neural network model. Journal of Neuroscience, 17(15), 5900–5920.
go back to reference Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Sellars, W. (1954). Some reflections on language games. Philosophy of Science, 21, 204–228.CrossRef Sellars, W. (1954). Some reflections on language games. Philosophy of Science, 21, 204–228.CrossRef
go back to reference Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1(19), 253–329. Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1(19), 253–329.
go back to reference Seung, S. (1998). Continuous attractors and oculomotor control. Neural Networks, 11(7–8), 1253–1258.CrossRef Seung, S. (1998). Continuous attractors and oculomotor control. Neural Networks, 11(7–8), 1253–1258.CrossRef
go back to reference Shagrir, O. (2012). Structural representations and the brain. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(3), 519–545.CrossRef Shagrir, O. (2012). Structural representations and the brain. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(3), 519–545.CrossRef
go back to reference Shepard, R., & Chipman, S. (1970). Second-order isomorphism of internal representations: Shapes of states. Cognitive Psychology, 1(1), 1–17.CrossRef Shepard, R., & Chipman, S. (1970). Second-order isomorphism of internal representations: Shapes of states. Cognitive Psychology, 1(1), 1–17.CrossRef
go back to reference Sprevak, M. (2011). Review of Representation Reconsidered by William Ramsey. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 669–675.CrossRef Sprevak, M. (2011). Review of Representation Reconsidered by William Ramsey. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 669–675.CrossRef
go back to reference Sterelny, K. (1995). Basic minds. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 251–270.CrossRef Sterelny, K. (1995). Basic minds. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 251–270.CrossRef
go back to reference Stich, S. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Stich, S. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference Turing, A. (1936). On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 42(2), 230–265.MathSciNetMATH Turing, A. (1936). On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 42(2), 230–265.MathSciNetMATH
go back to reference Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
go back to reference van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation. The Journal of Philosophy, 92(7), 345–381.CrossRef van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation. The Journal of Philosophy, 92(7), 345–381.CrossRef
go back to reference Wang, X. (2001). Synaptic reverberation underlying mnemonic persistent activity. Trends in Neurosciences, 24(8), 455–463.CrossRef Wang, X. (2001). Synaptic reverberation underlying mnemonic persistent activity. Trends in Neurosciences, 24(8), 455–463.CrossRef
go back to reference Watson, J. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological Review, 20(2), 158.CrossRef Watson, J. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological Review, 20(2), 158.CrossRef
go back to reference Wolpert, D., et al. (2003). A unifying computational framework for motor control and social interaction. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 358(1431), 593–602.CrossRef Wolpert, D., et al. (2003). A unifying computational framework for motor control and social interaction. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 358(1431), 593–602.CrossRef
Metadata
Title
Towards a Cognitive Neuroscience of Intentionality
Authors
Alex Morgan
Gualtiero Piccinini
Publication date
29-05-2017
Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Published in
Minds and Machines / Issue 1/2018
Print ISSN: 0924-6495
Electronic ISSN: 1572-8641
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-017-9437-2

Other articles of this Issue 1/2018

Minds and Machines 1/2018 Go to the issue

Premium Partner