Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Public Choice 3-4/2022

24.06.2019

Behavioral economics and the Virginia school of political economy: overlaps and complementarities

verfasst von: Roger D. Congleton

Erschienen in: Public Choice | Ausgabe 3-4/2022

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

A variety of complementarities and overlaps exist between the psychological strand of behavioral economics and the subjectivist strand of Virginia Political Economy. This paper provides an overview of those commonalities and places them in a common information processing framework. The framework can account for systematic mistakes, framing effects, subjectivity, individual variety, and several issues in constitutional political economy. It also reveals many commonalities between these two quite different approaches to human behavior.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
I hesitate to cite specific works by these prolific scholars as typical of their research—or at least those parts that I am referring to here. The best overviews of their research is provided by Nobel lectures in cases in which a scholar has won that prize, as with Simon (1979) and Kahneman (2002). A good place start with the other two scholars is Thaler (1980) and with Tversky’s joint work with Kahneman: Tversky and Kahneman (1973, 1986).
 
2
Again, it with great hesitation that I point to one or two works out of a lifetime of scholarship. For Smith, one should begin with his 2003 Nobel address; for Plott a good place to start is with his 2014 overview of the early days of experimental public choice research.
 
3
There are several very lengthy compendia of the works of the Jeremy Bentham and Herbert Spencer. However, a good place to start is with Bentham (1789). Herbert Spencer’s works are also voluminous; I suggest beginning with his first successful book, Spencer (1851) and focus on the sections dealing with the evolution of the physical and social sources of utility.
 
4
Information-processing models of the mind had previously played central roles in adaptive models of economics. They are also central to a strand of post-World War II psychological research. See, for example, Kahneman (2002, 2011), Pinker (1999, 2003) and Seligman et al. (2016). Informationally bounded rationality also affected economics and politics, as in Stigler (1961), Downs (1960), and Denzau and North (1994), the latter being the most encompassing of the early discussions by economists. Congleton (1978) is among the first general explorations of informationally bounded choice within the Virginia school.
 
5
A useful example of the super-rational approach to political economy is Wittman’s (1995) book on the impossibility of democratic failure.
 
6
The Virginia school has its roots in two centers: the Thomas Jefferson Center for the Studies in Political Economy and Social Philosophy at the University of Virginia and the Center for Study of Public Choice at the Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University and George Mason University (to which it relocated in the early 1980 s).
This essay focuses for the most part on scholars directly associated with these “Centers”, but it bears noting that the Virginia school also includes persons without long affiliations with those centers, such as Mancur Olson, Elinor Ostrom, Dennis Mueller, Charles Goetz, Charles Plott, Geoffrey Brennan, Bruno Frey, Peter Bernholz, Arye Hillman, Randall Holcombe, Gephard Kirchgässner and Michael Munger—many of whom are past visitors to the Center for Study of Public Choice, graduates of its Ph.D. programs, or regular presenters in its seminar series. I am a long-term affiliate—having variously been a student, graduate, research associate and center director during a period spanning more than four decades.
 
7
For overviews, see Houser and Stratmann (2012), Plott (2014), Kamm and Schram (2018), or Tyran and Wagner (2018). For a thorough overview of tensions between mainstream rational choice models and experimental results, see Ostrom (1998).
 
8
By “natural ignorance” is meant the state of individual knowledge at birth. As mentioned in the text, we are born largely ignorant of all things. Some knowledge is acquired without intent, as for example, that imparted by our parents and stumbled on by accident. Other is consciously sought and acquired. “Rational ignorance” is that part of one’s ignorance that is chosen. That is to say, it exists in cases in which one consciously decides not to pursue a type of information known to exist—such as the Chinese alphabet (for most persons not of Asian descent), quantum mechanics (for those other than professional physicists), and the color of a contemporary rock star’s eyes (for all but the most devoted fans), and so forth. These are cases in which a type or class of information is known to exist, but we (or most of us) choose to remain ignorant.
 
9
Such differences would exist even if we were all perfectly rational Bayesians because our direct experiences in life provide only relatively small samples of the choice settings confronted by human beings and the phenomena that we refer to as the “real world”. If our informational systems are not fundamentally Bayesian, no such convergence would necessarily follow from even very large samples.
For applications of the Bayesian approach to economics, see Stoneman (1981); for an early application to public choice, see Congleton (1991). More recently, Bayesian learning has played a key role in machine-learning algorithms; see Taylor and Stone (2009) or Ghavamzadeh et al. (2015). Many economists and game theorists use Baysesian updating as their reference point for rationality and the absence of long-term bias, as for example, in Charness and Chetan (2017).
 
10
This expression evidently was the invention of Ralph Waldo Emerson (1849), who argues that one should not worry about consistency, but then concludes that “There will be an agreement in whatever variety of actions, so they be each honest and natural in their hour. For of one will, the actions will be harmonious, however unlike they seem.” The potential irrationality of political decisionmaking was emphasized more recently by Black (1948) and Arrow (1951), who noted that political choices may be inconsistent even if the choices of individual voters are entirely self-consistent. The consistency (or lack thereof) of collective choice captured much of the attention and imagination of public choice theorists for its first four decades.
 
11
It should be acknowledged that few mainstream economists actually believe that consumers behave entirely self-consistently or that every individual behaves in a manner that can be regarded as having emerged from fully informed and consistent plans, but many do believe that models based on those assumptions provide useful insights into both individual decisionmaking and political-economic systems.
 
12
Downs (1960) also implicitly used natural ignorance to suggest the possibility of biased expectations or complete ignorance about the costs and benefits of government policies. Note that this differed from Stigler’s (1961) theory of the demand for information, which is essentially a demand for sample sizes, from which unbiased estimates would always be possible, albeit with larger error terms associated with smaller samples. Congleton (2001) clarifies this distinction.
 
13
My use of the term “clusters” may make it sound as if a sharp break exists among groups of individuals or researchers. Clusters of researchers or research circles are more like colors than atoms. That is to say, they are (improper) subsets along a continuum of research interests and approaches that are sufficiently similar to be identified as a category, rather than completely non-overlapping groups. In Denzau and North’s (1994) terms, members of such categories share mental models.
 
14
This is not entirely a coincidence–Sunstein has long served on the editorial board of Constitutional Political Economy.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Arrow, K. J. (1951). Social choice and individual values. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Arrow, K. J. (1951). Social choice and individual values. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Bentham, J. (1789/2013). An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. (Reprinted from Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham, Minerva Classics, Kindle Edition). Bentham, J. (1789/2013). An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. (Reprinted from Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham, Minerva Classics, Kindle Edition).
Zurück zum Zitat Black, D. (1948). On the rationale of group decision-making. Journal of Political Economy, 56(1), 23–34.CrossRef Black, D. (1948). On the rationale of group decision-making. Journal of Political Economy, 56(1), 23–34.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. M. (1985/2008). The reason of rules: Constitutional political economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. M. (1985/2008). The reason of rules: Constitutional political economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Buchanan, J. M. (1958). Public principles of public debt a defense and restatement. Homewood, IL: Irwin. Buchanan, J. M. (1958). Public principles of public debt a defense and restatement. Homewood, IL: Irwin.
Zurück zum Zitat Buchanan, J. M. (1978/1999). Natural and artifactual man. The collected works of James M. Buchanan, Vol 1, The logical foundations of constitutional liberty. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund. Buchanan, J. M. (1978/1999). Natural and artifactual man. The collected works of James M. Buchanan, Vol 1, The logical foundations of constitutional liberty. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
Zurück zum Zitat Buchanan, J. M. (1979). General implications of subjectivism in economics. What Should Economists Do?. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund. Buchanan, J. M. (1979). General implications of subjectivism in economics. What Should Economists Do?. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
Zurück zum Zitat Buchanan, J. M., & Congleton, R. D. (1998/2006). Politics by principle, not interest: Towards nondiscriminatory democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Buchanan, J. M., & Congleton, R. D. (1998/2006). Politics by principle, not interest: Towards nondiscriminatory democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent. Ann Arbor MI: University of Michigan Press. Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent. Ann Arbor MI: University of Michigan Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Buchanan, J. M., & Vanberg, V. J. (2002). Constitutional implications of radical subjectivism. Review of Austrian Economics, 15(2–3), 121–129.CrossRef Buchanan, J. M., & Vanberg, V. J. (2002). Constitutional implications of radical subjectivism. Review of Austrian Economics, 15(2–3), 121–129.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Charness, G., & Chetan, D. (2017). Confirmation bias with motivated beliefs. Games and Economic Behavior, 104(July), 1–23.CrossRef Charness, G., & Chetan, D. (2017). Confirmation bias with motivated beliefs. Games and Economic Behavior, 104(July), 1–23.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Congleton, R. D. (1978). The role of information in choice. Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University Dissertation. Congleton, R. D. (1978). The role of information in choice. Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University Dissertation.
Zurück zum Zitat Congleton, R. D. (1991). Ideological conviction and persuasion in the rent-seeking society. Journal of Public Economics, 44(1), 65–86.CrossRef Congleton, R. D. (1991). Ideological conviction and persuasion in the rent-seeking society. Journal of Public Economics, 44(1), 65–86.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Congleton, R. D. (2001). Rational ignorance, rational voter expectations, and public policy: A discrete informational foundation for fiscal illusion. Public Choice, 107(1–2), 35–64.CrossRef Congleton, R. D. (2001). Rational ignorance, rational voter expectations, and public policy: A discrete informational foundation for fiscal illusion. Public Choice, 107(1–2), 35–64.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Congleton, R. D. (2019). Toward a rule-based model of human choice: On the nature of homo constitutionalus. In R. E. Wagner (Ed.), James M. Buchanan: A theorist of political economy and social philosophy. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. Congleton, R. D. (2019). Toward a rule-based model of human choice: On the nature of homo constitutionalus. In R. E. Wagner (Ed.), James M. Buchanan: A theorist of political economy and social philosophy. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Zurück zum Zitat Congleton, R. D., & Hillman, A. L. (2015). Companion to the political economy of rent seeking. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.CrossRef Congleton, R. D., & Hillman, A. L. (2015). Companion to the political economy of rent seeking. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Debreu, G. (1959). Theory of value: An axiomatic analysis of economic equilibrium. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Debreu, G. (1959). Theory of value: An axiomatic analysis of economic equilibrium. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Denzau, A. T., & North, D. C. (1994). Shared mental models: Ideologies and institutions. Kyklos, 47(1), 3–31.CrossRef Denzau, A. T., & North, D. C. (1994). Shared mental models: Ideologies and institutions. Kyklos, 47(1), 3–31.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Downs, A. (1960). Why the government budget is too small in a democracy. World Politics, 12(4), 541–563.CrossRef Downs, A. (1960). Why the government budget is too small in a democracy. World Politics, 12(4), 541–563.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Emerson, R. W. (1849). Self-reliance. (Reprinted from Emerson, Ralph Waldo. Self-Reliance and Other Essays, Kindle Edition, 2017, Seattle WA: Amazon Classics). Emerson, R. W. (1849). Self-reliance. (Reprinted from Emerson, Ralph Waldo. Self-Reliance and Other Essays, Kindle Edition, 2017, Seattle WA: Amazon Classics).
Zurück zum Zitat Ghavamzadeh, M., Mannor, S., Pineau, J., & Tamar, A. (2015). Bayesian reinforcement learning: A survey. Foundations and Trends in Machine Learning, 8(5–6), 359–483.CrossRef Ghavamzadeh, M., Mannor, S., Pineau, J., & Tamar, A. (2015). Bayesian reinforcement learning: A survey. Foundations and Trends in Machine Learning, 8(5–6), 359–483.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Heiner, R. A. (1983). The origin of predictable behavior. American Economic Review, 73(4), 560–595. Heiner, R. A. (1983). The origin of predictable behavior. American Economic Review, 73(4), 560–595.
Zurück zum Zitat Holcombe, R. (2018). Political capitalism: How political influence is made and maintained. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Holcombe, R. (2018). Political capitalism: How political influence is made and maintained. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Houser, D., & Stratmann, T. (2012). Gordon Tullock and experimental economics. Public Choice, 152(1–2), 211–222.CrossRef Houser, D., & Stratmann, T. (2012). Gordon Tullock and experimental economics. Public Choice, 152(1–2), 211–222.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kahneman, D. (2002). Maps of bounded rationality: A perspective on intuitive judgment and choice. Nobel prize lecture, 8, 351–401. Kahneman, D. (2002). Maps of bounded rationality: A perspective on intuitive judgment and choice. Nobel prize lecture, 8, 351–401.
Zurück zum Zitat Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Macmillan. Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Macmillan.
Zurück zum Zitat Kamm, A. & Schram, A. (2018). Experimental public choice: elections. Oxford Handbook of Public Choice (Vol. 2, Ch. 44). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kamm, A. & Schram, A. (2018). Experimental public choice: elections. Oxford Handbook of Public Choice (Vol. 2, Ch. 44). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Ostrom, E. (1998). A behavioral approach to the rational choice theory of collective action. Presidential Address, American Political Science Association, 1997. American Political Science Review, 92(01), 1–22.CrossRef Ostrom, E. (1998). A behavioral approach to the rational choice theory of collective action. Presidential Address, American Political Science Association, 1997. American Political Science Review, 92(01), 1–22.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Pinker, S. (1999). How the mind works. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 882(1), 119–127.CrossRef Pinker, S. (1999). How the mind works. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 882(1), 119–127.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Pinker, S. (2003). The blank slate: The modern denial of human nature. New York: Penguin Group. Pinker, S. (2003). The blank slate: The modern denial of human nature. New York: Penguin Group.
Zurück zum Zitat Plott, C. R. (2014). Public choice and the development of modern laboratory experimental methods in economics and political science. Constitutional Political Economy, 25(4), 331–353.CrossRef Plott, C. R. (2014). Public choice and the development of modern laboratory experimental methods in economics and political science. Constitutional Political Economy, 25(4), 331–353.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Seligman, M. E., Railton, P., Baumeister, R. F., & Sripada, C. (2016). Homo prospectus. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Seligman, M. E., Railton, P., Baumeister, R. F., & Sripada, C. (2016). Homo prospectus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Shackle, G. L. S. (1969/2010). Decision order and time in human affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Shackle, G. L. S. (1969/2010). Decision order and time in human affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Simon, H. A. (1979). Rational decision making in business organizations. American Economic Review, 69(4), 493–513. Simon, H. A. (1979). Rational decision making in business organizations. American Economic Review, 69(4), 493–513.
Zurück zum Zitat Smith, V. L. (2003). Constructivist and ecological rationality in economics. American Economic Review, 93(3), 465–508.CrossRef Smith, V. L. (2003). Constructivist and ecological rationality in economics. American Economic Review, 93(3), 465–508.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Spencer, H. (1851). Social statics: Or, the conditions essential to happiness specified, and the first of them developed. London: John Chapman. Spencer, H. (1851). Social statics: Or, the conditions essential to happiness specified, and the first of them developed. London: John Chapman.
Zurück zum Zitat Stigler, G. J. (1961). The economics of information. Journal of Political Economy, 69(3), 213–225.CrossRef Stigler, G. J. (1961). The economics of information. Journal of Political Economy, 69(3), 213–225.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Stoneman, P. (1981). Intra-firm diffusion, Bayesian learning and profitability. Economic Journal, 91(362), 375–388.CrossRef Stoneman, P. (1981). Intra-firm diffusion, Bayesian learning and profitability. Economic Journal, 91(362), 375–388.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Sunstein, C. R. (2014). Why nudge? The politics of libertarian paternalism. New Haven CT: Yale University Press. Sunstein, C. R. (2014). Why nudge? The politics of libertarian paternalism. New Haven CT: Yale University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Taylor, M. E., & Stone, P. (2009). Transfer learning for reinforcement learning domains: A survey. Journal of Machine Learning Research, 10, 1633–1685. Taylor, M. E., & Stone, P. (2009). Transfer learning for reinforcement learning domains: A survey. Journal of Machine Learning Research, 10, 1633–1685.
Zurück zum Zitat Thaler, R. (1980). Toward a positive theory of consumer choice. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 1(1), 39–60.CrossRef Thaler, R. (1980). Toward a positive theory of consumer choice. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 1(1), 39–60.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. R. (2008). Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New York: Penguin Group. Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. R. (2008). Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New York: Penguin Group.
Zurück zum Zitat Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology, 5(2), 207–232.CrossRef Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology, 5(2), 207–232.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1986). Rational choice and the framing of decisions. Journal of Business, 59, S251–S278.CrossRef Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1986). Rational choice and the framing of decisions. Journal of Business, 59, S251–S278.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Tyran, J. R. & Wagner, A. K. (2018). Experimental Evidence on Expressive Voting. Oxford Handbook of Public Choice (Vol. 2, Ch. 45). Oxford UK: Oxford University Press. Tyran, J. R. & Wagner, A. K. (2018). Experimental Evidence on Expressive Voting. Oxford Handbook of Public Choice (Vol. 2, Ch. 45). Oxford UK: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Vanberg, V. J. (1994). Rules and choice in economics. New York: Taylor & Francis.CrossRef Vanberg, V. J. (1994). Rules and choice in economics. New York: Taylor & Francis.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Wagner, R. E. (1976). Revenue structure, fiscal illusion, and budgetary choice. Public Choice, 25(1), 45–61.CrossRef Wagner, R. E. (1976). Revenue structure, fiscal illusion, and budgetary choice. Public Choice, 25(1), 45–61.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Wagner, R. E., & Weber, W. E. (1977). Wagner’s law, fiscal institutions, and the growth of government. National Tax Journal, 30, 59–68.CrossRef Wagner, R. E., & Weber, W. E. (1977). Wagner’s law, fiscal institutions, and the growth of government. National Tax Journal, 30, 59–68.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Wittman, D. A. (1995). The myth of democratic failure: Why political institutions are efficient. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Wittman, D. A. (1995). The myth of democratic failure: Why political institutions are efficient. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Metadaten
Titel
Behavioral economics and the Virginia school of political economy: overlaps and complementarities
verfasst von
Roger D. Congleton
Publikationsdatum
24.06.2019
Verlag
Springer US
Erschienen in
Public Choice / Ausgabe 3-4/2022
Print ISSN: 0048-5829
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-7101
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00679-3

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 3-4/2022

Public Choice 3-4/2022 Zur Ausgabe

Premium Partner