Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Minds and Machines 3/2013

01.08.2013

The Mark of the Cognitive

verfasst von: Fred Adams, Rebecca Garrison

Erschienen in: Minds and Machines | Ausgabe 3/2013

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

It is easy to give a list of cognitive processes. They are things like learning, memory, concept formation, reasoning, maybe emotion, and so on. It is not easy to say, of these things that are called cognitive, what makes them so? Knowing the answer is one very important reason to be interested in the mark of the cognitive. In this paper, consider some answers that we think do not work and then offer one of our own which ties cognition to actions explained via the having of reasons.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 390 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe




 

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
We discuss these cases below.
 
2
Noe (2010, p. 42) talks as though he attributes mind to bacteria, but it is not clear to us whether he maintains that bacteria think.
 
3
Everyone agrees and knows that memory, perception, reasoning, and perhaps emotion are cognitive processes, but what we are asking is what makes them cognitive? In virtue of what are these processes of the same type—cognitive? Most practicing scientists presume there is an answer to this question but few try to give it.
 
4
See Clark and Chalmers (1998) and Rowlands (2010), for the pro and Adams and Aizawa (2008) for the con.
 
5
For more, see Adams (2010).
 
6
For arguments that it is see Noe (2004, 2010), for reservations see Aizawa (2007).
 
7
For examples and arguments that cognition requires embedding in an environment and use of that environment as a type of “scaffolding” see Clark (2008). We are not sure there is opposition to this view, if the scaffolding is not considered constitutive of mind.
 
8
We are not suggesting so-called “agent” causation, but differentiating two schemas for individuating actions.
 
9
See Parker (2001). Our claim is not that if some behavior has a chemical explanation it is not cognitive. Rather it is that if it has a chemical explanation that does not constitute being a reason or representation, then it is not cognitive. Reasons and representations themselves no doubt have chemical constitutions.
 
10
See Noe (2010), Maturana and Varela (1980), and Thompson (2010).
 
11
See Saigusa et al. (2008).
 
12
Of course this is not too surprising given the tendency of slime mold to be sensitive to properties such as heat and cold, oxygen and ammonia gradients, light and dark (Bonner 2009). Intermittent introduction of cold bursts could result in changes to internal chemical reactions. The periodicity could mimic memory (Ball 2008) and be explained in terms of the physics of well-understood oscillators.
 
13
We think having concepts and having reasons are related in this way. To have a reason one needs concepts, but having reasons extends beyond the mere having of concepts. Nonetheless, concepts are featured in reasons. If Herbert gathered coke cans for the reason that he wanted to keep the office tidy, he’d have both concepts of coke cans and reasons to collect them.
 
14
Herbert can’t do anything intentionally or purposefully. He has no reasons. He does not know what a soda can is. He has no beliefs or desires. He has no desire to retrieve the can, nor beliefs about retrieval. Herbert is not a cognitive agent despite the fact that his motions mimic those of a cognitive agent. It is on the basis of this mimicry of motion that Brooks deems Herbert’s behavior to be “intelligent.” Brooks claims that his robots “have goals,” “make predictions,” and “do things,” using the language of the intentional idiom, as if they were purposive, intentional agents. But there is no good reason to think any of this is true precisely because purposive, intentional agents act for reasons (just what Brooks denies of his robots). Someone might claim that if Herbert revises his behavior until the can is picked up successfully then this shows he does have the desire to pick up the can. To us, this would be a rampant form of behaviorism, long abandoned for good reasons.
 
15
There are, of course, theorists who do attribute cognition to plants based on the activity that plants engage in which is behaviorally similar to the behavior of reasoning creatures. See (Calvo and Keijzer 2008).
 
16
Another reason to think that Rowlands may be willing to include artifact function is that, in the end, he thinks the processes of a person (Otto) using a notebook to help remember his way around New York City count as cognitive processing (2010, p. 208) and the processing includes processing language and languages are clearly human artifacts.
 
17
Rowlands borrows from Millikan (1984, 1993) an account of “proper function” as that which some item is “supposed” to do or has been evolutionarily “designed” to do.
 
18
See Adams and Aizawa (2008).
 
19
It is sometimes hard to know exactly what to make of Rowlands’ view. For instance, at one point to diffuse worry about what “person” means in “personal level” cognitive processing, he says: “‘Person’ in this context, approximates to ‘organism capable of detecting changes in the environment and modifying its behavior accordingly (p. 146).” The problem of course is that bacteria, plants, and even slime-mold can do this. So, surely there is more to being a person or subject than this, and the problem Rowlands faces is saying what that is without circularity among his conditions of the mark of the cognitive.
 
20
So we continue to find Rowlands’ attempt to shrug off circularity unpersuasive. He spends an entire chapter (6) on what “ownership” comes to, but we find this explanation even less clear or persuasive.
 
21
We suspect Rowlands will try to evade these objections by invoking a “vehicle/content” distinction or “causal/constitutive” distinction. But what he has to say about these things in the relevant pages of the book are far from clear or persuasive (see chapter 8). What is more, as far as we can see, our examples fit the letter of his marks of the cognitive. As far as we can see, even if walking is only a vehicle, it is still a vehicle in a cognitive process of disclosing information about the world and will count as a cognitive process on his conditions, despite his protest to the contrary. Notice that his response to “walking around the corner” was not about vehicles or contents or causation or constitution but about proper function. So, we think he went with his best shot and we think it still is not good enough.
 
22
We are not saying that in principle a robot could not be built which operates with reasons, just that this is not what is happening with Herbert.
 
23
We are not saying that evolution cannot supply a creature with reasons. When it does, there must be some internal structure that constitutes a representation of a goal or desire that grounds the truth of the statement that the individual does something for a reason (its reason). Naturally, we also do not claim that reasons have to be consciously entertained.
 
24
We are not saying this is a mechanism to which minds have conscious access.
 
25
See Adams and Beighley (2011) for discussion of a similar idea by Fitch (2007).
 
26
See also Sterelny (2003) who suggests that “de-coupled” representations are a key ingredient in the evolution of cognition.
 
27
Of course not all sensory neurons are transducers. Amacrine cells in the retina are an example. But these would not be examples of neurons playing the role described in the termite mound. One may also object that sensory neurons themselves can be falsely tokened. But one must solve the “disjunction” problem for them, as well. Do they falsely indicate their usual cause or truly indicate a broader set of disjunctive causes? If the latter, they are still just information transducers. We suspect that the analogy to the termites is of the latter variety.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Adams, F. (2010). Why we still need a mark of the mental/cognitive. Cognitive Systems Research, 11, 324–331.CrossRef Adams, F. (2010). Why we still need a mark of the mental/cognitive. Cognitive Systems Research, 11, 324–331.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Oxford: Blackwell-Wiley. Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Oxford: Blackwell-Wiley.
Zurück zum Zitat Adams, F., & Beighley, S. (2011). The mark of the mental. In J. Garvey (Ed.), The continuum companion to the philosophy of mind (pp. 54–72). London: Continuum International Publishing Group. Adams, F., & Beighley, S. (2011). The mark of the mental. In J. Garvey (Ed.), The continuum companion to the philosophy of mind (pp. 54–72). London: Continuum International Publishing Group.
Zurück zum Zitat Aizawa, K. (2007). Understanding the embodiment of perception. Journal of Philosophy, 104, 5–25. Aizawa, K. (2007). Understanding the embodiment of perception. Journal of Philosophy, 104, 5–25.
Zurück zum Zitat Ball, P. (2008). Cellular memory hints at the origins of intelligence. Nature, 451, 385.CrossRef Ball, P. (2008). Cellular memory hints at the origins of intelligence. Nature, 451, 385.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bonner, J. T. (2009). The social amoeba: The biology of cellular slime molds. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Bonner, J. T. (2009). The social amoeba: The biology of cellular slime molds. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without reason. A.I. Memo 1293. Cambridge, MA: MIT/AI Lab. Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without reason. A.I. Memo 1293. Cambridge, MA: MIT/AI Lab.
Zurück zum Zitat Calvo, P., & Keijzer, F. (2008). Cognition in plants. In F. Baluska (Ed.), Plant-environment interactions: From sensory plant biology to active plant behavior (pp. 247–266). Berlin: Springer. Calvo, P., & Keijzer, F. (2008). Cognition in plants. In F. Baluska (Ed.), Plant-environment interactions: From sensory plant biology to active plant behavior (pp. 247–266). Berlin: Springer.
Zurück zum Zitat Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.CrossRef Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Enc, B., & Adams, F. (1998). Functions and goal-directedness. In C. Allen, M. Bekoff, & G. Lauder (Eds.), Nature’s purposes (pp. 371–394). Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford. Enc, B., & Adams, F. (1998). Functions and goal-directedness. In C. Allen, M. Bekoff, & G. Lauder (Eds.), Nature’s purposes (pp. 371–394). Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford.
Zurück zum Zitat Fitch, T. (2007). Nano-intentionality. Biology & Philosophy, 23, 157–177.CrossRef Fitch, T. (2007). Nano-intentionality. Biology & Philosophy, 23, 157–177.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1980). Autopoesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRef Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1980). Autopoesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Millikan, R. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Millikan, R. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Noe, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Noe, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Noe, A. (2010). Out of our heads. New York: Hill & Wang. Noe, A. (2010). Out of our heads. New York: Hill & Wang.
Zurück zum Zitat Parker, S. (2001). Kingdom classification: Bacteria. Minneapolis: Compass Points Books. Parker, S. (2001). Kingdom classification: Bacteria. Minneapolis: Compass Points Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford. Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford.
Zurück zum Zitat Saigusa, T., Tero, A., Nagaki, T., & Kuramoto, Y. (2008). Amoeba Anticipate Periodic Events. Physical Review of Letters, 100, 018101-1–018101-4. Saigusa, T., Tero, A., Nagaki, T., & Kuramoto, Y. (2008). Amoeba Anticipate Periodic Events. Physical Review of Letters, 100, 018101-1–018101-4.
Zurück zum Zitat Sterelny, K. (2003). Thought in a hostile world: The evolution of cognition. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. Sterelny, K. (2003). Thought in a hostile world: The evolution of cognition. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.
Zurück zum Zitat Thompson, E. (2010). Mind in life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Thompson, E. (2010). Mind in life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Turner, J. S. (Forthcoming). Super organisms and superindividuality: the emergence of individuality in a social insect assemblage. In F. Bouchard & P. Hunemann (eds.), From groups to individuals. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Turner, J. S. (Forthcoming). Super organisms and superindividuality: the emergence of individuality in a social insect assemblage. In F. Bouchard & P. Hunemann (eds.), From groups to individuals. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Metadaten
Titel
The Mark of the Cognitive
verfasst von
Fred Adams
Rebecca Garrison
Publikationsdatum
01.08.2013
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Erschienen in
Minds and Machines / Ausgabe 3/2013
Print ISSN: 0924-6495
Elektronische ISSN: 1572-8641
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-012-9291-1

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 3/2013

Minds and Machines 3/2013 Zur Ausgabe

Premium Partner