Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Journal of Business Ethics 4/2013

01.09.2013

East Meets West: Toward a Universal Ethic of Virtue for Global Business

verfasst von: Daryl Koehn

Erschienen in: Journal of Business Ethics | Ausgabe 4/2013

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Rudyard Kipling famously penned, “East is East, West is West, and never the twain shall meet.” His poetic line suggests that Eastern and Western cultures are irreconcilably different and that their members engage in fundamentally incommensurable ethical practices. This paper argues that differing cultures do not necessarily operate by incommensurable moral principles. On the contrary, if we adopt a virtue ethics perspective, we discover that East and West are always meeting because their virtues share a natural basis and structure. This article sketches the rudiments of what a universal virtue ethic might look like. Such an ethic is especially relevant and valuable in this era of global business.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
As I have argued elsewhere, referring to “Asian” ethics or “Western” ethics is problematic because these geographical regions are huge and contain diverse communities. Moreover, cultures are not static nor are they isolated from each other. Cultures are continually cross-pollinating each other with ideas. However, in this paper, I have retained references to Eastern and Western ethics because these terms belong to the discourse of moral relativists who want to insist upon the vast disparity in cultures and their ethics (see, e.g., Quintelier and Fessler 2012). As I argue in this paper, pace the cultural ethical relativists, these cultures are not in fact so different insofar as elements of virtue ethics expounded by Aristotle and Confucius and manifested in countries as diverse as France (Western) and China (Eastern) are remarkably the same.
 
2
The only author I have found who has attempted a sustained and multi-topic comparison of Confucius and Aristotle is Yu (1998a). My analysis differs from his in several crucial respects. First, Yu is not especially interested in arguing for the possibility of a universal virtue of ethic as a counter to ethical relativism. Second, he is really contrasting Confucianism with Aristotle insofar as he draws on texts by Mencius and on other “Confucian” classics, not confining himself to the Analects (whose comments are traditionally imputed at least in part to Confucius). I prefer to stay close to the Analects because it makes it easier to stay focused on the highly similar structure and nature of virtue as argued for by two thinkers. I do not have to refract the arguments about virtue through an entire interpretive tradition. Third, I am interested in points of similarity either not discussed or not highlighted by Yu—e.g., the role and relevance of experience, the ability to cope with so-called “moral luck,” the crucial importance of shame, the focus on an internal locus of control, and the part played by the larger political community in the development of virtue. While I concur with Yu that both thinkers have a natural basis for virtue and view virtue as habitual, I disagree with his assertion that Aristotle’s ethic revolves around a distinction between virtuous activity and the possession of virtue, while Confucius has no such distinction. In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle’s general thrust is that virtue is valuable insofar as we act well—hence, his claim that a “virtuous” person who spends his or her entire life asleep would be virtuous only in an equivocal sense (Aristotle 1985, pp. 1095b25–1096a5). The real worth of virtue lies in its action-directing and action-modifying force. In my view, Aristotle and Confucius are in perfect accord on this score. Confucius, too, praises as virtuous not those who say noble things but those who enact virtue on a daily basis. For example, he praises his student Yen Hui who listens well to Confucius, incorporates what he hears into practice, and who finds joy in quotidian activities (Confucius 1997, p. 2.9, 6.11). Like Aristotle, Confucius would not have found Yen Hui of much ethical interest if the young man had spent his entire day sleeping. It is the endless active cultivation of virtue that is Confucius’ focus (Confucius 1997, p. 6.18, 7.3, 7.8, 7.28).
 
3
In addition, there is considerable anecdotal evidence suggesting that multinational firms do not necessarily suffer when they take what we in the West would see as the ethical high road. One huge American-based computer company decided it would stop paying bribes to customs officials in India. The CEO was warned by fellow computer firm managers that his decision, while perhaps morally commendable, would mean corporate disaster. The firm's computers would never be allowed to leave airport warehouses. Despite this dire prediction, the CEO stuck to his guns. He met with local officials and quietly told them that, although his predecessor may have sanctioned the payment of bribes, under his leadership, the firm would no longer pay bribes to expedite shipments. The firm soon found that its shipments were moving faster than ever before. When customs officials realized that there was nothing to be gained by holding up these shipments, they simply let the computers through. By making the morally right choice, the CEO gained a competitive advantage. I do not claim that such choices always have a happy ending, but I would argue that there is no compelling evidence that firms that act in accordance with high moral standards consistently suffer business losses.
 
4
Both Aristotelianism and Confucianism stress that virtue lies in a mean (Confucius 1997, p. 6.26; Aristotle 1985, p. 1106a2-30). I have consciously refrained from discussing this apparent similarity for several reasons. First, this particular issue is one that has recently been canvassed by several thinkers (Sim 2004; Xia 2009). Second, to do this issue justice, I would have to discuss at some length what Aristotle, in my view, does and does not compass within his notion of a mean “relative to us.” That topic itself is quite complex and very contentious as evidenced by Urmson’s claim that “few philosophical theories have been more frequently and more grossly misunderstood…than the doctrine of the mean” (Urmson 1988, p. 28). Third, the Confucian take on the idea of a mean is equally complex (Legge 1930; Leys 1997; Ames and Hall 2001), relating to complicated ideas of harmony, physics, process, etc. Consequently, to compare the two in any persuasive way would require a small treatise on its own.
 
5
All quotations are taken from Aristotle (1985). I have quoted from two different editions of the Confucius and have clearly indicated which edition I am citing at each point.
 
6
McLeod (2009) argues that Aristotle, unlike Confucius, makes morality depend primarily upon the exercise of individual reason. In my view, McLeod’s approach is overly simplistic because (1) he forgets that Aristotle is quite clear that the development of reason is itself a social/political process and (2) because he wrongly assumes that Confucius thinks virtue is acquired through a kind of slavish adherence to social norms.
 
7
Indeed, it would be worth investigating whether Asian-Americans, Asian-Canadians, etc., are thriving in the West at least in part because the Confucian virtue ethic overlaps so considerably with the Aristotelian ethic of virtue. As far as I know, no one has even raised this question, much less studied it.
 
8
Tu (1999, p. 292) also stresses that Confucius’ ethic aims at bringing human beings into harmony with the cosmos: “A life informed and enriched by an anthropocosmic vision is not merely human but fully human, which means a sympathetic resonance in and a mutual responsiveness to the will of Heaven.”
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Abratt, R., Nel, D., & Higgs, N. (1992). An examination of the ethical beliefs of managers using selected scenarios in a cross-cultural environment. Journal of Business Ethics, 11, 29–35.CrossRef Abratt, R., Nel, D., & Higgs, N. (1992). An examination of the ethical beliefs of managers using selected scenarios in a cross-cultural environment. Journal of Business Ethics, 11, 29–35.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ames, R., & Hall, D. (2001). Focusing the familiar: A translation and interpretation of the Zhongyong. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press). Ames, R., & Hall, D. (2001). Focusing the familiar: A translation and interpretation of the Zhongyong. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press).
Zurück zum Zitat Aristotle. (1985). Nicomachean ethics (T. Irwin, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co. Aristotle. (1985). Nicomachean ethics (T. Irwin, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.
Zurück zum Zitat Arjoon, S. (2000). Virtue theory as a dynamic theory of business. Journal of Business Ethics, 28(2), 159–178.CrossRef Arjoon, S. (2000). Virtue theory as a dynamic theory of business. Journal of Business Ethics, 28(2), 159–178.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Athanassoulis, N. (2005). Morality, moral luck and responsibility: Fortune’s web. New York: Palgrave.CrossRef Athanassoulis, N. (2005). Morality, moral luck and responsibility: Fortune’s web. New York: Palgrave.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Boyle, J. (1992). Natural law and the ethics of tradition. In R. P. George (Ed.), Natural law theory: Contemporary essays (pp. 3–30). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Boyle, J. (1992). Natural law and the ethics of tradition. In R. P. George (Ed.), Natural law theory: Contemporary essays (pp. 3–30). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Charles, J. D. (2010). Saving a bad marriage: Political liberalism and the natural law, a review of Christopher Wolfe, natural law liberalism. Modern Age, 52(1), 71. Charles, J. D. (2010). Saving a bad marriage: Political liberalism and the natural law, a review of Christopher Wolfe, natural law liberalism. Modern Age, 52(1), 71.
Zurück zum Zitat Confucius. (1997) Analects. (D. C. Lau, Trans.). London: Penguin Books. Confucius. (1997) Analects. (D. C. Lau, Trans.). London: Penguin Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Confucius. (2003). Analects. (E. Slingerland, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co. Confucius. (2003). Analects. (E. Slingerland, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.
Zurück zum Zitat Dancy, J. (2006). Ethics without principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dancy, J. (2006). Ethics without principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Garver, E. (2006). Confronting Aristotle’s ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRef Garver, E. (2006). Confronting Aristotle’s ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gier, N. (2004). The virtue of non-violence: From Gautama to Gandhi. Albany: SUNY Press. Gier, N. (2004). The virtue of non-violence: From Gautama to Gandhi. Albany: SUNY Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Harman, G. (2000). Moral relativism defended. In G. Harman (Ed.), Explaining value and other essays in moral philosophy (pp. 3–19). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Harman, G. (2000). Moral relativism defended. In G. Harman (Ed.), Explaining value and other essays in moral philosophy (pp. 3–19). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Herman, B. (2000). Morality and everyday Life. Proceedings and Addresses of the APA, 74(2), 29–45. Herman, B. (2000). Morality and everyday Life. Proceedings and Addresses of the APA, 74(2), 29–45.
Zurück zum Zitat Herodotus. (2003). The histories (A. de Selincourt, Trans.). London: Penguin Classics. Herodotus. (2003). The histories (A. de Selincourt, Trans.). London: Penguin Classics.
Zurück zum Zitat Hofstede, G. (1980). Culture’s consequences: International differences in work-related values. Beverly Hills: Sage. Hofstede, G. (1980). Culture’s consequences: International differences in work-related values. Beverly Hills: Sage.
Zurück zum Zitat Hofstede, G. (1983). National cultures in four dimensions: A research-theory of cultural dimensions among nations. International Studies of Management and Organization, 13, 52–60. Hofstede, G. (1983). National cultures in four dimensions: A research-theory of cultural dimensions among nations. International Studies of Management and Organization, 13, 52–60.
Zurück zum Zitat Hofstede, G. (1984). The cultural relativity of the quality of life concept. Academy of Management Review, 9, 389–398. Hofstede, G. (1984). The cultural relativity of the quality of life concept. Academy of Management Review, 9, 389–398.
Zurück zum Zitat Hofstede, G., & Bond, M. H. (1988). The Confucius connection: From cultural roots to economic growth. Organizational Dynamics, 16(4), 5–21.CrossRef Hofstede, G., & Bond, M. H. (1988). The Confucius connection: From cultural roots to economic growth. Organizational Dynamics, 16(4), 5–21.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hume, D. (1975) Enquiry concerning the principles of morals. In L. A. Selby-Bigge (ed.), 3rd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hume, D. (1975) Enquiry concerning the principles of morals. In L. A. Selby-Bigge (ed.), 3rd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Ivanhoe, P. (2000). Confucian moral self-cultivation. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. Ivanhoe, P. (2000). Confucian moral self-cultivation. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.
Zurück zum Zitat Kirkland, R. (2008). Taoism and confucianism (through the Han Dynasty). Encyclopedia of Taoism, 1, 137–140. Kirkland, R. (2008). Taoism and confucianism (through the Han Dynasty). Encyclopedia of Taoism, 1, 137–140.
Zurück zum Zitat Kiss, E. (2006). Combining clarity and complexity: A layered approach to cross-cultural ethics. In R. Grant (Ed.), Naming evil, judging evil (pp. 139–173). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRef Kiss, E. (2006). Combining clarity and complexity: A layered approach to cross-cultural ethics. In R. Grant (Ed.), Naming evil, judging evil (pp. 139–173). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Koehn, D., & Leung, A. (2008). Dignity in Western versus Chinese cultures: Theoretical overview and practical illustrations. Business and Society Review, 113(4), 477–504.CrossRef Koehn, D., & Leung, A. (2008). Dignity in Western versus Chinese cultures: Theoretical overview and practical illustrations. Business and Society Review, 113(4), 477–504.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kupperman, J. J. (1999). Learning from Asian philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. Kupperman, J. J. (1999). Learning from Asian philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Legge, J. (1930). The four books, Confucian analects, the great learning, the doctrine of the mean, and the works of mencius. Shanghai: The Chinese Book Company. Legge, J. (1930). The four books, Confucian analects, the great learning, the doctrine of the mean, and the works of mencius. Shanghai: The Chinese Book Company.
Zurück zum Zitat Leung, A. (2000). Gender differences in guanxi behaviors: An examination of People’s Republic of China State-owned enterprises. International Review of Women and Leadership, 6, 48–59. Leung, A. (2000). Gender differences in guanxi behaviors: An examination of People’s Republic of China State-owned enterprises. International Review of Women and Leadership, 6, 48–59.
Zurück zum Zitat Leys, S. (1997). The analects of Confucius/translation and notes. New York: Norton Paperback. Leys, S. (1997). The analects of Confucius/translation and notes. New York: Norton Paperback.
Zurück zum Zitat Li, L. (2011). Performing bribery in China: Guanxi-practice, corruption with a human face. Journal of Contemporary China, 20(68), 1–20.CrossRef Li, L. (2011). Performing bribery in China: Guanxi-practice, corruption with a human face. Journal of Contemporary China, 20(68), 1–20.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat MacIntyre, A. (1981). After virtue. South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press. MacIntyre, A. (1981). After virtue. South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press.
Zurück zum Zitat McLeod, G. A. (2009). Moral personhood in confucius and aristotle, Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut, Storrs. McLeod, G. A. (2009). Moral personhood in confucius and aristotle, Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut, Storrs.
Zurück zum Zitat Porter, J. (2003). A tradition of civility: The natural law as a tradition of moral inquiry. Scottish Journal of Theology, 56(1), 27–48.CrossRef Porter, J. (2003). A tradition of civility: The natural law as a tradition of moral inquiry. Scottish Journal of Theology, 56(1), 27–48.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Provis, C. (2010). Virtuous decision making for business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 91(3), 3–16.CrossRef Provis, C. (2010). Virtuous decision making for business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 91(3), 3–16.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Quintelier, K. J. P., & Fessler, D. M. T. (2012). Varying versions of moral relativism: The philosophy and psychology of normative relativism. Biology and Philosophy, 27(1), 95–113.CrossRef Quintelier, K. J. P., & Fessler, D. M. T. (2012). Varying versions of moral relativism: The philosophy and psychology of normative relativism. Biology and Philosophy, 27(1), 95–113.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Rachels, J. (2010). The elements of moral philosophy (6th ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill Higher Education. Rachels, J. (2010). The elements of moral philosophy (6th ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill Higher Education.
Zurück zum Zitat Robertson, C. J., & Hoffman, J. J. (2000). How different are we? An investigation of Confucian values in the United States. Journal of Managerial Issues, 12(1), 34–48. Robertson, C. J., & Hoffman, J. J. (2000). How different are we? An investigation of Confucian values in the United States. Journal of Managerial Issues, 12(1), 34–48.
Zurück zum Zitat Romar, E. J. (2002). Virtue is good business: Confucianism as a practical business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 38(1–2), 119–131.CrossRef Romar, E. J. (2002). Virtue is good business: Confucianism as a practical business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 38(1–2), 119–131.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Rotter, J. B. (1954). Social learning and clinical psychology. New York: Prentice-Hall.CrossRef Rotter, J. B. (1954). Social learning and clinical psychology. New York: Prentice-Hall.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Sim, M. (2004). Harmony and the mean in the Nicomachean ethics and Zhongyong (中庸). Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy, 3(2), 253–280. Sim, M. (2004). Harmony and the mean in the Nicomachean ethics and Zhongyong (中庸). Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy, 3(2), 253–280.
Zurück zum Zitat Tu, W. (1999). Confucius: The embodiment of faith in humanity. World and I, 14(11), 292–305. Tu, W. (1999). Confucius: The embodiment of faith in humanity. World and I, 14(11), 292–305.
Zurück zum Zitat Urmson, J. O. (1988). Aristotle’s ethics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Urmson, J. O. (1988). Aristotle’s ethics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Zurück zum Zitat Vitell, S., Nwachukwu, S., & Barnes, J. (1993). The effects of culture on ethical decision-making: An application of Hofstede’s typology. Journal of Business Ethics, 12, 753–760.CrossRef Vitell, S., Nwachukwu, S., & Barnes, J. (1993). The effects of culture on ethical decision-making: An application of Hofstede’s typology. Journal of Business Ethics, 12, 753–760.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Wallis, V. (2004). Two old women: An Alaska legend of betrayal, courage, and survival. New York: Harper Perennial. Wallis, V. (2004). Two old women: An Alaska legend of betrayal, courage, and survival. New York: Harper Perennial.
Zurück zum Zitat Wong, D. B. (1984). Moral relativity. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Wong, D. B. (1984). Moral relativity. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Yu, J. (1998a). The ethics of Confucius and Aristotle. New York: Routledge. Yu, J. (1998a). The ethics of Confucius and Aristotle. New York: Routledge.
Zurück zum Zitat Yu, J. (1998b). Virtue: Confucius and Aristotle. Philosophy East & West, 48(2), 323–347.CrossRef Yu, J. (1998b). Virtue: Confucius and Aristotle. Philosophy East & West, 48(2), 323–347.CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
East Meets West: Toward a Universal Ethic of Virtue for Global Business
verfasst von
Daryl Koehn
Publikationsdatum
01.09.2013
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Erschienen in
Journal of Business Ethics / Ausgabe 4/2013
Print ISSN: 0167-4544
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-0697
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-013-1816-x

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 4/2013

Journal of Business Ethics 4/2013 Zur Ausgabe

Premium Partner