Skip to main content

01.04.2024

Attentiveness in elections with impressionable voters

verfasst von: Costel Andonie, Daniel Diermeier

Erschienen in: Public Choice

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

We propose a model of attentiveness in elections with impressionable voters under three electoral rules: plurality, approval voting, and negative plurality. Voters’ conduct is determined by their attentiveness and impressions of candidates. We show that attentiveness is as important as voters’ preferences for the outcome of the election. Specifically, we show that candidates benefit from increased voter attention under all rules other than negative plurality. We then consider exogenous and endogenous attentiveness and show how our model can account for momentum effects in primaries, where candidates rise quickly and then fade away. Finally we consider the case of news coverage tone and show that under plurality rule e.g., primary elections, candidates may benefit from frequent news coverage even if the news is negative.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Anhänge
Nur mit Berechtigung zugänglich
Fußnoten
1
A tie is a measure zero event in our analysis, i.e., it occurs non-generically, and can be ignored. For completeness we can assume that ties are broken with equal probability.
 
2
See Sect. 4.1 for further discussion, and examples of the factors that determine voters’ attentiveness.
 
3
The two ways to define the “event” probabilities \(\Pr _{\theta }^{t}(.)\) are equivalent, and each can be derived from the other.
 
4
Strictly speaking, we would have to index the set K by subscript \(\theta\) for the group of voters, and superscript t for time. For simplicity of notation, however we drop these two indexes here and in analogous cases.
 
5
The parameter \(\lambda _{p}\) need not be the same across all voters. As we will prove in Proposition 1, the distribution of vote measures in a stationary distribution does not depend on \(\lambda _{p}\). This parameter can vary across e.g., groups of voters, without changing the stationary measures of votes.
 
6
An alternative method of updating aspirations in the literature is that of Cyert-March (Cyert & March, 1963) where aspirations are a linear mixture of previous period aspirations and an average of present period impressions. The analysis would be more difficult, but would yield qualitatively similar results.
 
7
We note that \(K_{\theta }^{\tau }\) is a random variable, with the distribution \(\{\Pr _{\theta }(K)\}_{K\subseteq N}\) as defined previously. We also note that if \(\sum _{\tau =1}^{t}|K_{\theta }^{\tau }|=0\), i.e., voters do not pay attention to any candidate up to period t, then the average of impressions from \(\tau =1\) to t is not well-defined. In this situation, we take, for example, \(a_{\theta }^{t+1}=a_{\theta }^{0}\) an arbitrary value.
 
8
If the events \(\{e_{\theta }(i)\}_{i\in N}\) are correlated, some results continue to apply, but others are more difficult to prove, and likely necessitate assumptions on the full distribution of the attentiveness vector \(e_{\theta }\). Specifically, the results concerning the impact of positive/negative impressions would not change, while the results concerning attentiveness would be limited.
 
9
In addition to the direct effect of the attention probabilities \(r_{\theta }(.)\) discussed, we note that attention probabilities also indirectly impact vote measures through the impression probabilities \(q_{\theta }(.)\). As aspirations are computed as average of impressions of candidates voters pay attention to, paying more attention to a candidate makes it more likely that voters’ impressions of that candidate have a larger weight on aspirations. In other words, attention probabilities affect the aspirations \(a_{\theta }\) in a stationary distribution. Furthermore, probabilities of positive impression \(q_{\theta }(.)\) depend on aspirations, yielding the indirect effect. However, this indirect effect is second-order, and not likely to dominate the direct effect we discuss above. For this reason, we set it aside.
 
10
In the case of full attentiveness, i.e., \(k=n\), which corresponds to the model of Andonie and Diermeier (2022), the process has a unique stationary distribution.
 
11
Under negative plurality, if attentiveness is endogenous then the distribution of the event vector \(e_{\theta }^{t}\) can never be stationary, and so Proposition 1 does not apply. Moreover, it is easy to see that the process cannot have distributions where the vote measures are stationary.
 
12
The formal condition that “the average \(v_{\theta }^{1}\) for candidate 1 is sufficiently larger than the same average for the other candidates” is complicated, and we omit stating it formally in the proposition. In general, the condition depends not only on the fixed components \(v_{\theta }^{i}\) and group shares \(s_{\theta }\), but also on other parameters, e.g, distribution F(.), etc. (see the proof to Proposition 3 in the appendix).
 
13
Recall that in our model aspirations are means of past impressions. Therefore, if past impressions are negative, then aspirations will be low.
 
14
Under negative plurality, we assume that \(r_{R}(3)\) is “sufficiently” close to 1. We assume this additional condition for the following reason. From previous propositions, under negative plurality, the vote measure of a candidate increases if voters pay less attention to that candidate. Therefore, even though all voters rank candidate 3 at the bottom, if the attention probability \(r_{R}(3)\) is low enough, the vote measure of candidate 3 can increase so that it surpasses that of candidate 1 or candidate 2. To shut down this effect, which we separately analysed previously, we make the assumption that \(r_{R}(3)\) is “sufficiently” large.
 
15
The cutoff \(v^{*}\) is characterized by the implicit equation: \((3-F( \frac{2v^{*}:-1}{4\alpha }))(8-F(\frac{2v^{*}-3}{4\alpha })-F(\frac{ 1+2v^{*}}{4\alpha }))=16\).
 
16
In the quasi-stationary distribution under negative plurality, each of the three candidates can win, but the probability that candidate 3 wins is smaller than the probability that candidate 1 or candidate 2 wins.
 
17
We can think of this specification as a simplified form of the following more detailed conception of news coverage. Suppose the distribution of impressions of candidate i among voters of type \(\theta\) is as follows:
$$\begin{aligned} \pi _{\theta }^{t}(i):=v_{\theta }^{i}+\chi ^{i}+\xi ^{i}+\alpha \epsilon _{\theta }^{t}(i), \end{aligned}$$
where \(\chi ^{i}\) is a binary random variable that can take values “\(+\nu ^{i}\)” and “\(-\nu ^{i}\)”, with probabilities \(\pi ^{i}\), and \(1-\pi ^{i}\) respectively; and \(\xi ^{i}\) is a continuous random variable with a symmetric, single-peaked, distribution around 0. The two additional random variables, \(\chi ^{i}\) and \(\xi ^{i}\), model the following two features. First, in some periods the news coverage of a candidate can be positive, i.e., when the realization of \(\chi ^{i}\) is \(+\nu ^{i}\), and in other periods news coverage can be negative, i.e., when the realization of \(\chi ^{i}\) is \(-\nu ^{i}\). Second, some voters may interpret some news as good, while others may interpret the same news as bad. This is captured by the second random variable \(\xi ^{i}\). This more detailed extension, however, is equivalent to the specification above, where \(\mu ^{i}\) corresponds to the expectation of \(\chi ^{i}\), and the uncertainty is combined into the random term \(\epsilon _{\theta }^{t}(i)\).
 
18
The effect of an increase of \(\mu ^{i}\) on the mean of impressions \(\pi _{\theta }(i)\) is larger than the effect on the aspirations \(a_{\theta }\), and so the probability of positive impression \(q_{\theta }(i)\) increases with \(\mu ^{i}\).
 
19
Here, we focus our analysis on plurality rule. The analysis under the two other rules is similar.
 
20
To see that, consider first the effect of an increase in the impression probability \(q_{\theta }(i)\) on the distribution of vote measures. An increase of \(q_{\theta }(i)\) (assuming \(q_{\theta }(l)\), for \(l\ne i\), are fixed) induces an increase in the vote measure of candidate i, \(S_{\theta }(i)\), and a decrease in the vote measure of each candidate \(j\ne i\), \(S_{\theta }(j)\). Consider now in addition the effect of a decrease in the impression probabilities \(q_{\theta }(l)\), for each candidate \(l\ne i\). First, \(S_{\theta }(i)\) further increases. Second, we note that the measure of abstentions \(S_{\theta }(A)\) increases as well, as voters become less likely to have positive impressions of candidates \(l\ne i\). This implies that, on average, the vote measure of a candidate \(j\ne i\) further decreases. The vote measures \(S_{\theta }(j)\), for \(j\ne i\), decrease on average, however, the vote measure of some candidates \(l\ne i\) may increase, depending on their ranks in the vector of fixed components \(u_{\theta }\), and the shape of the distribution function of the random component \(\epsilon\).
 
21
For technical reasons in the case of negative plurality we derive “quasi-stationary” distributions.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Achen, C., & Bartels, L. (2002). Blind retrospection: Electoral responses to droughts, flu, and shark attacks. Presented at the Annual Meeting of the APSA, Boston, September 2002. Achen, C., & Bartels, L. (2002). Blind retrospection: Electoral responses to droughts, flu, and shark attacks. Presented at the Annual Meeting of the APSA, Boston, September 2002.
Zurück zum Zitat Achen, C., & Bartels, L. (2004). Musical chairs: Pocketbook voting and the limits of democratic accountability. Presented at the Annual Meeting of the APSA, Chicago, September 2004. Achen, C., & Bartels, L. (2004). Musical chairs: Pocketbook voting and the limits of democratic accountability. Presented at the Annual Meeting of the APSA, Chicago, September 2004.
Zurück zum Zitat Achen, C., & Bartels, L. (2016). Democracy for realists: Why elections do not produce responsive government. Princeton University Press.CrossRef Achen, C., & Bartels, L. (2016). Democracy for realists: Why elections do not produce responsive government. Princeton University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Anagol, S., & Fujiwara, T. (2016). The runner-up effect. Journal of Political Economy, 124(4), 927–91.CrossRef Anagol, S., & Fujiwara, T. (2016). The runner-up effect. Journal of Political Economy, 124(4), 927–91.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Andonie, C., & Diermeier, D. (2017). Path-dependency and coordination in multi-candidate elections with behavioral voters. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 29(4), 520–545.CrossRef Andonie, C., & Diermeier, D. (2017). Path-dependency and coordination in multi-candidate elections with behavioral voters. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 29(4), 520–545.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Andonie, C., & Diermeier, D. (2019). Impressionable voters. American Economic Journal: Microeconomics, 11(1), 79–104. Andonie, C., & Diermeier, D. (2019). Impressionable voters. American Economic Journal: Microeconomics, 11(1), 79–104.
Zurück zum Zitat Andonie, C., & Diermeier, D. (2022). Electoral institutions with impressionable voters. Social Choice and Welfare, 59, 683–733.CrossRef Andonie, C., & Diermeier, D. (2022). Electoral institutions with impressionable voters. Social Choice and Welfare, 59, 683–733.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bartels, L. (1988). Presidential primaries and the dynamics of public choice. Princeton University Press.CrossRef Bartels, L. (1988). Presidential primaries and the dynamics of public choice. Princeton University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Baumgartner, F., & Jones, B. (2009). Agendas and instability in American politics. University of Chicago Press. Baumgartner, F., & Jones, B. (2009). Agendas and instability in American politics. University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Bendor, J. (2010). Bounded rationality and politics. University of California Press. Bendor, J. (2010). Bounded rationality and politics. University of California Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Bendor, J., Diermeier, D., Siegel, D., & Ting, M. (2011). A behavioral theory of elections. Princeton University Press.CrossRef Bendor, J., Diermeier, D., Siegel, D., & Ting, M. (2011). A behavioral theory of elections. Princeton University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bendor, J., Diermeier, D., & Ting, M. (2003). A behavioral model of turnout. American Political Science Review, 97, 261–280.CrossRef Bendor, J., Diermeier, D., & Ting, M. (2003). A behavioral model of turnout. American Political Science Review, 97, 261–280.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Borgers, T., & Sarin, R. (2000). Naive reinforcement learning with endogenous aspirations. International Economic Review, 41, 921–950.CrossRef Borgers, T., & Sarin, R. (2000). Naive reinforcement learning with endogenous aspirations. International Economic Review, 41, 921–950.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bouton, L. (2013). A theory of strategic voting in runoff elections. American Economic Review, 103, 1248–1288.CrossRef Bouton, L. (2013). A theory of strategic voting in runoff elections. American Economic Review, 103, 1248–1288.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bouton, L., & Castanheira, M. (2012). One person, many votes: Divided majority and information aggregation. Econometrica, 80(1), 43–87.CrossRef Bouton, L., & Castanheira, M. (2012). One person, many votes: Divided majority and information aggregation. Econometrica, 80(1), 43–87.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bush, R., & Mosteller, F. (1955). Stochastic models of learning. Wiley.CrossRef Bush, R., & Mosteller, F. (1955). Stochastic models of learning. Wiley.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cho, I., & Matsui, A. (2005). Learning aspiration in repeated games. Journal of Economic Theory, 124, 171–2001.CrossRef Cho, I., & Matsui, A. (2005). Learning aspiration in repeated games. Journal of Economic Theory, 124, 171–2001.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cole, S., Healy, A., & Werker, E. (2012). Do voters demand responsive governments? Evidence from Indian disaster relief. Journal of Development Economics, 97, 167–181.CrossRef Cole, S., Healy, A., & Werker, E. (2012). Do voters demand responsive governments? Evidence from Indian disaster relief. Journal of Development Economics, 97, 167–181.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cox, G. (1987). Electoral equilibrium under alternative voting institutions. American Journal of Political Science, 31(1), 82–108.CrossRef Cox, G. (1987). Electoral equilibrium under alternative voting institutions. American Journal of Political Science, 31(1), 82–108.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cyert, R., & March, J. (1963). A behavioral theory of the firm. Prentice Hall. Cyert, R., & March, J. (1963). A behavioral theory of the firm. Prentice Hall.
Zurück zum Zitat Diermeier, D., & Li, C. (2017). Electoral control with behavioral voters. Journal of Politics, 79(3), 890–902.CrossRef Diermeier, D., & Li, C. (2017). Electoral control with behavioral voters. Journal of Politics, 79(3), 890–902.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Duverger, M. (1954). Political parties: Their organization and activity in the modern state. Wiley. Duverger, M. (1954). Political parties: Their organization and activity in the modern state. Wiley.
Zurück zum Zitat Gasper, J., & Reeves, A. (2011). Make it rain? Retrospection and the attentive electorate in the context of natural disasters. American Journal of Political Science, 55(2), 340–355.CrossRef Gasper, J., & Reeves, A. (2011). Make it rain? Retrospection and the attentive electorate in the context of natural disasters. American Journal of Political Science, 55(2), 340–355.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Jones, B., & Baumgartner, F. (2005). The politics of attention: How government prioritizes problems. University of Chicago Press. Jones, B., & Baumgartner, F. (2005). The politics of attention: How government prioritizes problems. University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Karandikar, R., Mookherjee, D., Ray, D., & Vega-Redondo, F. (1998). Evolving aspirations and cooperation. Journal of Economic Theory, 80, 292–331.CrossRef Karandikar, R., Mookherjee, D., Ray, D., & Vega-Redondo, F. (1998). Evolving aspirations and cooperation. Journal of Economic Theory, 80, 292–331.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kingdon, J. (2003). Agendas, alternatives, and public policies. Longman. Kingdon, J. (2003). Agendas, alternatives, and public policies. Longman.
Zurück zum Zitat Ledyard, J. (1984). The pure theory of large two-candidate elections. Public Choice, 44, 7–41.CrossRef Ledyard, J. (1984). The pure theory of large two-candidate elections. Public Choice, 44, 7–41.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Myatt, D. (2007). On the theory of strategic voting. Review of Economic Studies, 74, 255–281.CrossRef Myatt, D. (2007). On the theory of strategic voting. Review of Economic Studies, 74, 255–281.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Myatt, D., & Fisher, S. (2002). Tactical coordination in plurality electoral systems. Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 18(4), 504–522.CrossRef Myatt, D., & Fisher, S. (2002). Tactical coordination in plurality electoral systems. Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 18(4), 504–522.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Myerson, R. (1999). Theoretical comparisons of electoral systems. European Economic Review, 43, 671–697.CrossRef Myerson, R. (1999). Theoretical comparisons of electoral systems. European Economic Review, 43, 671–697.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Myerson, R. (2002). Comparison of scoring rules in Poisson voting games. Journal of Economic Theory, 103, 219–251.CrossRef Myerson, R. (2002). Comparison of scoring rules in Poisson voting games. Journal of Economic Theory, 103, 219–251.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Myerson, R., & Weber, R. (1993). A theory of voting equilibria. American Political Science Review, 87, 102–114.CrossRef Myerson, R., & Weber, R. (1993). A theory of voting equilibria. American Political Science Review, 87, 102–114.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Palfrey, T. (1989). A mathematical proof of Duverger’s law. In P. Ordeshook (Ed.), Models of strategic choice in politics (pp. 69–92). University of Michigan Press. Palfrey, T. (1989). A mathematical proof of Duverger’s law. In P. Ordeshook (Ed.), Models of strategic choice in politics (pp. 69–92). University of Michigan Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Palfrey, T., & Rosenthal, H. (1983). A strategic calculus of voting. Public Choice, 41, 7–53.CrossRef Palfrey, T., & Rosenthal, H. (1983). A strategic calculus of voting. Public Choice, 41, 7–53.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Palfrey, T., & Rosenthal, H. (1985). Voter participation and strategic uncertainty. American Political Science Review, 79, 62–78.CrossRef Palfrey, T., & Rosenthal, H. (1985). Voter participation and strategic uncertainty. American Political Science Review, 79, 62–78.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Palomino, F., & Vega-Redondo, F. (1999). Convergence of aspirations and (partial) cooperation in the prisoner’s dilemma. International Journal of Game Theory, 28, 465–488.CrossRef Palomino, F., & Vega-Redondo, F. (1999). Convergence of aspirations and (partial) cooperation in the prisoner’s dilemma. International Journal of Game Theory, 28, 465–488.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Sides, J., & Vavreck, L. (2013). The gamble: Choice and chance in the 2012 presidential election. Princeton University Press. Sides, J., & Vavreck, L. (2013). The gamble: Choice and chance in the 2012 presidential election. Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Simon, H. (1955). A behavioral model of rational choice. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69(1), 99–118.CrossRef Simon, H. (1955). A behavioral model of rational choice. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69(1), 99–118.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Simon, H. (1971). Designing organizations for an information-rich world. In M. Greenberger (Ed.), Computers, communications and the public interest. Johns Hopkins Press. Simon, H. (1971). Designing organizations for an information-rich world. In M. Greenberger (Ed.), Computers, communications and the public interest. Johns Hopkins Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Thorndike, E. (1898). Animal intelligence: An experimental study of the associative processes in animals. Psychological Review (Monograph Supplement), 2(8), 4–160. Thorndike, E. (1898). Animal intelligence: An experimental study of the associative processes in animals. Psychological Review (Monograph Supplement), 2(8), 4–160.
Metadaten
Titel
Attentiveness in elections with impressionable voters
verfasst von
Costel Andonie
Daniel Diermeier
Publikationsdatum
01.04.2024
Verlag
Springer US
Erschienen in
Public Choice
Print ISSN: 0048-5829
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-7101
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-024-01161-5

Premium Partner