Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Social Choice and Welfare 3/2017

18.01.2017 | Original Paper

Conformity in voting

verfasst von: Bernardo Moreno, María del Pino Ramos-Sosa

Erschienen in: Social Choice and Welfare | Ausgabe 3/2017

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

A group of agents has to decide whether to accept or reject a proposal. Agents vote in favor of or against the proposal and, if the number of agents in favor is greater than a certain threshold, the proposal is accepted. Conformist agents vote based on not only their opinion but also the votes of other agents. Independent agents consider only their own opinions. If all agents are conformists and vote simultaneously, there are undominated Nash equilibria in which the decision is different from that obtained if all agents vote for their opinions. Next, we provide the number of independent agents sufficient to obtain, in any equilibrium, the decision obtained when all agents vote for their opinions. This number depends on the total number of agents, the threshold, and the conformity measure. If agents vote sequentially, the voting behavior of conformist agents does not affect the decision.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Anhänge
Nur mit Berechtigung zugänglich
Fußnoten
1
In the sequential version of the game, in Sect. 5, the equilibrium concept used is that of subgame perfect Nash equilibrium.
 
2
We assume that external advisors or consultants have incentives only for being sincere and representing the interests of their employers; they receive no gain by deviating from that behavior.
 
3
We acknowledge that it could be very natural to think that when agents have different groups to conform to, they prefer to conform to those whose messages coincide with their own opinions. Our results hold under this assumption.
 
4
See Sobel (2005) for a study of interdependent preferences applied to the ultimatum game case in which agents’ preferences also depend on the consumption of others.
 
5
Section 5 analyzes a sequential version of the game.
 
6
Note that our property of selfishness is related to the notion of selfish preferences used in Sobel (2005), which refers to the preferences that do not directly depend on the messages of others.
 
7
Moreno and Ramos-Sosa (2015) opens the door to more general versions of conformity. Agents may pay attention to some specific subsets of agents. Those subsets of agents could be either groups of experts, or a leader, or, as Kenneth Shepsle proposed to the authors, an agent may want to conform to some agents and not to others. Note that in these cases, the identity of the agents plays an important role.
 
8
An anonymous referee proposes to us another version of conformity in which agents want to conform to as many agents as possible. In Sect. 4, we show how this alternative version of conformity relates to that proposed in this study.
 
9
For every preference profile, the alternative selected by any q-truthful social choice function specifies the decision and vote of each agent. Alternatively, any q-truthful social choice function could specify the decision and number of agents voting for each option. The former could be related to an open ballot scenario whereas the latter is more related to a secret ballot scenario in which the decision is made public once all agents have voted. Our results remain valid under this alternative definition of a q-truthful social choice function.
 
10
A more realistic scenario would be one in which the preference relations of the agents are unknown. We assume complete information as a first step before analysing the implications of incomplete information in future research.
 
11
Note that for any profile different from \(\succeq ^{0}\), any weakly undominated Nash equilibrium implements the \(1-\)truthful social choice function.
 
12
Note that for any profile different from \(\succeq ^{1},\) any weakly undominated Nash equilibrium implements the \(n-\)threshold rule.
 
13
We thank the anonymous referee who advised us to refer to these preference profiles as problematic and to adopt a criterion stating when a preference profile is more problematic than another.
 
14
We assume that these external advisors have incentives only to be sincere and to represent the interests of their employers, and receive no gain by deviating from that behavior.
 
15
We acknowledge that in a more general model, conformist agents may not observe the message of independent agents before they send their messages. For instance, conformist agents may know the number of independent agents but do not know their identities. This is an interesting scenario that we leave for further research.
 
16
Admittedly, an exact number of independent agents could also be obtained for any given \((h_{1},\ldots ,h_{n})\) but we consider that the symmetric case is a focal point.
 
17
We thank an anonymous referee for proposing this alternative way of modeling conformity.
 
18
The proof when n is odd and \(q=\frac{n+1}{2}\) is included in Moreno and Ramos-Sosa (2015).
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Akerlof GA (1997) Social distance and social decisions. Econometrica 65(5):1005–1027 Akerlof GA (1997) Social distance and social decisions. Econometrica 65(5):1005–1027
Zurück zum Zitat Asch SE (1951) Effects of group pressure upon the modification and distortion of judgments. In: Harold Guetzkow (ed) Groups, leadership, and men. Carnegie Press, Pittsburgh, pp 222–236 Asch SE (1951) Effects of group pressure upon the modification and distortion of judgments. In: Harold Guetzkow (ed) Groups, leadership, and men. Carnegie Press, Pittsburgh, pp 222–236
Zurück zum Zitat Bernheim BD (1994) A theory of conformity. J Polit Econ 102(5):841–877 Bernheim BD (1994) A theory of conformity. J Polit Econ 102(5):841–877
Zurück zum Zitat Bernheim BD, Exley CL (2015) Understanding conformity: an experimental investigation. Harvard Business School NOM Unit Working Paper (16-070) Bernheim BD, Exley CL (2015) Understanding conformity: an experimental investigation. Harvard Business School NOM Unit Working Paper (16-070)
Zurück zum Zitat Buechel B, Hellmann T, Klössner S (2015) Opinion dynamics and wisdom under conformity. J Econ Dyn Control 52:240–257CrossRef Buechel B, Hellmann T, Klössner S (2015) Opinion dynamics and wisdom under conformity. J Econ Dyn Control 52:240–257CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Buchanan JM, Tullock G (1962) The calculus of consent: logical foundations of constitutional democracy, vol 100. University of Michigan Press, MichiganCrossRef Buchanan JM, Tullock G (1962) The calculus of consent: logical foundations of constitutional democracy, vol 100. University of Michigan Press, MichiganCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Coats JC, Gronberg TJ, Grosskopf B (2009) Simultaneous versus sequential public good provision and the role of refunds–an experimental study. J Public Econ 93(1):326–335CrossRef Coats JC, Gronberg TJ, Grosskopf B (2009) Simultaneous versus sequential public good provision and the role of refunds–an experimental study. J Public Econ 93(1):326–335CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Deutsch M, Gerard HB (1955) A study of normative and informational social influences upon individual judgment. J Abnorm Soc Psychol 51(3):629CrossRef Deutsch M, Gerard HB (1955) A study of normative and informational social influences upon individual judgment. J Abnorm Soc Psychol 51(3):629CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Dutta B, Sen A (2012) Nash implementation with partially honest individuals. Games Econ Behav 74(1):154–169CrossRef Dutta B, Sen A (2012) Nash implementation with partially honest individuals. Games Econ Behav 74(1):154–169CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Feddersen T, Pesendorfer W (1998) Convicting the innocent: the inferiority of unanimous jury verdicts under strategic voting. Am Polit Sci Rev 92(01):23–35CrossRef Feddersen T, Pesendorfer W (1998) Convicting the innocent: the inferiority of unanimous jury verdicts under strategic voting. Am Polit Sci Rev 92(01):23–35CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Glaeser EL, Sacerdote B, Scheinkman JA (1996) Crime and social interactions. Q J Econ 111:507–548CrossRef Glaeser EL, Sacerdote B, Scheinkman JA (1996) Crime and social interactions. Q J Econ 111:507–548CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Herrera H, Martinelli C (2006) Group formation and voter participation. Theor Econ 1(4):461–487 Herrera H, Martinelli C (2006) Group formation and voter participation. Theor Econ 1(4):461–487
Zurück zum Zitat Jones SR (1984) The economics of conformism. Blackwell, Oxford Jones SR (1984) The economics of conformism. Blackwell, Oxford
Zurück zum Zitat Luzzati T (1999) Economic theory and conformism, vol 68. Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham Glos Luzzati T (1999) Economic theory and conformism, vol 68. Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham Glos
Zurück zum Zitat Maggi G, Morelli M (2006) Self enforcing voting in international organizations. Am Econ Rev 96(4):1137–1158CrossRef Maggi G, Morelli M (2006) Self enforcing voting in international organizations. Am Econ Rev 96(4):1137–1158CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Mansbridge JJ (1986) Why we lost the ERA. University of Chicago Press, Chicago Mansbridge JJ (1986) Why we lost the ERA. University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Zurück zum Zitat Moreno B, Ramos-Sosa MP (2015) Voting by conformity. Málaga Economic Theory Research Center. WP 2015-3 Moreno B, Ramos-Sosa MP (2015) Voting by conformity. Málaga Economic Theory Research Center. WP 2015-3
Zurück zum Zitat Postlewaite A (1998) The social basis of interdependent preferences. Eur Econ Rev 42(3):779–800CrossRef Postlewaite A (1998) The social basis of interdependent preferences. Eur Econ Rev 42(3):779–800CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Rivas J, Rodríguez-Álvarez C (2014) Deliberation, leadership and information aggregation. Documentos de Trabajo (ICAE) 4:1–34 Rivas J, Rodríguez-Álvarez C (2014) Deliberation, leadership and information aggregation. Documentos de Trabajo (ICAE) 4:1–34
Zurück zum Zitat Sobel J (2005) Interdependent preferences and reciprocity. J Econ Lit 43(2):392–436CrossRef Sobel J (2005) Interdependent preferences and reciprocity. J Econ Lit 43(2):392–436CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
Conformity in voting
verfasst von
Bernardo Moreno
María del Pino Ramos-Sosa
Publikationsdatum
18.01.2017
Verlag
Springer Berlin Heidelberg
Erschienen in
Social Choice and Welfare / Ausgabe 3/2017
Print ISSN: 0176-1714
Elektronische ISSN: 1432-217X
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-016-1023-7

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 3/2017

Social Choice and Welfare 3/2017 Zur Ausgabe

Premium Partner