Skip to main content

2016 | Buch

David Hume’s Humanity

The Philosophy of Common Life and Its Limits

insite
SUCHEN

Über dieses Buch

Scott Yenor argues that David Hume's reputation as a skeptic is greatly exaggerated and that Hume's skepticism is a moment leading Hume to defend common life philosophy and the humane commercial republic. Gentle, humane virtues reflect the proper reaction to the complex mixture of human faculties that define the human condition.

Inhaltsverzeichnis

Frontmatter
Chapter 1. David Hume’s Philosophy of Common Life
Abstract
There is a crisis in the scientific study of politics. This crisis manifests itself in the increasing specialization and focus on quasi-mathematical reductive research methods and in the irrelevance of political science to the actual practice of politics in America and in the modern world. Political scientists are, more and more, trained in a particular subfield and those trained in political science share only a commitment to methods of study; research design seems to be what holds the profession together. There are depressingly few books or bodies of knowledge that one would have to master in order to be considered an educated political scientist today: the idea that there is a body of knowledge that defines the profession seems quite quaint or naïve. This constitutes a victory of method or skills over content and substance. What is true of political science is true of university life as such, where the split between science and humanism grows larger every year. Today the “spirit of geometry,” to use Pascal’s phrase, triumphs over the “spirit of finesse,” just as it seemed to be doing in the early seventeenth century.1 The currency of the scientific spirit is ascendant relatively and absolutely, while the prestige of humanities has rarely, if ever, been lower. “Humanists” in philosophy and history, for instance, seem to have turned to science as a model for how to conduct their studies.
Scott Yenor
Chapter 2. “Nothing but Sophistry and Illusion”: Metaphysical Speculation before Hume
Abstract
Hume’s situates his philosophy of common life in the broad context of ancient and modern treatments of human capacities. The Treatise contains an explicit discussion “Of the Antient Philosophy” and “Of the Modern Philosophy” (Book 1; Part IV; Sections III and IV, respectively), though his views on both permeate this Part and Book. The elements that concern Hume include how previous philosophers have accounted for the nature of matter, the intelligibility of nature, and explaining how or if people reliably sense matter. The most telling question concerns the reliability of the senses and the tendency of previous philosophers to entertain “skepticism with regard to the senses” (1.IV.II) because that is where human capacities intersect with the broader world. Previous thinkers provided an account of nature that allowed people to depend upon the accuracy of the senses or perhaps not to rely upon them. The previous accounts of first things require a penetration into the hidden recesses of nature and a showing of how people fit into that stream of nature (or do not). These are questions of metaphysics, a word of opprobrium for Hume (see, e.g., EHU 165, T 268). Hume criticizes these previous treatments to reveal the true sphere of human knowledge. He continues the work of “some late philosophers in England, who have begun to put the science of man on a new footing” (T xvii), yet he furthers and radicalizes this work to reveal a footing both less and more sure.
Scott Yenor
Chapter 3. Active Sovereignty in Natural and Moral Philosophy
Abstract
Hume accepts the “realistic” critique of ancient philosophy offered by modern thinkers. Hume’s first, most obvious, and seemingly greatest philosophic accomplishment lies in subjecting the principles of modern philosophy to a searching skeptical criticism. The second, deeper goal is to illuminate our obscure condition and contradictory faculties and hence to distinguish the natural difficulties involved in philosophizing from artificial difficulties that modern thinkers have involved themselves in. Articulating the inconsistencies and mysteries, Hume provides a philosophy of common life and establishes grounds for philosophic modesty and political moderation.
Scott Yenor
Chapter 4. “Mitigated Scepticism” and Our “Mixed Kind of Life”: The Philosophic Modesty of Hume’s Science of Common Life
Abstract
This chapter lays out the contradictory features of human nature that make up the equipment out of which human beings form judgments about the world. It culminates in Hume’s most complete statement of what the human condition is, which then forms the touchstone for his treatment of morality, politics, history and religion.
Scott Yenor
Chapter 5. The Liberal Imagination and the Problem of Abstract Speculative Principles in Politics
Abstract
Hume initiated a critique of modern ideology that came to prominence after the French Revolution in the writings of Edmund Burke, Hegel, and Tocqueville. Hume’s critique grows out of his concern about modern rationalism’s actively sovereign imagination. Social contract theory and its attendant doctrines are political equivalents of philosophic doctrines such as primary and secondary qualities or personal identity. Just as Hume had criticized those philosophic doctrines in part to prepare the way for a philosophy of common life, Hume’s criticisms of social contract and other political principles lead him to defend the commercial republic as the arrangements most suited to our “mixed kind of life.” There is a crucial difference between Hume’s intervention into philosophy and his treatment of political theories. Philosophical conundrums such as those viewed in the previous chapters are revealing, though they do not engage deep human emotions. Merely philosophic errors are “ridiculous” (T 272); arguments over abstruse topics are more likely to induce sleep than riots. Theoretical intrusions into politics implicate strong passions, established institutions, and the basis for political community. Political systemizers seek to remold institutions and customs inconsistent with their principles. If they are opposed by another system, passion can run especially high and civil conflict can ensue.
Scott Yenor
Chapter 6. Humanity and Commerce
Abstract
Hume’s dissatisfaction with modern political philosophy led him to the study of history as a mirror to “the constant and universal principles of human nature” (EHU 83). This study of history, while it led him to insist that there was an enduring human nature across time, also led him to appreciate the unique accomplishments (and problems) in political practice of modern Europe of his time1 and to see the political arrangements of ancient regimes as almost unbelievable distortions of human nature. For Hume, ancient political institutions are peculiar, violent, immoderate, and generally undesirable, while modern practice is gentle and moderate and fosters happiness and human flourishing. How can Hume reach this conclusion about the superiority of modern to ancient times? How are we to understand his turn to history as a mirror of nature when it comes to studying human nature?
Scott Yenor
Chapter 7. Religious Revolution and England’s Humane Political Constitution
Abstract
The humane virtues are the proper reaction to the “mixed kind of life” to which nature has consigned human beings. In its tranquility, order, moderation, and gentleness, the commercial polity reflects the fortified temper, softened passions, self-conscious reflections and relatively steady equilibrium central to a happy disposition (cf. E 177n with EPM 256–7). Hume’s History of England shows how the unique achievement of England’s humane constitution arose in history and how the constitution relies on a complex set of mores to arise and sustain itself. No one in the depths of the Middle Ages would have predicted that England, of all places, would lead the world into an era of humanity and liberty. Only when the superstitious edifice of feudalism crumbled did an ethos of humanity, learning, and industry arise. The edifice crumbled in unexpected ways (through enthusiastic religion) as initiated by unexpected people (the Tudors). This chapter outlines the destruction of the feudal order so we can understand the political, economic, and social underpinnings for a humane polity.
Scott Yenor
Chapter 8. Religious Belief and Hume’s Philosophy of Common Life
Abstract
Acombination of agnosticism and natural suppositions sustains a philosophy of common life. Agnostic on how mechanisms of understanding function or how nature works, we can suppose that we adequately judge or that nature works steadily and continue from there. The problem Hume confronts in his conception of history arises from a conflict between his desire to be agnostic on questions about how things in history work on one hand and our need to put forth propositions about how history moves. The last chapter covered the difficulties of establishing the “common sense” principles for a study of history since every account of history presumes something about the meaning of history and what moves history. That he conceives of history as determined by accident implies an answer to the question of how history works and what moves history. As troubling, Hume’s own account lends support to the view that history is animated by a spirit of progress behind accidents that are on the surface. How should or can philosophy of common life proceed if or when non-controversial natural suppositions are not available?
Scott Yenor
Chapter 9. Humanity and Theology in Hume’s Religious Dialogues
Abstract
Hume’s philosophy of common life is an attractive approach to achieving human knowledge and a plausible ground for the gentle, humane virtues. Oriented by our “mixed kind of life” and aware of the depths that lay beyond reason, philosophy submits to reasonable, universal, permanent, and irresistible presuppositions from common life. Awareness of human limits cultivates a spirit of modesty and humility in scientific inquirers and a spirit of gentle humanity in social relations. Emphasis on the non-rational, non-scientific elements of human nature distances Hume from his Enlightenment forbearers who vainly sought a scientific explanation for everything in an effort to disprove, overcome, or outflank Christian orthodoxy. The last chapter ended with questions about whether Hume is not in deeper agreement with Enlightenment thinkers on the issues of why human beings turn to God (the psychology of religion) and whether human beings inhabit a disenchanted world (where no miracles happen). These questions implicate Hume’s philosophy of common life at its core by raising the unavoidable, embarrassing question of what counts as a deliverance of common life. Hume’s philosophy of common life is not “nonfoundational” if it takes a (secretly dogmatic) position on controversial, “pre-rational” issues such as history, miracles, or the psychology of religion.
Scott Yenor
Chapter 10. Toward a More Philosophical Philosophy of Common Life
Abstract
It should be clear that I oppose the very old, vulgar view that Hume abandoned philosophy for the study of history and for the pursuit of literary fame. Hume’s philosophic achievement lies in an articulation of the “mixed kind of life” to which human beings are consigned. The human condition is defined by inescapable oppositions between reasonableness and sentimentality, reason and the imagination, the need for action and the need for rest, the particular and the universal, sociality and individuality, and history and nature, among others. The proper political and ethical reaction to the paradoxes and contradictions defining human nature is best found in modern commercial republics, where the virtues of humanity, gentle political authority, and an easy-going tolerance find a home. Modern arrangements provide freedom for people to work out the contradictions in their nature in a manner consistent with their own character and inclinations. Hume has, to a large degree, brought about a de-mystified, disenchanted, moderately skeptical, humanist ethos. The philosophy of common life arises almost of itself in the modern commercial republic, though it sometimes needs to be maintained and restored by humanizing philosophers when excessively rationalist or excessively mystical ways of thinking emerge.
Scott Yenor
Backmatter
Metadaten
Titel
David Hume’s Humanity
verfasst von
Scott Yenor
Copyright-Jahr
2016
Verlag
Palgrave Macmillan US
Electronic ISBN
978-1-137-53959-5
Print ISBN
978-1-349-71193-2
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137539595