Skip to main content

2018 | OriginalPaper | Buchkapitel

Constitutions as Conventions: A History of Non-reception

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Russell Hardin’s theory of constitutions as conventions implies several conclusions that are striking, deep, important, counterintuitive, and very hard to deny. Nevertheless, they have had little influence on the field of political theory. This chapter seeks to explain that through two theses. (1) The theory embarrasses the prevailing schools of political thought (participatory and/or deliberative democracy, “high” or rationalist liberalism, and Cambridge historicism) not just by denying their doctrines but by suggesting the irrelevance of many of their favorite questions. (2) The theory seems, as Hardin presents it, more pessimistic and quietist than it needs to be. This chapter suggests that the theory contains within it under-stressed resources that make room for constant institutional progress and political reform.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Anhänge
Nur mit Berechtigung zugänglich
Fußnoten
1
The politics in question consisted, roughly, of (democratic) socialism cum participatory democracy.
 
2
One reason the theory has found it hard to gain purchase might that the relevant volumes embody diverse genres. Hardin (1982) is mostly formal, though non-technical. Hardin (1995) is more or less a work in comparative politics. Hardin (1999) is largely historical. And Hardin (2007) is interpretive. To understand the theory’s full implications and force, one must, alas, read all four.
 
3
Compare Sabl (2012), Chapters 1 and 4.
 
4
An anecdote: when I mentioned to a top Yale graduate student that Hardin’s work was underappreciated, he replied, somewhat surprised, that One for All was quite widely assigned in courses on ethnic conflict. When I clarified that I meant the work was underappreciated in political theory, he replied, “Oh, of course it’s not read in political theory.”
 
5
 
6
The power attaching to leaders who are in a position to solve coordination problems, as well as collectively to a government granted this power by institutions, is noted by Hardin (1999: 102, 107, and esp. 114) and appears as early as Schelling (1960, Chap. 3). For an extended treatment see Calvert (1992). Ian Kershaw’s short book Hitler (2000) could be seen as a primer on how to leverage the coordination power attaching to the extra-constitutional role of leader, or Führer, into vast and terrifying power. One might note that the Nazi term for its totalitarian policy of requiring all civil society and voluntary groups to align themselves with Nazi ideology was Gleichschaltung, whose literal meaning is ensuring that all railways use the same gauge of track. Nazification was conceptualized, in other words, as a coordination problem. Hitler solved it.
 
7
The cover is available at https://​global.​oup.​com/​academic/​product/​liberalism-constitutionalis​m-and-democracy-9780199261680?​cc=​us&​lang=​en&​; it is a detail, in mirror image, of a painting whose provenance I could not establish.
 
8
See the various writings of Sheldon Wolin (1994a, b, 2004).
 
9
http://​www.​bls.​gov/​soc/​soc_​2010_​alphabetical_​index.​xls, accessed 21 October 2015; the latest update mentioned there is January 2013.
 
10
Compare Democracy and Knowledge, 11, where Ober’s account of coordination omits the possibility of biased or impure games: all sink or swim together.
 
11
Walzer puts forth this idea in many works, notably The Company of Critics (1988).
 
12
Rawls (1999: 115, 115 n 8) cites David Lewis’ philosophical account of convention as an explication of common knowledge.
 
13
On this, excellent is Bøyum (2013).
 
14
It is, however, uncommon in the Anglo-American world to admit to regarding moral philosophy as “one form of political action.” An exception, containing that quotation, is Goodin (1988: ix).
 
15
An implicit minor premise, at least some of the time, is that political theory is a non-progressive discipline. Unlike science, on this view, it cannot hope to build on past discoveries (perhaps through the use of technical as opposed to everyday language) and document discoveries for use in the future.
 
16
For the most classic expression see Gutmann (1985).
 
17
Thus when Chwe (2001: 102) spells out in formal terms what his book has been calling “coordination” problems, the payoffs are those of an assurance game (see the Appendix). Ober cites Chwe at several points and in two places unmistakably describes an assurance game in prose: “If I know you all will fight, then I will too”; “Building common knowledge in public institutions addresses the ‘carry through’ problem faced by people with shared goals, but who will not individually act to achieve them unless each believes that others will act likewise” (Ober 2008: 179, 191; cf. 192, 194f, 199f.). Naturally, common knowledge and social monitoring solve that problem. They do not solve the (“impure,” “bargaining”) problem in which different groups in society share an interest in peace and order but benefit differentially from different forms of order. That requires authority, whether personal or constitutional, which will in turn give rise to disputes over authority.
 
18
For instance, the framers’ decision to give commerce pride of place in the constitutional system made it unlikely that the system could accommodate large-scale land reform as the compensation for plantation slavery and the culmination of Reconstruction (Du Bois 1935).
 
19
Thus, Wolin in 1997, two years before Liberalism, Constitutionalism, and Democracy, describes postwar American elites as having produced “corruption, constitutional violations, incalculable death and destruction visited upon hapless populations abroad, steadily worsening racial relations, deepening class divisions, discreditation of the idea of public service (except for convicted felons) and, not least, a political system that large numbers of Americans wish to disown” (Wolin 1997: 154). This is not, to put it mildly, Hardin’s most salient or dominant assessment of American constitutionalism.
 
20
There is also the possibility of partial disallegiance. In the 1980s in South Los Angeles, the police lost the trust of the local population to such an extent as to be considered merely a particularly well-organized gang. Such disallegiance has substantial costs to the larger community—again, partly expressed through potential or actual civil unrest—even though local residents made no effort towards formal revolution, towards founding a new city government or opting out of governmental institutions that seemed immediately useful, like roads and schools.
 
21
See, most recently, Tuck (2015).
 
22
The first of these claims may sound shocking to those who see the Civil Rights movement as broadly accepting American institutions. But I believe the historical case is very strong that Martin Luther King and other Civil Rights leaders endorsed the abstract principles that the Declaration and Constitution professed while denying absolutely that existing American society practiced them even approximately. See Lyons (1998) and Sabl (2001).
 
23
Thus Chong (1991) explains the decline of the Civil Rights movement after the mid-sixties partly as a consequence of the fact that its economic and social goals were vague, lacking a clear focal point or stopping point, once civil and political rights had been achieved.
 
24
In Sabl (2002), I call this the “paradox of innovation.”
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Bøyum, Steinar. 2013. Rawls’s Notion of the Political Conception as Educator. European Journal of Political Theory 12: 136–152.CrossRef Bøyum, Steinar. 2013. Rawls’s Notion of the Political Conception as Educator. European Journal of Political Theory 12: 136–152.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Calvert, Randall. 1992. Leadership and Its Basis in Problems of Social Coordination. International Political Science Review 13: 7–24.CrossRef Calvert, Randall. 1992. Leadership and Its Basis in Problems of Social Coordination. International Political Science Review 13: 7–24.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Chong, Dennis. 1991. Collective Action and the Civil Rights Movement. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Chong, Dennis. 1991. Collective Action and the Civil Rights Movement. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Chwe, Michael Suk-Young. 2001. Rational Ritual: Culture, Coordination and Common Knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Chwe, Michael Suk-Young. 2001. Rational Ritual: Culture, Coordination and Common Knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Du Bois, W.E.B. 1935. Black Reconstruction. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company. Du Bois, W.E.B. 1935. Black Reconstruction. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company.
Zurück zum Zitat Fawcett, Edmund. 2014. Liberalism: The Life of an Idea. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Fawcett, Edmund. 2014. Liberalism: The Life of an Idea. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Freeden, Michael. 2005. Liberal Languages. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Freeden, Michael. 2005. Liberal Languages. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Fung, Archon. 2012. Continuous Institutional Innovation and the Pragmatic Conception of Democracy. Polity 44: 609–624.CrossRef Fung, Archon. 2012. Continuous Institutional Innovation and the Pragmatic Conception of Democracy. Polity 44: 609–624.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Geuss, Raymond. 2005. Neither History Nor Praxis. In Outside Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Geuss, Raymond. 2005. Neither History Nor Praxis. In Outside Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Goodin, Robert. 1988. Reasons for Welfare. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Goodin, Robert. 1988. Reasons for Welfare. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Gutmann, Amy. 1985. Communitarian Critics of Liberalism. Philosophy and Public Affairs 14: 308–322. Gutmann, Amy. 1985. Communitarian Critics of Liberalism. Philosophy and Public Affairs 14: 308–322.
Zurück zum Zitat Hardin, Russell. 1982. Collective Action. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Hardin, Russell. 1982. Collective Action. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 1995. One for All. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ———. 1995. One for All. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 1999. Liberalism, Constitutionalism, and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef ———. 1999. Liberalism, Constitutionalism, and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2007. David Hume: Moral and Political Theorist. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef ———. 2007. David Hume: Moral and Political Theorist. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Harrington, Michael. 1983. The Politics at God’s Funeral: The Spiritual Crisis of Western Civilization. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston. Harrington, Michael. 1983. The Politics at God’s Funeral: The Spiritual Crisis of Western Civilization. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
Zurück zum Zitat Hibbing, John, and Elizabeth Theiss-Morse. 2002. Stealth Democracy: Americans’ Beliefs About How Government Should Work. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Hibbing, John, and Elizabeth Theiss-Morse. 2002. Stealth Democracy: Americans’ Beliefs About How Government Should Work. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hume, David. 1740. Treatise of Human Nature 3.1.1.9. Hume, David. 1740. Treatise of Human Nature 3.1.1.9.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 1987. The Sceptic. In Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene F. Miller, revised ed. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. ———. 1987. The Sceptic. In Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene F. Miller, revised ed. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
Zurück zum Zitat Kershaw, Ian. 2000. Hitler. London: Longman’s. Kershaw, Ian. 2000. Hitler. London: Longman’s.
Zurück zum Zitat Lyons, David. 1998. Moral Judgment, Historical Reality, and Civil Disobedience. Philosophy and Public Affairs 27: 31–49.CrossRef Lyons, David. 1998. Moral Judgment, Historical Reality, and Civil Disobedience. Philosophy and Public Affairs 27: 31–49.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ober, Josiah. 2006. Thucydides and the Invention of Political Science. In Brill’s Companion to Thucydides, ed. Antonios Rengakos and Antonios Tsakmakis. Leiden: Brill. Ober, Josiah. 2006. Thucydides and the Invention of Political Science. In Brill’s Companion to Thucydides, ed. Antonios Rengakos and Antonios Tsakmakis. Leiden: Brill.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2008. Democracy and Knowledge: Innovation and Learning in Classical Athens. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef ———. 2008. Democracy and Knowledge: Innovation and Learning in Classical Athens. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Pettit, Philip. 1997. Republicanism. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Pettit, Philip. 1997. Republicanism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Philp, Mark. 2007. Political Conduct. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Philp, Mark. 2007. Political Conduct. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Pocock, J.G.A. 1975. The Machiavellian Moment. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Pocock, J.G.A. 1975. The Machiavellian Moment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Przeworski, Adam. 1999. Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense. In Democracy’s Value, ed. Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón, 23–55. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Przeworski, Adam. 1999. Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense. In Democracy’s Value, ed. Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón, 23–55. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice. revised ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice. revised ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Sabl, Andrew. 2001. Looking Forward to Justice: Rawlsian Civil Disobedience and Its Non-Rawlsian Lessons. Journal of Political Philosophy 9: 331–349.CrossRef Sabl, Andrew. 2001. Looking Forward to Justice: Rawlsian Civil Disobedience and Its Non-Rawlsian Lessons. Journal of Political Philosophy 9: 331–349.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2002. When Bad Things Happen from Good People (and Vice-Versa): Hume’s Political Ethics of Revolution. Polity 35: 73–92.CrossRef ———. 2002. When Bad Things Happen from Good People (and Vice-Versa): Hume’s Political Ethics of Revolution. Polity 35: 73–92.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2012. Hume’s Politics: Coordination and Crisis in the History of England. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ———. 2012. Hume’s Politics: Coordination and Crisis in the History of England. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Sagar, Rahul. 2014. Secrets and Leaks: The Dilemma of State Secrecy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Sagar, Rahul. 2014. Secrets and Leaks: The Dilemma of State Secrecy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Schaefer, David Lewis. 1979. Justice or Tyranny? A Critique of John Rawls’ A Theory of Justice. Port Washington: Kennikat Press. Schaefer, David Lewis. 1979. Justice or Tyranny? A Critique of John Rawls’ A Theory of Justice. Port Washington: Kennikat Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Schelling, Thomas. 1960. Strategies of Conflict. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Schelling, Thomas. 1960. Strategies of Conflict. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Tuck, Richard. 2015. The Sleeping Sovereign. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Tuck, Richard. 2015. The Sleeping Sovereign. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Walzer, Michael. 1988. The Company of Critics. New York: Basic Books. Walzer, Michael. 1988. The Company of Critics. New York: Basic Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Wolin, Sheldon. 1969. Political Theory as a Vocation. American Political Science Review 63: 1062–1082.CrossRef Wolin, Sheldon. 1969. Political Theory as a Vocation. American Political Science Review 63: 1062–1082.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 1994b. Norm and Form: The Constitutionalizing of Democracy. In Athenian Political Thought and the Reconstruction of American Democracy, ed. J. Peter Euben, John Wallach, and Josiah Ober, 29–58. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ———. 1994b. Norm and Form: The Constitutionalizing of Democracy. In Athenian Political Thought and the Reconstruction of American Democracy, ed. J. Peter Euben, John Wallach, and Josiah Ober, 29–58. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 1997. The Destructive Sixties and Postmodern Conservatism. In Reassessing the Sixties, ed. Stephen Macedo. New York: Norton. ———. 1997. The Destructive Sixties and Postmodern Conservatism. In Reassessing the Sixties, ed. Stephen Macedo. New York: Norton.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2004. Politics and Vision. expanded ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ———. 2004. Politics and Vision. expanded ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Metadaten
Titel
Constitutions as Conventions: A History of Non-reception
verfasst von
Andrew Sabl
Copyright-Jahr
2018
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-61070-2_6