Skip to main content

2013 | Buch

Cylindric-like Algebras and Algebraic Logic

herausgegeben von: Hajnal Andréka, Miklós Ferenczi, István Németi

Verlag: Springer Berlin Heidelberg

Buchreihe : Bolyai Society Mathematical Studies

insite
SUCHEN

Über dieses Buch

Algebraic logic is a subject in the interface between logic, algebra and geometry, it has strong connections with category theory and combinatorics. Tarski’s quest for finding structure in logic leads to cylindric-like algebras as studied in this book, they are among the main players in Tarskian algebraic logic. Cylindric algebra theory can be viewed in many ways: as an algebraic form of definability theory, as a study of higher-dimensional relations, as an enrichment of Boolean Algebra theory, or, as logic in geometric form (“cylindric” in the name refers to geometric aspects). Cylindric-like algebras have a wide range of applications, in, e.g., natural language theory, data-base theory, stochastics, and even in relativity theory. The present volume, consisting of 18 survey papers, intends to give an overview of the main achievements and new research directions in the past 30 years, since the publication of the Henkin-Monk-Tarski monographs. It is dedicated to the memory of Leon Henkin.​

Inhaltsverzeichnis

Frontmatter

Introduction

Introduction
Abstract
The theory of cylindric algebras (CAs) and Tarskian algebraic logic have been immensely successful in, e.g., applications to such a diversity of fields as logic, mathematics, computer science, artificial intelligence, linguistics and even relativity theory. In some of the applications one has to transcend (a little) the original definition of CAs but not its spirit. For example, the emphasis shifted to relativized CAs and to adding extra operations such as, e.g., substitutions (sτ s). To keep the original Tarskian spirit of CAs, in this volume we consider only quasi-polyadic operations (e.g., substitutions where τ is finite) as opposed to Halmos’ polyadic ones (e.g., substitutions with all infinite τs). These and similar generalizations are the reason for “cylindric-like” algebras in the title in place of simply CAs.
Hajnal Andréka, Miklós Ferenczi, István Németi

Algebraic Notions Applied to Cylindric-Like Algebras

Frontmatter
Reducing First-order Logic to Df3, Free Algebras
Abstract
Alfred Tarski in 1953 formalized set theory in the equational theory of relation algebras [Tar,53a, Tar,53b]. Why did he do so? Because the equational theory of relation algebras (RA) corresponds to a logic without individual variables, in other words, to a propositional logic. This is why the title of the book [Tar-Giv,87] is “Formalizing set theory without variables”. Tarski got the surprising result that a propositional logic can be strong enough to “express all of mathematics”, to be the arena for mathematics. The classical view before this result was that propositional logics in general were weak in expressive power, decidable, uninteresting in a sense. By using the fact that set theory can be built up in it, Tarski proved that the equational theory of RA is undecidable. This was the first propositional logic shown to be undecidable.
Hajnal Andréka, István Németi
Varieties of Two-Dimensional Cylindric Algebras
Abstract
In this chapter we survey recent developments in the theory of twodimensional cylindric algebras. In particular, we will deal with varieties of two-dimensional diagonal-free cylindric algebras and with varieties of two-dimensional cylindric algebras with the diagonal. It is well known that two-dimensional diagonal-free cylindric algebras correspond to the two variable equality-free fragment of classical first-order logic FOL, whereas two-dimensional cylindric algebras with the diagonal correspond to the two variable fragment of FOL with equality. It is also well known that one-dimensional cylindric algebras, also called Halmos monadic algebras, provide algebraic completeness for the one variable fragment of FOL. For a systematic discussion on the connection between various fragments of FOL and classes of (cylindric) algebras that correspond to these fragments we refer to [And-Nem-Sai,01].
Nick Bezhanishvili
Completions and Complete Representations
Abstract
The title of this chapter indicates a rather technical topic, but it can also be thought of as a foundational issue in logic. The question to be considered is this: to what extent can we use an abstract mathematical language to express and reason about relations? Going back at least as far as Augustus de Morgan [Mor,60], a relation can be defined explicitly, as a set of tuples of some fixed length. This allows us to focus on the mathematical aspects of relations and ignore other more problematic features that might arise from other approaches, such as a linguistic analysis of the use of relations in natural language. In order to treat relations algebraically, we consider them abstractly, identify certain relational operations (e.g., the operation of taking the converse of a binary relation) and write down some equational axioms which are sound for the chosen kind of relations (e.g., a binary relation is equal to the converse of its converse). Ideally, our set G of equations will be equationally complete, so that any equation valid over fields of relations of a certain rank equipped with the chosen set-theoretically definable operators will be entailed by Γ.
Robin Hirsch, Ian Hodkinson
Amalgamation, Interpolation and Epimorphisms in Algebraic Logic
Abstract
The amalgamation property (for classes of models), since its discovery, has played a dominant role in algebra and model theory. Algebraic logic is the natural interface between universal algebra and logic (in our present context a variant of first order logic). Indeed, in algebraic logic amalgamation properties in classes of algebras are proved to be equivalent to interpolation results in the corresponding logic. In algebra, the properties of epimorphisms (in the categorial sense) being surjective is well studied. In algebraic logic, this property is strongly related to the famous Beth definability property [Hen-Mon-Tar,85] 5.6.10. Pigozzi [Pig,71] is a milestone for working out such equivalences for cylindric algebras, see also [Mad-Say,07], [And-Nem-Sai,01]. In first order logic, Craig interpolation theorem is equivalent to Beth definability theorem; however this equivalence no longer holds for certain modifications of first order logic, be it reducts or expansions, like L n (first order logic restricted to finitely many n variables) and the extensions of first order logic studied in [Hen-Mon-Tar,85] Sec. 4.3, which are essentially finitary but have an infinitary flavour.
Judit X. Madarász, Tarek Sayed Ahmed
Neat Reducts and Neat Embeddings in Cylindric Algebras
Abstract
An important central concept introduced in [Hen-Mon-Tar,85] is that of neat reducts, and the related one of neat embeddings. The notion of neat reducts is due to Leon Henkin, and one can find that the discussion of this notion is comprehensive and detailed in [Hen-Mon-Tar,85] (closer to the end of the book). This notion proved useful in at least two respects. Analyzing the number of variables appearing in proofs of first order formulas [Hir-Hod,02c], and characterizing the class of representable algebras; those algebras that are isomorphic to genuine algebras of relations. In fact, several open problems that appeared in [Hen-Mon-Tar,85] are on neat reducts, some of which appeared in part 1, and (not yet resolved) appeared again in part 2. This paper, among other things, surveys the status of these problems 40 years after they first appeared. Long proofs are omitted, except for one, which gives the gist of techniques used to solve such kind of problems.
Tarek Sayed Ahmed

Representation Theory

Frontmatter
A New Representation Theory: Representing Cylindric-like Algebras by Relativized Set Algebras
Abstract
Representation theorems. As is known, cylindric algebras are not representable in the classical sense (as a subdirect product of cylindric set algebras), in general. But, the Resek-Thompson theorem states that if the system of cylindric axioms is extended by a new axiom, by the merry-goround property (MGR, for short), then the cylindric-like algebra obtained is representable by a cylindric relativized set algebra. Furthermore, if, in additional, axiom (C4) is weakened (only the commutativity of the single substitutions is assumed) then it is representable by an algebra in Dα, (see [And-Tho,88] and [Fer,07a]). This style of representation theorem is closely connected with the completeness theorems based on the Henkin style semantics in mathematical logic. By an r-representation of a cylindric-like algebra we mean a representation by a cylindric-like relativized set algebra.
Miklós Ferenczi*
Representing all Cylindric Algebras by Twisting on a Problem of Henkin
Abstract
Had the class of cylindric set algebras turned out to be finitely (and/or nicely) axiomatizable, algebraic logic would have evolved along a markedly different path than it did in the past 40 years. Among other things, it would have probably spelled the end of the “abstract” class CAα as a separate subject of research; after all, why bother with abstract algebras, if a few nice extra equations can get us from there to concrete algebras of relations. As it is, Monk’s 1969 result (and its various improvements by algebraic logicians from Andréka to Venema), stating that for α > 2, RCAα is not axiomatizable finitely, meant, among other things, that CAα was here to stay, and its “distance” from RCAα became an important research topic. To mention just one example of how this distance can be measured, we refer to the representation theory of CAs, where sufficient conditions for a CA to be representable are sought. This line of research is typical: the question one asks here is “what is missing from CAs to be representable?”. But Henkin (himself a prolific contributor to representation theory) turned around this question and instead of asking how much CAs needed to be representable, he asked how much set algebras needed to be “distorted” to provide representations for all CAs. Now, if the answer is “very much”, then we haven’t got closer to understanding either CAs or the possible causes of their non-representability.
András Simon

Notions of Logic Related to Cylindric-Like Algebras

Frontmatter
Representable Cylindric Algebras and Many-Dimensional Modal Logics
Abstract
The equationally expressible properties of the cylindrifications and the diagonals in finite-dimensional representable cylindric algebras can be divided into two groups:
(i)
‘One-dimensional’ properties describing individual cylindrifications. These can be fully characterised by finitely many equations saying that each c i , for i < n, is a normal (c i 0 = 0), additive (c i (x+y) = c i x+c i y) and complemented closure operator:
$$ x \leqslant C_i x\quad \quad C_i c_i x \leqslant C_i x\quad \quad C_i \left( { - C_i x} \right) \leqslant - C_i x. $$
(2.0.1)
 
(ii)
‘Dimension-connecting’ properties, that is, equations describing the diagonals and interaction between different cylindrifications and/or diagonals. These properties are much harder to describe completely, and there are many results in the literature on their complexity.
 
Agi Kurucz
Completions, Complete Representations and Omitting Types
Abstract
Algebraic logic arose as a subdiscipline of algebra mirroring constructions and theorems of mathematical logic. It is similar in this respect to such fields as algebraic geometry and algebraic topology, where the main constructions and theorems are algebraic in nature, but the main intuitions underlying them are respectively geometric and topological. The main intuitions underlying algebraic logic are, of course, those of formal logic. Investigations in algebraic logic can proceed in two conceptually different, but often (and unexpectedly) closely related ways. First one tries to investigate the algebraic essence of constructions and results in logic, in the hope of gaining more insight that one could add to his understanding, thus to his knowledge. Second, one can study certain “particular” algebraic structures (or simply algebras) that arise in the course of his first kind of investigations as objects of interest in their own right and go on to discuss questions which naturally arise independently of any connection with logic. But often such purely algebraic results have impact on the logic side. Examples are the undecidability of the representation problem for finite relation algebras [Hir-Hod,01d] that led to deep results concerning undecidability of product modal logics [Hir-Hod-Kur,02a] answering problems of Gabbay and Shehtman.
Tarek Sayed Ahmed
Elements of Cylindric Algebraic Model Theory
Abstract
According to J. Donald Monk, one of the authors of ‘Cylindric Algebras’, the basic monograph on algebraic logic, the fact that the sets of all \( \phi ^\mathfrak{M} \)’s consisting of sequences satisfying the first order formula φ in the model \( \mathfrak{M} \) constitutes the universe of a cylindric set algebra is ‘the main motivating force for […] the whole topic of algebraic logic.’ (cf. [Mon,00] p. 453). Therefore, the investigation of cylindric set algebras from the point of view of their close links to first order models has a distinguished role in algebraic logic. In the course of this investigation, the specific properties of models (e.g. universality, homogeneity, saturatedness) become algebraic ones, and the various connections between models correspond to different kinds of isomorphisms between the cylindric set algebras concerned (see e.g. [Hen-Mon-Tar,85] 4.3.68(7) and (10), [Hen-Mon-Tar,85] pp. 37 and 45, [Mon,00] Sections 5 and 6).
György Serény
Cylindric Modal Logic
Abstract
The formalism of cylindric modal logic can be motivated from two directions. In its own right, it forms an interesting bridge over the gap between propositional formalisms and first-order logic, in that it formalizes first-order logic as if it were a modal formalism: The assignments of first-order variables can be seen as states or possible worlds of the modal formalism, and the quantifiers ∃ and ∀ may be studied as special cases of the modal operators ♢ and ☐, respectively. Elaborating this idea, we find that from this modal viewpoint, the standard semantics of first-order logic corresponds to just one of many possible classes of Kripke frames, and that other classes might be of interest as well.
Yde Venema

Applications of Cylindric-Like Algebras

Frontmatter
Crs and Guarded Logics: A Fruitful Contact
Abstract
Back and forth between algebra and model theory. Algebra and model theory are complementary stances in the history of logic, and their interaction continues to spawn new ideas, witness the interface of First-Order Logic and Cylindric Algebra. This chapter is about a more specialized contact: the flow of ideas between algebra and modal logic through ‘guarded fragments’ restricting the range of quantification over objects. Here is some general background for this topic. For a start, the connection between algebra and model theory is rather tight, since we can view universal algebra as the equational logic part of standard first-order model theory. As an illustration, van Benthem [Ben,88] has a purely model-theoretic proof of Jónsson’s Theorem characterizing the equational varieties with distributive lattices of congruence relations, a major tool of algebraists. Deeper connections arise in concrete cases with categorial dualities, such as that between BAOs and the usual relational models of modal logic. An important example is the main theorem in Goldblatt and Thomason [Gol-Tho,74] characterizing the elementary modally definable frame classes through their closure under taking generated sub-frames, disjoint unions, p-morphic images, and anti-closure under ultrafilter extensions. Its original proof goes back and forth between algebras and frames, in order to apply Birkhoff’s characterization of equational varieties.
Johan Van Benthem
Cylindric Probability Algebras
Abstract
Sometimes it is not enough to prove that a formula φ(x) is satisfied or not by an element aA in the model \( \mathfrak{A} \) we are interested in. It may happen that we are looking for the quantity of those aA for which φ[a] is true. Of course, the mathematical discipline for these considerations is probability theory. The logic suitable for this kind of reasoning was introduced by H. J. Keisler in 1976. This logic has formulas similar to those of L A L ω1ω (A is a countable admissible set), except that the quantifiers (Pxr) (rA ∪ [0, 1] is a real number) are used instead of the usual quantifiers (∀x) and (∃x). A model for this logic is a pair \( \left\langle {\mathfrak{A},\mu } \right\rangle \), where \( \mathfrak{A} \) is a classical structure and μ is a probability measure defined in such a way that definable subsets of the universe A are measurable. The quantifiers are interpreted in the natural way, i.e.
$$ \left\langle {\mathfrak{A},\mu } \right\rangle | = \left( {Px \geqslant r} \right)\phi \left( x \right)\quad \quad iff\quad \quad \mu \left\{ {a \in A:\left\langle {\mathfrak{A},\mu } \right\rangle | = \phi \left[ a \right]} \right\} \geqslant r. $$
Radosav. S. ĐorĐević, Miodrag. D. Rašković
Cylindric Algebras and Relational Databases
Abstract
The success of the relational data model introduced by Codd [Cod,70] can — at least partly — be attributed to its clarity and succinctness. The semantics of the model are constraints among and within the base relations which, as it turned out, could be formulated in various fragments of first order logic. Therefore, a natural approach seems to be the general framework of cylindric structures. The two main examples of these are concrete algebras of n-ary relations on the one hand, and algebras of first order sentences on the other. It is interesting to note that throughout most of the research on the theory of relational databases, this dichotomy can be observed, albeit in a different terminology. Codd’s relational algebra and domain- or tuple calculus are well known examples for this phenomenon, and, keeping in mind the connection between cylindric algebras and first order logic, it comes as no surprise that the resulting query languages are of the same expressive power. The extended relations of [Yan-Pap,82] are, loosely speaking, nothing else than an embedding of some finite cylindric algebra into an infinite algebra of formulae, and a transformation from finite dimensional relations to formulae (and infinite dimensional cylindric algebras) is implicitly present in [Cos,87].
Ivo Düntsch
Probability Measures and Measurable Functions on Cylindric Algebras
Abstract
The concept of probability (measure) defined on a Boolean algebra and that of a measurable function with respect to Boolean set algebras are basic concepts of probability theory (measure theory). In probability theory, the concept of algebras of events (as Boolean algebra) plays the role of propositional logic.
Miklós Ferenczi

Other Algebraic Versions of Logic

Frontmatter
Cylindric Set Algebras and IF Logic
Abstract
Independence-friendly logic (IF logic) [Hin,96, Hin-San,89] is a conservative extension of first-order logic that can be viewed as a generalization of Henkin’s branching quantifiers [Hen,61]. For example, in the branching quantifier sentence
Allen L. Mann
Polyadic Algebras
Abstract
Polyadic algebras were introduced and intensively studied by Halmos, after having studied cylindric algebras in Tarski’s seminar in Berkeley; we refer to Section 5.4 of [Hen-Mon-Tar,85], see also [Hal,62]. This class of algebras can be regarded as an alternative approach to algebraize first order logic. After a thorough reformulation of Henkin, Monk, and Tarski, polyadic algebras also can be regarded as certain generalizations of cylindric algebras. On one hand, polyadic algebras have nice representation properties, on the other, their languages are rather large (in the ω-dimensional case the cardinality of their set of operations is continuum), which makes their equational theory recursively undecidable for trivial reasons. This is undesirable from metalogical point of view, hence, during the last decades, certain countable (even finite) reducts of polyadic algebras have also been intensively studied. The goal of this research direction is to find a countable reduct of polyadic algebras which has nice representation properties, and, at the same time, their equational theory is recursively enumerable.
Gábor Sági

Connections with Abstract Algebraic Logic and Universal Logic

Frontmatter
Definability Issues in Universal Logic
Abstract
Besides Universal Logic (J-Y. Béziau [Bez,10], [Bez,05]) we focus on its predecessor Universal Algebraic Logic going back to the 70’s ([And-Ger-Nem,77], [And-Ger-Nem,73]) and originating with Tarski’s school, cf. [Hen-Mon-Tar,85, Part II, Sec. 5.6, p. 255].
Ildikó Sain
Backmatter
Metadaten
Titel
Cylindric-like Algebras and Algebraic Logic
herausgegeben von
Hajnal Andréka
Miklós Ferenczi
István Németi
Copyright-Jahr
2013
Verlag
Springer Berlin Heidelberg
Electronic ISBN
978-3-642-35025-2
Print ISBN
978-3-642-35024-5
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-35025-2

Premium Partner