Skip to main content
Erschienen in: AI & SOCIETY 2/2021

03.01.2021 | Original Article

Debate: what is personhood in the age of AI?

verfasst von: David J. Gunkel, Jordan Joseph Wales

Erschienen in: AI & SOCIETY | Ausgabe 2/2021

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

In a friendly interdisciplinary debate, we interrogate from several vantage points the question of “personhood” in light of contemporary and near-future forms of social AI. David J. Gunkel approaches the matter from a philosophical and legal standpoint, while Jordan Wales offers reflections theological and psychological. Attending to metaphysical, moral, social, and legal understandings of personhood, we ask about the position of apparently personal artificial intelligences in our society and individual lives. Re-examining the “person” and questioning prominent construals of that category, we hope to open new views upon urgent and much-discussed questions that, quite soon, may confront us in our daily lives.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 390 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe




 

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
It should be noted that this way of characterizing “natural person” is not “natural” but culturally specific. It has a distinctly European and Christian pedigree. The concept of “person” is individuated and specified according to the qualifying capability or a set of faculties that (it is assumed) naturally belong to an individual entity. This is the case beginning (at least) in the sixth century with Boethius’s (1973, chap. 3) definition, persona est naturae rationalis individua substantia (“a person is an individual substance of a rational nature”); continuing through John Locke’s characterization, “a thinking intelligent being that has reason and reflection and can consider itself as itself” (Locke 1998, sec. 2.27.9); and beyond (e.g. Strawson 1959; Taylor 1985). This is, however, not necessarily the correct or only way to formulate and define “person.” In a number of African traditions, like Ubuntu, person is not the natural condition of an individual human being, it is an achieved social condition. Instead of operationalizing the individuated “cogito ergo sum” of Descartes, this way of thinking proceeds from the adage: “I am because we are, and since we are, therefore I am” (Mbiti 1990, pp. 108–109). In these traditions (and it should be noted that this is not one univocal tradition but a constellation of different but related traditions), personhood is not something naturally belonging to an individual, but “something which has to be achieved, and it is not given simply because one is born of human seed” (Menkiti 1984, p. 172). Consideration of these important cultural differences in the way that “natural person” has been defined and characterized was not included as part of the prepared remarks during the debate. They did, however, figure prominently during the question and answer period. For more on this subject, see the collection of essays Ubuntu and Personhood, edited by James Ogude (2018).
 
2
The proposal, which was not adopted as originally written, immediately generated controversy as evidenced by 250 scientists, engineers and AI professionals who signed an open letter to the European Commission (2016) opposing the proposals and asserting that robots and AI, no matter how autonomous or intelligent they might appear to be, are nothing more than tools.
 
3
Some meanings of “person” (e.g. conferred legal and social statuses) refer first to how the object of the attribution will be treated, whereas natural personhood purposes to refer first to what the object is, independently of treatment. Oftentimes, natural personhood is seen as possessing an intrinsic “moral personhood” that demands a further attributed status or role within society—as in the rejection of slavery on the basis of human persons’ moral status. For a recent survey and argument, see Gordon (2020a, b), who would ground an individual’s intrinsic moral personhood in that individual’s functional capacities. I agree that moral personhood ought to be considered as recognized rather than conferred, with recognition motivated intrinsically by moral worth rather than instrumentally by the anticipated consequences of (non-)recognition. However, on the ground of this worth, I follow Robert Spaemann (2006): the individual’s personhood (natural and, in certain measures, moral) is intrinsic not to that individual’s capacities but to that individual’s membership in a kind, the mature members of which ordinarily have these capacities. This position accommodates the moral worth of both the very young and the severely disabled without reducing personhood to the merely biological category of humanity. On another note, while appreciating that many are wary of an all-sufficient “essentialism” because of its reductive possibilities, anti-metaphysical models have their own inadequacies. I would resist a definition of personhood as a solely a social achievement because, as Dr. Gunkel acknowledges, societies find it easy to deny personhood to certain groups. That being said, the concept of Ubuntu has affinities with the relationality wherein, by my definitions, personhood is exercised most fully.
 
4
Spaemann writes that “ancient applications of the word [person]”, “though they refer to human beings,” see these beings “not as instances of a kind or examples of a general concept, but as bearers of a social role (in the widest sense) or as occupants of a legal status. Behind this role and presupposed by it, there stands the bearer of the role,” not a subject who may or may not live in accord with his or her nature, but simply “the human nature itself.” In Stoicism, this nature itself is a role, but behind this still “there seems to be no subject at all” but only destiny (2006, p. 23).
 
5
On Old Testament views of God’s self-revelation see e.g. Preuss (1995, pp. 194–195). For New Testament developments, see e.g. Kittel (1964). Athanasius of Alexandria distinguishes between how God is revealed in time as Creator and how God eternally exists as Father and Son and Spirit (Anatolios 2018, pp. 129–131). In the late fourth century, Augustine’s De Trinitate (2012b, sec. 4.5.25) refines this view to its decisive Western form. By the appearances of the persons in history, God reveals his inner life so that it might become humans’ destination (Hill 1991, paras. 89–90).
 
6
That is to say, God’s tri-personal relationality, self-complete in the divine life, needs no external relation to live in a fully personal manner. Unlike the divine persons of the single God, human persons exist separately and so the full flourishing of their relational handing-over is accomplished by one person’s interiority freely going forth toward another in a relationship by which the other’s outward self-expression is also received into one’s own interior and understood as an expression of the other’s interior. On this view, our personhood is not fully expressed when abstracted from personal inter-relations, accomplished between persons, in community. (Even the Christian eremitical tradition has community with God, rather than mere solitude, as its orientation).
 
7
Narrower reckonings of personhood risk both being arbitrary and neglecting that in which apparently personal AIs would appear personal. Some invoke “rationality” without consciousness as sufficient for “mind” or “intelligence,” with speculative rationality as the capacity for logical syllogizing or calculation (Newell and Simon 1976; cf. Hobbes), and practical rationality as the capacity to accomplish goals in the best possible way (Russell and Norvig 2009, p. 2). However useful to AI advances, these reductions of rationality are inadequate to our discussion. First, a speculative “computationalism” holds that the simulation of ratiocination just is thought because thought is and only is a certain kind of calculation (Kim 2010, pp. 160–161). Irrespective of consciousness, then, AIs that implemented this kind could be said to think and (depending on what else might make up a person) could even be called persons. Yet this assumed separability of reasoning (let alone personhood) from consciousness is non-obvious. In much late antique, medieval (Van Nieuwenhove 2017), and Enlightenment (Kant) thought on the person, logical reasoning (ratio) is meaningful as such by the inseparably co-penetrating light of conscious apprehension (intellectus). This should give us pause. Second, for defining the person, practical rationality without consciousness ignores the dimension of personhood—self-aware subjectivity, a personal inner life—which we will feel ourselves to be meeting when we encounter a persuasive social AI. Culturally, we have found this viscerally horrifying (e.g. the Stepford wives). (Intriguingly, some propose that autistic persons varyingly experience those around them as goal-directed but without comprehensible interiority (Hamilton 2009).) Definitions of “person” without subjectivity and inter-subjectivity are blind to these distinctions. Beyond my scope, on “functionalism” see Piccinini (2010); Levin (2018).
 
8
I use the term “empathy” to designate the act of taking another’s thoughts and emotions into oneself, to know that person’s position—but I do not see this as meaning that we must remain confined to the horizon of that other's own assessment of this position. My use accords with what the Latin patristic and medieval traditions call compassio, whence our term “compassion.” To embrace rather than to be embraced by the horizon of the other person’s point of view is a refinement not always present in contemporary understandings of “empathy” (Lanzoni 2015; Stueber 2019), whence Bloom (2016) advocates a “compassion” of concern and outward acts by which one seeks to alleviate another’s ills, but without shared emotional or cognitive experience. I use “empathic compassion” to capture the richer compassio.
 
9
There will be not anything that it is “like” to be them along the lines of Nagel’s (1974) question “what is it like to be a bat?” (I am intentionally loose in my terminology, not wishing to commit to a particular model or definition).
 
10
While not decisive, this analogy is the basis for the Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness (Low 2012): “[T]he weight of evidence indicates that humans are not unique in possessing the neurological substrates that generate consciousness. Non-human animals, including all mammals and birds, and many other creatures, including octopuses, also possess these neurological substrates.” Here, consciousness is not a thing alongside the living bodily organism, but a property of that living organism.
 
11
To simulate a brain is at present impossible. We lack a map of the “connectome,” i.e. of each and every neuron’s connections. Moreover, the complex interactions of interconnected neurons are incompletely understood (Bentley et al. 2016; Schafer 2018), as also are the roles of environmental and proprioceptive feedback—i.e. the influence of embodied situatedness (Jabr 2012). Even were these worked out, the why and what of the network’s interior activity could still be uninterpretable to us, despite its intelligible outward behavior; cf. Pearl (2019).
 
12
The question of artifactual consciousness in whatever degree is contentious. Near-future AIs based on contemporary techniques will be apparent but unreal persons because their interior lives will be behaviorally hinted but subjectively unreal. My comments on the neural network align somewhat with Block (1978) and with Searle’s (1980) “Chinese Room.” On whether phenomenal consciousness would be metaphysically possible in any future artifact, here are some doubts: If any sort of non-biological machine can have true phenomenal consciousness (and not just a behavioral or functional simulation thereof), then consciousness is not limited to the physical processes (i.e. embodied nervous systems) that produce the conscious experience and subjective self-awareness from which humans (at least) engage in the social relations I term “personal.” Options then abound. Some, deeming it impossible to account for consciousness by physics or indeed any human inquiry, posit that consciousness, like mass, is a fundamental property of matter, such that “the basic physical constituents of the universe have mental properties, whether or not they are living organisms” (Nagel 1978, p. 181). Others argue that, by some deep laws, not the matter of neurons but the functional or information-processing properties of a system give rise to conscious subjectivity (Chalmers 2010, pp. 26–27; Tegmark 2017, p. 304). This would preserve, even prioritize, the relevance of consciousness as an intrinsic property of certain patterns of information processing—but it begs the question of what counts as “information” and its processing. Chalmers (2011) proposes that not just any physical change would count, but only causal physical relationships of a particular sort, the sort that formally parallels the causal state transitions that accomplish information processing in the brain. This would escape Searle’s famous jibe that the vibrating molecules of his wall could be said to compute a word processing program, under a certain (selective) mapping (Searle 1992, pp. 208–209; Harnad 1994). Even under Chalmers’ constraints, one might question whether “information” and “computation” can ever be said to be observer-independent properties of a natural or engineered system. Paul Schweizer (2019a, b) argues that Chalmers’ definitions do not even apply to all instances of what we would consider to be computation; the only factor common across all instances is an observer’s discernment of computation in them. To reconcile Chalmers and Schweizer easily, we could adopt the broadest possible interpretation, which Chalmers seems willing at least to entertain, that consciousness of some sort exists wherever there is causation, and so “[e]xperience is information from the inside; physics is information from the outside” (Chalmers 1997, pp. 293–310). If consciousness and information processing are intrinsically present only because everywhere present, then Chalmers’ position approaches panpsychism.
 
13
Spaemann writes (2006, p. 243): “Let us take the severely disabled first. Are we dealing with a thing? Or with an animal of a different kind? Of course not. We are dealing with a patient.... [A] human being incapable of personal expression... [we see] as a sick human in need of help. We look for ways of helping if we can, for ways of restoring ‘nature’, providing an opportunity to take that place reserved for him or her in the community of persons until death.” Our response to the disabled, he concludes, “is the acid test of our humanity.”
 
14
John Danaher’s “ethical behaviorism” (2019, 2020a, b) opposes this position but seems to beg the original question. For Danaher, a robot’s “observable behavioural relations and reactions to us [and the world]” are “sufficient epistemic ground or warrant” for our believing of its relationship with us what we would believe of humans under similar circumstances (2020a). In the case of evaluating whether the friendship-conditions of “mutuality” (true, intentional good-will) and “authenticity” (presenting oneself as one is) are met on the part of friend-behaving agents, we ought—against the claim that robots have no inner life and therefore meet neither of these conditions—apply epistemically the same behavioral standard that we apply to humans and animals (Danaher 2019). Danaher does not wish to assert ontological behaviorism (that friendship just is behavior), only methodological behaviorism (behavior is the ground upon which we assert friendship and its inner states). However, he seems to slip from (1) arguing that the ordinary epistemic standards are met and should be enough for our belief that friendship-conditions are met, to (2) arguing that therefore the friendship conditions are met: “[I]t is (technically) possible for the mutuality and authenticity conditions to be satisfied in our friendships with robots” such that “there is nothing illusory or unreal about robotic friendships” (2019). For, if “[t]here is no inner state that you need to seek to confirm” the intentions and love expressed in human behavior, then you ought not seek such a state for robots but ought to affirm that “simulated feeling can be genuine feeling, not fake or dishonest feeling” (2020b). This is not a conflation if he is simply drawing the epistemically warranted conclusion, but is the case of human beings in fact analogically parallel to that of robots? True, someday robots may satisfy the epistemic conditions based upon which we ordinarily are justified in believing that the mutuality and authenticity conditions have been satisfied in human relationships. But even so, does the exotic case of the apparently personal robot justify our continuing to rely on the naïve epistemic behaviorism that serves us well for fellow humans? The experience of an Imax planetarium satisfies the epistemic conditions based upon which I ordinarily feel myself justified (and am justified) in believing that I am gazing upon the night sky. Only additional knowledge (e.g. “this is a planetarium, not a window”)—not immediately available in the context of the planetarium experience—persuades me that this is not a night sky. Lacking this additional knowledge, a naïve viewer would be justified (although incorrect) in believing that she was observing the night sky. This, however, does not make the simulated night sky to be a genuine night sky, and the answer to whether or not that difference matters ought to hinge on more than whether or not the naïve observer is epistemically justified in her belief. So, when Danaher argues that we are justified in believing that the robot has met the conditions of true friendship, it is true that the robot has met the un-critiqued epistemic conditions for our belief in human friendship-conditions, but not true that, as Danaher would have it, “the mutuality and authenticity conditions [have been] satisfied in our friendships with robots” (2019). The satisfaction of epistemic grounds for believing friendship-conditions to be satisfied is not identical to the satisfaction of those friendship-conditions themselves, any more than footprints appearing without a foot are identical to the invisible man that we assume to have produced them. Danaher’s argument, then, amounts only to a restatement of the problem, and it invites us to interrogate the hidden assumptions that enable us easily (and I think rightly) to assert that these are sufficient grounds in the case of our assessing humans. Perhaps certain ontological assumptions (e.g. an analogy between others’ behavior and my own behavior as rooted in conscious experiences) are baked into our own epistemology—assumptions that, while experientially difficult to shake, might not actually hold in our “relationships” with robots. A potential middle term between our own interior states and the presumed states of those who behave like us is the appearance of identical material conditions—i.e. biology. The robot’s lack of a nervous system gives us reason for our intuition that it might not have the interior states by which it could accomplish mutuality and authenticity. I agree with Danaher that, “while shared biological properties might give us more grounds for believing in our human friends it is not clear that these grounds are necessary or sufficient for believing in [human] friendship” (2019). By analogy with the planetarium, however, a different object of friendship may require more extensive grounds because the different object challenges the general assumptions (biology, experience) that may underlie the assumed reliability of our epistemic assumptions (observation of behavior)—unless Danaher means to make behavioral performance not only the epistemic ground but also the actual object of reference for statements about mutuality. In this case, however, he will have arrived at the very ontological behaviorism that he wishes to avoid.
 
15
Despite millennia of domestication, dogs have lives of their own that set limits on our interactions with them. Future AI companions will not have such limits, except insofar as technology cannot supply a solution or as may enhance the experience of the end user.
 
16
See discussion and application to robots of this Aristotelian concept in Richardson (2016a, b).
 
17
This could be a slow but decisive habituation. As Joanna Bryson (2015) warns, “our behavior can radically change without a shift in either explicit or implicit motivations—with no deliberate decision to refocus.” Bryson worries (2010) that ascribing personhood to robots could sap the human social capital available for relationships with other human beings; humans might even choose the “easier” robots who are beholden to our whims. I build on this concern to ask whether the egocentric tendencies of socialization with robots might distort our expression of that which is most “personal” about us—our capacity for empathic self-gift and interpersonal communion.
 
18
On this theme applied to sex robots, see e.g. Harvey (2015) and Richardson (2015) in contrast to proponents such as Levy (2008).
 
19
Technological innovations like AI and socially interactive robots complicate the usual way of thinking about and resolving questions regarding moral and legal standing. Efforts to fit these entities into the existing moral and legal categories often strain against the limits of the very concepts that have been deployed, necessitating a kind of “conceptual re-engineering” or what Alexis Burgess and David Plunkett (2013) call “conceptual ethics.” Alexis Dyschkant, for instance, suggests that we might gain some traction in this effort by moving away from binary categorizations and thinking more in terms of a spectrum of differences: “We may benefit from remembering that being capable of having rights and duties is not always a zero sum game, and sometimes more like a spectrum. There are already lots of variations on which sorts of rights some humans have on the basis of their status as a prisoner or as a minor. Some humans have more rights and some have less. It seems plausible that animals could also exist on this spectrum.... While it would be ridiculous to give bonobos the ability to vote, that should not be a barrier to considering a bonobo a person in some respects.” (2015, p. 2108).
 
20
Augustine calls this “using” (uti) a thing rather than “enjoying” it (frui) (1996, sec. 1.3.3; 1.33.37). To “enjoy” is to find in the other thing one’s ultimate satisfaction; if a person or possession is “enjoyed,” one reduces that thing to oneself. Augustinian “use” is not to be confused with the egocentric “use” against which Kant warns and that Augustine would class as superbia. Augustinian “use” takes one’s relationship with the person or object up into the higher relation binding all to an origin and destiny in God. This is Augustine’s antidote to superbia.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Anatolios K (2018) Retrieving Nicaea: the development and meaning of Trinitarian Doctrine. Baker Academic, Grand Rapids Anatolios K (2018) Retrieving Nicaea: the development and meaning of Trinitarian Doctrine. Baker Academic, Grand Rapids
Zurück zum Zitat Athanasius of Alexandria (1980a) Orations against the Arians, Book III [Selections] [ca. 339–343]. In: Norris RA (ed) The Christological controversy, re-typeset ed. Fortress Press, Philadelphia, pp 65–78 Athanasius of Alexandria (1980a) Orations against the Arians, Book III [Selections] [ca. 339–343]. In: Norris RA (ed) The Christological controversy, re-typeset ed. Fortress Press, Philadelphia, pp 65–78
Zurück zum Zitat Athanasius of Alexandria (1980b) Orations against the Arians, Book I [ca. 339–343]. In: Rusch WC (ed) The Trinitarian controversy, re-typeset ed. Fortress Press, Philadelphia, pp 55–104 Athanasius of Alexandria (1980b) Orations against the Arians, Book I [ca. 339–343]. In: Rusch WC (ed) The Trinitarian controversy, re-typeset ed. Fortress Press, Philadelphia, pp 55–104
Zurück zum Zitat Augustine of Hippo (1887) The City of God, against the Pagans [413–427]. In: St. Augustine’s City of God and Christian Doctrine. Christian Literature Publishing Co., Buffalo Augustine of Hippo (1887) The City of God, against the Pagans [413–427]. In: St. Augustine’s City of God and Christian Doctrine. Christian Literature Publishing Co., Buffalo
Zurück zum Zitat Augustine of Hippo (1996) Teaching Christianity [De doctrina Christiana] [396–426], 1st edn. New City Press, Hyde Park Augustine of Hippo (1996) Teaching Christianity [De doctrina Christiana] [396–426], 1st edn. New City Press, Hyde Park
Zurück zum Zitat Augustine of Hippo (2004) The literal meaning of genesis [De Genesi ad litteram] [401–415]. On genesis. New City Press, Hyde Park, pp 168–506 Augustine of Hippo (2004) The literal meaning of genesis [De Genesi ad litteram] [401–415]. On genesis. New City Press, Hyde Park, pp 168–506
Zurück zum Zitat Augustine of Hippo (2012a) The confessions [397–401], 2nd edn. New City Press, Hyde Park Augustine of Hippo (2012a) The confessions [397–401], 2nd edn. New City Press, Hyde Park
Zurück zum Zitat Augustine of Hippo (2012b) The Trinity [399–419], 2nd edn. New City Press, Hyde Park Augustine of Hippo (2012b) The Trinity [399–419], 2nd edn. New City Press, Hyde Park
Zurück zum Zitat Bauckham R (2008) Jesus and the God of Israel: God crucified and other studies on the New Testament’s Christology of Divine identity. Eerdmans, Grand Rapids Bauckham R (2008) Jesus and the God of Israel: God crucified and other studies on the New Testament’s Christology of Divine identity. Eerdmans, Grand Rapids
Zurück zum Zitat Benford G, Malartre E (2007) Beyond human: living with robots and cyborgs, 1st edn. Forge Books, New York Benford G, Malartre E (2007) Beyond human: living with robots and cyborgs, 1st edn. Forge Books, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Block N (1978) Troubles with functionalism. Minn Stud Philos Sci 9:261–325 Block N (1978) Troubles with functionalism. Minn Stud Philos Sci 9:261–325
Zurück zum Zitat Bloom P (2016) Against empathy: the case for rational compassion. Ecco, New York Bloom P (2016) Against empathy: the case for rational compassion. Ecco, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Boethius (1973) Contra Eutychen [ca. 513]. In: theological tractates. The consolation of philosophy. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Boethius (1973) Contra Eutychen [ca. 513]. In: theological tractates. The consolation of philosophy. Harvard University Press, Cambridge
Zurück zum Zitat Bryson JJ (2010) Robots should be slaves. In: Wilks Y (ed) Close engagements with artificial companions: key social, psychological, ethical and design issues. John Benjamins Publishing Company, Philadelphia, pp 63–74CrossRef Bryson JJ (2010) Robots should be slaves. In: Wilks Y (ed) Close engagements with artificial companions: key social, psychological, ethical and design issues. John Benjamins Publishing Company, Philadelphia, pp 63–74CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bryson JJ (2015) Artificial intelligence and pro-social behaviour. In: Misselhorn C (ed) Collective agency and cooperation in natural and artificial systems: explanation, implementation and simulation. Springer International, Cham, pp 281–306CrossRef Bryson JJ (2015) Artificial intelligence and pro-social behaviour. In: Misselhorn C (ed) Collective agency and cooperation in natural and artificial systems: explanation, implementation and simulation. Springer International, Cham, pp 281–306CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bryson JJ, Diamantis ME, Grant TD (2017) Of, for, and by the people: the legal lacuna of synthetic persons. Artif Intell Law 25:273–291CrossRef Bryson JJ, Diamantis ME, Grant TD (2017) Of, for, and by the people: the legal lacuna of synthetic persons. Artif Intell Law 25:273–291CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Carpenter J (2016) Culture and human-robot interaction in militarized spaces. Ashgate, BurlingtonCrossRef Carpenter J (2016) Culture and human-robot interaction in militarized spaces. Ashgate, BurlingtonCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Chalmers DJ (1997) The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory, Revised ed. Oxford University Press, New York Chalmers DJ (1997) The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory, Revised ed. Oxford University Press, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Chalmers DJ (2010) The character of consciousness, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, New YorkCrossRef Chalmers DJ (2010) The character of consciousness, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, New YorkCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Chalmers DJ (2011) A computational foundation for the study of cognition. J Cogn Sci 12:323–357 Chalmers DJ (2011) A computational foundation for the study of cognition. J Cogn Sci 12:323–357
Zurück zum Zitat Chopra S, White LF (2011) A legal theory for autonomous artificial agents. University of Michigan Press, Ann ArborCrossRef Chopra S, White LF (2011) A legal theory for autonomous artificial agents. University of Michigan Press, Ann ArborCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Committee on Legal Affairs (2016) Draft report with recommendations to the commission on civil law rules on robotics. European Parliament Committee on Legal Affairs (2016) Draft report with recommendations to the commission on civil law rules on robotics. European Parliament
Zurück zum Zitat Darling K, Nandy P, Breazeal C (2015) Empathic concern and the effect of stories in human-robot interaction. In: 2015 24th IEEE International Symposium on robot and human interactive communication (RO-MAN). pp 770–775 Darling K, Nandy P, Breazeal C (2015) Empathic concern and the effect of stories in human-robot interaction. In: 2015 24th IEEE International Symposium on robot and human interactive communication (RO-MAN). pp 770–775
Zurück zum Zitat Dennett DC (1998) Brainstorms: philosophical essays on mind and psychology. MIT Press, Cambridge Dennett DC (1998) Brainstorms: philosophical essays on mind and psychology. MIT Press, Cambridge
Zurück zum Zitat Derrida J (2005) Paper machine. Trans. Rachel Bowlby, 1st edn. Stanford University Press, Stanford Derrida J (2005) Paper machine. Trans. Rachel Bowlby, 1st edn. Stanford University Press, Stanford
Zurück zum Zitat Douglass F (2016) Narrative of the life of Frederick Douglass, an American slave: written by himself [1845], Critical. Yale University Press, New Haven Douglass F (2016) Narrative of the life of Frederick Douglass, an American slave: written by himself [1845], Critical. Yale University Press, New Haven
Zurück zum Zitat Dyschkant A (2015) Legal personhood: how we are getting it wrong. Univ Ill Law Rev 2015:2075–2110 Dyschkant A (2015) Legal personhood: how we are getting it wrong. Univ Ill Law Rev 2015:2075–2110
Zurück zum Zitat Gelin R (2016) The domestic robot: ethical and technical concerns. In: Ferreira MIA, Sequeira JS, Tokhi MO, et al. (eds) A world with robots (International Conference on Robot Ethics: ICRE 2015). Springer, New York Gelin R (2016) The domestic robot: ethical and technical concerns. In: Ferreira MIA, Sequeira JS, Tokhi MO, et al. (eds) A world with robots (International Conference on Robot Ethics: ICRE 2015). Springer, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Gill C (1996) Personality in Greek epic, tragedy, and philosophy: the self in dialogue. Oxford University Press, Oxford Gill C (1996) Personality in Greek epic, tragedy, and philosophy: the self in dialogue. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Zurück zum Zitat Gregory I (1992) Moralia in Iob; Commento Morale a Giobbe 1 (I-VIII) [586–590]. Città Nuova, Rome Gregory I (1992) Moralia in Iob; Commento Morale a Giobbe 1 (I-VIII) [586–590]. Città Nuova, Rome
Zurück zum Zitat Gregory I (1997) Moralia in Iob; Commento Morale a Giobbe 3 (XIX-XXVII) [586–590]. Città Nuova, Rome Gregory I (1997) Moralia in Iob; Commento Morale a Giobbe 3 (XIX-XXVII) [586–590]. Città Nuova, Rome
Zurück zum Zitat Hill E (1991) Introduction. In: The trinity, 1st edn. New City Press, Hyde Park Hill E (1991) Introduction. In: The trinity, 1st edn. New City Press, Hyde Park
Zurück zum Zitat Hume D (1980) A treatise of human nature [1738–40]. Oxford University Press, New York Hume D (1980) A treatise of human nature [1738–40]. Oxford University Press, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Hurtado LW (2005) Lord Jesus Christ: devotion to Jesus in earliest Christianity. Eerdmans, Grand Rapids Hurtado LW (2005) Lord Jesus Christ: devotion to Jesus in earliest Christianity. Eerdmans, Grand Rapids
Zurück zum Zitat Hurtado LW (2018) Honoring the son: Jesus in earliest Christian devotional practice. Lexham Press, Bellingham Hurtado LW (2018) Honoring the son: Jesus in earliest Christian devotional practice. Lexham Press, Bellingham
Zurück zum Zitat Kim J (2010) Philosophy of Mind, 3rd edn. Routledge, Boulder, CO Kim J (2010) Philosophy of Mind, 3rd edn. Routledge, Boulder, CO
Zurück zum Zitat Kittel G (1964) δόξα. In: Friedrich G, Kittel G (eds) Theological dictionary of the new testament. Eerdmans, Grand Rapids, pp 233–255 Kittel G (1964) δόξα. In: Friedrich G, Kittel G (eds) Theological dictionary of the new testament. Eerdmans, Grand Rapids, pp 233–255
Zurück zum Zitat Kurki VA (2019) A theory of legal personhood. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRef Kurki VA (2019) A theory of legal personhood. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kurki VAJ, Pietrzykowski T (eds) (2017) Legal personhood: animals, artificial intelligence and the unborn. Springer International Publishing, Cham, Switzerland Kurki VAJ, Pietrzykowski T (eds) (2017) Legal personhood: animals, artificial intelligence and the unborn. Springer International Publishing, Cham, Switzerland
Zurück zum Zitat Leong B, Selinger E (2019) Robot eyes wide shut: understanding dishonest anthropomorphism. In: Proceedings of the Conference on fairness, accountability, and transparency. Association for Computing Machinery, New York, pp 299–308 Leong B, Selinger E (2019) Robot eyes wide shut: understanding dishonest anthropomorphism. In: Proceedings of the Conference on fairness, accountability, and transparency. Association for Computing Machinery, New York, pp 299–308
Zurück zum Zitat Levin J (2018) Functionalism. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy, Fall 2018. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University Levin J (2018) Functionalism. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy, Fall 2018. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University
Zurück zum Zitat Levy D (2008) Love and sex with robots: the evolution of human-robot relationships. Harper Perennial, New York Levy D (2008) Love and sex with robots: the evolution of human-robot relationships. Harper Perennial, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Locke J (1998) An essay concerning human understanding [1689], Revised. Penguin Classics, London Locke J (1998) An essay concerning human understanding [1689], Revised. Penguin Classics, London
Zurück zum Zitat Low P (2012) The Cambridge declaration on consciousness. In: Panskepp J, Reiss D, Edelman D, et al. (eds). Churchill College, University of Cambridge Low P (2012) The Cambridge declaration on consciousness. In: Panskepp J, Reiss D, Edelman D, et al. (eds). Churchill College, University of Cambridge
Zurück zum Zitat Markoff J (2015) Machines of loving grace: the quest for common ground between humans and robots. Ecco, New York Markoff J (2015) Machines of loving grace: the quest for common ground between humans and robots. Ecco, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Mauss M (1985) A category of the human mind: the notion of person; the notion of self. In: Carrithers M, Collins S, Lukes S, Mauss M (eds) The category of the person: anthropology, philosophy, history. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Mauss M (1985) A category of the human mind: the notion of person; the notion of self. In: Carrithers M, Collins S, Lukes S, Mauss M (eds) The category of the person: anthropology, philosophy, history. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Zurück zum Zitat Mbiti JS (1990) African religions & philosophy, 2nd edn. Heinemann, Portsmouth Mbiti JS (1990) African religions & philosophy, 2nd edn. Heinemann, Portsmouth
Zurück zum Zitat Menkiti IA (1984) Person and community in African traditional thought. In: Wright RA (ed) African philosophy, 3rd edn. University Press of America, Lanham, pp 171–182 Menkiti IA (1984) Person and community in African traditional thought. In: Wright RA (ed) African philosophy, 3rd edn. University Press of America, Lanham, pp 171–182
Zurück zum Zitat Nagel T (1978) Panpsychism. Mortal questions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 181–195 Nagel T (1978) Panpsychism. Mortal questions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 181–195
Zurück zum Zitat Najork M (2016) Using machine learning to improve the email experience. In: Proceedings of the 25th ACM International Conference on information and knowledge management. p 891 Najork M (2016) Using machine learning to improve the email experience. In: Proceedings of the 25th ACM International Conference on information and knowledge management. p 891
Zurück zum Zitat Ogude J (2018) Ubuntu and personhood. Africa World Press, Trenton Ogude J (2018) Ubuntu and personhood. Africa World Press, Trenton
Zurück zum Zitat Pearl J (2019) The limitations of opaque learning machines. In: Brockman J (ed) Possible minds: twenty-five ways of looking at AI, 1st edn. Penguin Press, New York, pp 13–19 Pearl J (2019) The limitations of opaque learning machines. In: Brockman J (ed) Possible minds: twenty-five ways of looking at AI, 1st edn. Penguin Press, New York, pp 13–19
Zurück zum Zitat Preuss HD (1995) Old testament theology. Westminster John Knox Press, Louisville Preuss HD (1995) Old testament theology. Westminster John Knox Press, Louisville
Zurück zum Zitat Reeves B, Nass C (2003) The media equation: how people treat computers, television, and new media like real people and places, New Edition. CSLI, Stanford Reeves B, Nass C (2003) The media equation: how people treat computers, television, and new media like real people and places, New Edition. CSLI, Stanford
Zurück zum Zitat Richardson K (2016a) Are sex robots as bad as killing robots? In: Seibt J, Nørskov M, Andersen SS (eds) What social robots can and should do: proceedings of robophilosophy 2016/TRANSOR 2016. IOS Press, Amsterdam, pp 27–31 Richardson K (2016a) Are sex robots as bad as killing robots? In: Seibt J, Nørskov M, Andersen SS (eds) What social robots can and should do: proceedings of robophilosophy 2016/TRANSOR 2016. IOS Press, Amsterdam, pp 27–31
Zurück zum Zitat Rist JM (2020) What is a Person?: Realities, constructs, illusions, 1st edn. Cambridge University Press, New York Rist JM (2020) What is a Person?: Realities, constructs, illusions, 1st edn. Cambridge University Press, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Russell S, Norvig P (2009) Artificial intelligence: a modern approach, 3rd edn. Pearson, Upper Saddle RiverMATH Russell S, Norvig P (2009) Artificial intelligence: a modern approach, 3rd edn. Pearson, Upper Saddle RiverMATH
Zurück zum Zitat Salmond JW (1902) Jurisprudence, Or the Theory of the Law. Stevens and Haynes, London Salmond JW (1902) Jurisprudence, Or the Theory of the Law. Stevens and Haynes, London
Zurück zum Zitat Schweizer P (2019b) Computation in physical systems: a normative mapping account. In: Berkich D, d’Alfonso MV (eds) On the cognitive, ethical, and scientific dimensions of artificial intelligence: themes from IACAP 2016. Springer International Publishing, Cham, pp 27–47CrossRef Schweizer P (2019b) Computation in physical systems: a normative mapping account. In: Berkich D, d’Alfonso MV (eds) On the cognitive, ethical, and scientific dimensions of artificial intelligence: themes from IACAP 2016. Springer International Publishing, Cham, pp 27–47CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Searle JR (1980) Minds, brains, and programs. Behav Brain Sci 3:417–457CrossRef Searle JR (1980) Minds, brains, and programs. Behav Brain Sci 3:417–457CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Siedentop L (2014) Inventing the individual: the origins of western liberalism, 1st edn. Belknap Press, CambridgeCrossRef Siedentop L (2014) Inventing the individual: the origins of western liberalism, 1st edn. Belknap Press, CambridgeCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Singer P (2009) Speciesism and moral status. Metaphilosophy 40:567–581CrossRef Singer P (2009) Speciesism and moral status. Metaphilosophy 40:567–581CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Solum LB (1992) Legal personhood for artificial intelligences. N C Law Rev 70:1231–1287 Solum LB (1992) Legal personhood for artificial intelligences. N C Law Rev 70:1231–1287
Zurück zum Zitat Spaemann R (2006) Persons: the difference between “someone” and “something.” Oxford University Press, New York Spaemann R (2006) Persons: the difference between “someone” and “something.” Oxford University Press, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Strawson PF (1959) Individuals: an essay in descriptive metaphysics. Methuen & Co, London Strawson PF (1959) Individuals: an essay in descriptive metaphysics. Methuen & Co, London
Zurück zum Zitat Taylor C (1985) The person. In: Carrithers M, Collins S, Lukes S (eds) The category of the person, First Paperback Edition. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 257–281 Taylor C (1985) The person. In: Carrithers M, Collins S, Lukes S (eds) The category of the person, First Paperback Edition. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 257–281
Zurück zum Zitat Tegmark M (2017) Life 3.0: being human in the age of artificial intelligence. Knopf, New York Tegmark M (2017) Life 3.0: being human in the age of artificial intelligence. Knopf, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Tertullian of Carthage (2011) Against Praxeas [ca. 213]: The text edited, with an introduction, translation, and commentary, bilingual, Reprint Edition. Wipf & Stock Pub, Eugene Tertullian of Carthage (2011) Against Praxeas [ca. 213]: The text edited, with an introduction, translation, and commentary, bilingual, Reprint Edition. Wipf & Stock Pub, Eugene
Zurück zum Zitat Turner J (2018) Robot rules: regulating artificial intelligence, 1st edn. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, Switzerland Turner J (2018) Robot rules: regulating artificial intelligence, 1st edn. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham, Switzerland
Zurück zum Zitat United States Supreme Court (1964) Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U.S. 184 United States Supreme Court (1964) Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U.S. 184
Zurück zum Zitat Wiener N (1988) The human use of human beings: cybernetics and society, New Edition. Da Capo Press, New York Wiener N (1988) The human use of human beings: cybernetics and society, New Edition. Da Capo Press, New York
Metadaten
Titel
Debate: what is personhood in the age of AI?
verfasst von
David J. Gunkel
Jordan Joseph Wales
Publikationsdatum
03.01.2021
Verlag
Springer London
Erschienen in
AI & SOCIETY / Ausgabe 2/2021
Print ISSN: 0951-5666
Elektronische ISSN: 1435-5655
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-020-01129-1

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 2/2021

AI & SOCIETY 2/2021 Zur Ausgabe

Premium Partner