Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Public Choice 1-2/2016

02.09.2016

Endogenous competence and a limit to the Condorcet Jury Theorem

verfasst von: Bryan C. McCannon, Paul Walker

Erschienen in: Public Choice | Ausgabe 1-2/2016

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

The seminal contribution known as the Condorcet Jury Theorem observes that under a specific set of conditions an increase in the size of a group tasked with making a binary decision (“guilty or “innocent, say) leads to an improvement in the group’s ability to make the correct choice. An assumption that is not properly appreciated in the relevant literature is that the competency of the group members is assumed to be exogenous. In numerous applications, members of the group make investments to improve the accuracy of their decision making (e.g., pre-meeting efforts). We consider the collective action problem that arises. We show that if individual competence is endogenous, then increases in the group size encourages free riding. This trades off with the value of information aggregation. Thus, the value of the larger group size is muted. Extensions illustrate that if committee members are allowed to exit/not participate, the equilibrium committee size is reduced. Additionally, supermajority voting rules encourage investments and, consequently, individual competence.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
We are not the first to recognize the potential problem with endogenizing competence. Ben-Yashar and Nitzan (2001) raise the issue. They limit their analysis to a numerical example comparing a committee of three to a single decision maker, and document a reduction in aggregate competence when a social planner sets the effort investment. Persico (2003) allows uninformed agents to invest in a noisy signal before voting. Martinelli (2006) considers voters with differing preferences. He explores how investments in identifying the correct state-space are adjusted according to the size of the electorate (rather than using the common preference framework considered here). Hao and Suen (2009), in a review of committee decision-making models, also point out that the accuracy of a group’s decision can be worsened if the informational signals are acquired with a cost. They do not explore the interaction between this cost and group size. Additionally, the potential problem is hypothesized in McCannon (2011).
 
2
Thus, the literature on rationally-ignorant voters (Congleton 2001; Caplan 2007) and its moral arguments (Brennan 2011) is a useful reference. We differ, though, in that we formally explore how the quality of voter decision making adjusts with changes in the size of the relevant group. Our work is more closely related to that of Martinelli (2006), who extends the rational-ignorance framework to electorates whose investments in information decline to zero, but the decision nevertheless corresponds to the majoritys preference when the number of voters becomes arbitrarily large. We differ from these works by considering agents with common preferences.
 
3
Tullock’s main argument is that the belief that public goods problems in private markets require government intervention is incomplete. Government bureaucrats also suffer from the free-rider problem and, therefore, it is unclear whether government intervention is an effective way of dealing with public goods. As an example, he compares a designer of bumpers on Chevrolets to a politician. Both gain only a tiny fraction of the benefits they create, while incurring private costs. The primary difference between the two is that General Motors has an incentive to monitor and punish ineffective bumper designers, but that voters too suffer from free riding when holding politicians accountable. Also, see Tullock (1967) for a further discussion.
 
4
These are, of course, strong assumptions, but they are standard in the literature. For an overview discussion of the role of the interdependence in competence, see McCannon (2011). One would expect that free riding can be exacerbated if there is also positive serial correlation. This extension, though, is not considered here.
 
5
In practice, individuals differ substantially in their ability to acquire information and make good decisions. The assumption of identical competence production functions is made for convenience. Similarly, individuals may differ in the benefit they receive from a correct decision (or, relatedly, the disutility from an erroneous one), which would incentivize heterogeneous investments. The main argument (that there exists a free-riding problem in group decision making that is exacerbated in larger groups) can be expected to hold in these extended environments.
 
6
We make this assumption to minimize the difference between the model presented here and the standard framework employed in the literature. With strategic voting and abstention permitted, as in Feddersen and Pesendorfer (1996), one would expect that the decision by others to abstain would affect the effort investment. See Austen-Smith and Banks (1996) and Ben-Yashar (2006) for discussions on the impact of strategic voting.
 
7
The alternative name for this theorem is the “Two-Policemen-and-a-Drunk Theorem”: if two policemen are taking a drunk prisoner to his cell, then, regardless of the amount of wobbling that goes on, if the guards keep the prisoner between them and they make it to the cell, then the prisoner must also make it to the cell.
 
8
So long as \(\frac{dc}{de}>0\) \(\forall e\), assuming \(\underline{p}= \frac{1}{2}\) does not affect Proposition 2.
 
9
As with any theoretical model with a multiplicity of equilibria, comparative statics are difficult. Here, we deal with this difficulty by considering the addition of the new individuals to an existing cohort to retain the P partitions. Furthermore, the result presumes the existence of an equilibrium and illustrates that if an asymmetric equilibrium (defined in terms of the partition condition) exists, then the main result [Proposition 2] continues to hold.
 
10
To simplify the proof, the assumption \(\underline{p}>{1 \over 2N}+{1 \over 2}\) for a fixed e is employed, which is a sufficient (but not necessary) condition.
 
11
With a non-decisive supermajority rule, \(K_{N}(E,A)=K_{N}(E,B)=K_{N}(E)\) from (9).
 
12
This is a sufficient and not necessarily a necessary condition, since it guarantees the convexity of the function. For a simple majority (\(k=\frac{N+1}{2}\)), this requires only that \(p>\frac{1}{2}+\frac{1}{N-1}\). Also, the group size results consider increasing N by increments of d where, for common voting rules (\(\frac{1}{2}\), \(\frac{3}{5}\), \(\frac{2}{3}\), and \(\frac{3}{4}\) for example), these are small increments: 2, 5, 3, and 4, respectively.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Andreoni, J. A. (1995). Cooperation in public-goods experiments: kindness or confusion? American Economic Review, 85(4), 891–904. Andreoni, J. A. (1995). Cooperation in public-goods experiments: kindness or confusion? American Economic Review, 85(4), 891–904.
Zurück zum Zitat Austen-Smith, D., & Banks, J. S. (1996). Information aggregation, rationality, and the Condorcet Jury Theorem. American Political Science Review, 90(1), 34–45.CrossRef Austen-Smith, D., & Banks, J. S. (1996). Information aggregation, rationality, and the Condorcet Jury Theorem. American Political Science Review, 90(1), 34–45.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Black, D. (1958). The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Black, D. (1958). The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Ben-Yashar, R. (2006). Information is important to Condorcet jurors. Public Choice, 127(3), 305–319.CrossRef Ben-Yashar, R. (2006). Information is important to Condorcet jurors. Public Choice, 127(3), 305–319.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ben-Yashar, R., & Nitzan, S. I. (1997). The optimal decision rule for fixed-size committees in dichotomous choice situations: the general result. International Economic Review, 38(1), 175–186.CrossRef Ben-Yashar, R., & Nitzan, S. I. (1997). The optimal decision rule for fixed-size committees in dichotomous choice situations: the general result. International Economic Review, 38(1), 175–186.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ben-Yashar, R., & Nitzan, S. I. (2001). The invalidity of the Condorcet Jury Theorem under endogenous decision skills. Economics of Governance, 2(3), 243–249.CrossRef Ben-Yashar, R., & Nitzan, S. I. (2001). The invalidity of the Condorcet Jury Theorem under endogenous decision skills. Economics of Governance, 2(3), 243–249.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ben-Yashar, R., & Paroush, J. (2001). Optimal decision rules for fixed-sized committees in polychotomous choice situations. Social Choice and Welfare, 18(4), 737–746.CrossRef Ben-Yashar, R., & Paroush, J. (2001). Optimal decision rules for fixed-sized committees in polychotomous choice situations. Social Choice and Welfare, 18(4), 737–746.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ben-Yashar, R., Koh, W. T. H., & Nitzan, S. I. (2012). Is specialization desirable in committee decision making? Theory and Decision, 72(3), 341–357.CrossRef Ben-Yashar, R., Koh, W. T. H., & Nitzan, S. I. (2012). Is specialization desirable in committee decision making? Theory and Decision, 72(3), 341–357.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ben-Yashar, R., & Zahavi, M. (2011). The Condorcet Jury Theorem and extension of the franchise with rationally ignorant voters. Public Choice, 148(3–4), 435–443.CrossRef Ben-Yashar, R., & Zahavi, M. (2011). The Condorcet Jury Theorem and extension of the franchise with rationally ignorant voters. Public Choice, 148(3–4), 435–443.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Berend, D., & Sapir, L. (2005). Monotonicity in Condorcet Jury Theorem. Social Choice and Welfare, 24(1), 83–92.CrossRef Berend, D., & Sapir, L. (2005). Monotonicity in Condorcet Jury Theorem. Social Choice and Welfare, 24(1), 83–92.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Berg, S. (1993). Condorcet’s jury theorem revisited. European Journal of Political Economy, 9(3), 437–446.CrossRef Berg, S. (1993). Condorcet’s jury theorem revisited. European Journal of Political Economy, 9(3), 437–446.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Berg, S. (1996). Condorcet’s jury theorem and the reliability of majority voting. Group Decision and Negotiation, 5(3), 229–238.CrossRef Berg, S. (1996). Condorcet’s jury theorem and the reliability of majority voting. Group Decision and Negotiation, 5(3), 229–238.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Boland, P. J. (1989). Majority systems and the Condorcet Jury Theorem. Statistician, 38(3), 181–189.CrossRef Boland, P. J. (1989). Majority systems and the Condorcet Jury Theorem. Statistician, 38(3), 181–189.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent: logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.CrossRef Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent: logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Caplan, B. (2007). The myth of the rational voter. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Caplan, B. (2007). The myth of the rational voter. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Cason, T. N., & Khan, F. U. (1999). A Laboratory study of voluntary public goods provision with imperfect monitoring and communication. Journal of Development Economics, 58(2), 533–552.CrossRef Cason, T. N., & Khan, F. U. (1999). A Laboratory study of voluntary public goods provision with imperfect monitoring and communication. Journal of Development Economics, 58(2), 533–552.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Clarke, E. H. (1971). Multipart pricing of public goods. Public Choice, 11(1), 17–33.CrossRef Clarke, E. H. (1971). Multipart pricing of public goods. Public Choice, 11(1), 17–33.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Congleton, R. D. (2001). Rational ingorance, rational voter expectations, anbd public policy: a discrete informational foundation for fiscal illusion. Public Choice, 107(1), 35–64.CrossRef Congleton, R. D. (2001). Rational ingorance, rational voter expectations, anbd public policy: a discrete informational foundation for fiscal illusion. Public Choice, 107(1), 35–64.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Congleton, R. D. (2007). Informational limits to democratic public policy: The Jury Theorem, yardstick competition, and ignorance. Public Choice, 132(3), 333–352.CrossRef Congleton, R. D. (2007). Informational limits to democratic public policy: The Jury Theorem, yardstick competition, and ignorance. Public Choice, 132(3), 333–352.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Coughlan, P. J. (2000). In defense of unanimous jury verdicts: Mistrials, communication, and strategic voting. American Political Science Review, 94(2), 375–393.CrossRef Coughlan, P. J. (2000). In defense of unanimous jury verdicts: Mistrials, communication, and strategic voting. American Political Science Review, 94(2), 375–393.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat de Condorcet, M. J. A. N. (1985). Essai sur l’application de l’analyse a la probabilite des decisions rendues a la pluralite des voix. Paris: Imprimerie Royale. de Condorcet, M. J. A. N. (1985). Essai sur l’application de l’analyse a la probabilite des decisions rendues a la pluralite des voix. Paris: Imprimerie Royale.
Zurück zum Zitat Dougherty, K. L. (2015). Supermajority rules. In J. C. Heckelman & N. R. Miller (Eds.), Handbook of social choice and voting (pp. 102–116). Worcester: Edward Elgar.CrossRef Dougherty, K. L. (2015). Supermajority rules. In J. C. Heckelman & N. R. Miller (Eds.), Handbook of social choice and voting (pp. 102–116). Worcester: Edward Elgar.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Dougherty, K. L., & Edward, J. (2012). Voting for Pareto optimality: A multidimensional analysis. Public Choice, 151(3), 655–678.CrossRef Dougherty, K. L., & Edward, J. (2012). Voting for Pareto optimality: A multidimensional analysis. Public Choice, 151(3), 655–678.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Dougherty, K. L., Edward, J., & Ragan, R. (2015). The value of formalism: Re-examining external costs and decision costs with multiple groups. Public Choice, 163(1), 31–52.CrossRef Dougherty, K. L., Edward, J., & Ragan, R. (2015). The value of formalism: Re-examining external costs and decision costs with multiple groups. Public Choice, 163(1), 31–52.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper. Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper.
Zurück zum Zitat Feddersen, T. J., & Pesendorfer, W. (1996). The swing voters curse. American Economic Review, 86(3), 408–424. Feddersen, T. J., & Pesendorfer, W. (1996). The swing voters curse. American Economic Review, 86(3), 408–424.
Zurück zum Zitat Fey, M. (2003). A note on the Condorcet Jury Theorem with supermajority voting rules. Social Choice and Welfare, 20(1), 27–32.CrossRef Fey, M. (2003). A note on the Condorcet Jury Theorem with supermajority voting rules. Social Choice and Welfare, 20(1), 27–32.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gabel, M. J., & Shipan, C. R. (2004). A social choice perspective to expert consensus panels. Journal of Health Economics, 23(3), 543–564.CrossRef Gabel, M. J., & Shipan, C. R. (2004). A social choice perspective to expert consensus panels. Journal of Health Economics, 23(3), 543–564.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gregory, M. E. (2010). Freedom in French enlightenment thought. New York: Peter Lang.CrossRef Gregory, M. E. (2010). Freedom in French enlightenment thought. New York: Peter Lang.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Grofman, B. (1975). A comment on democratic theory: A preliminary mathematical model. Public Choice, 21(1), 99–103.CrossRef Grofman, B. (1975). A comment on democratic theory: A preliminary mathematical model. Public Choice, 21(1), 99–103.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Grofman, B. (1978). Judgmental competence of individuals and groups in a dichotomous choice situation: Is a majority of heads better than one? Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 6(1), 47–60.CrossRef Grofman, B. (1978). Judgmental competence of individuals and groups in a dichotomous choice situation: Is a majority of heads better than one? Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 6(1), 47–60.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Groves, T. (1973). Incentives and teams. Econometrica, 41(4), 617–633.CrossRef Groves, T. (1973). Incentives and teams. Econometrica, 41(4), 617–633.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hao, L., & Suen, W. (2009). Decision-making in committees. Canadian Journal of Economics, 42(2), 359–392.CrossRef Hao, L., & Suen, W. (2009). Decision-making in committees. Canadian Journal of Economics, 42(2), 359–392.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Helland, E., & Raviv, Y. (2008). The optimal jury size when jury deliberation follows a random walk. Public Choice, 134(3), 255–262.CrossRef Helland, E., & Raviv, Y. (2008). The optimal jury size when jury deliberation follows a random walk. Public Choice, 134(3), 255–262.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hummel, P. (2010). Jury theorems with multiple alternatives. Social Choice and Welfare, 34(1), 65–103.CrossRef Hummel, P. (2010). Jury theorems with multiple alternatives. Social Choice and Welfare, 34(1), 65–103.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hummel, P. (2012). Deliberation in large juries with diverse preferences. Public Choice, 150(3), 595–608.CrossRef Hummel, P. (2012). Deliberation in large juries with diverse preferences. Public Choice, 150(3), 595–608.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Karotkin, D., & Paroush, J. (2003). Optimum committee size: Quality-versus-quantity dilemma. Social Choice and Welfare, 20(3), 429–441.CrossRef Karotkin, D., & Paroush, J. (2003). Optimum committee size: Quality-versus-quantity dilemma. Social Choice and Welfare, 20(3), 429–441.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kazmann, R. G. (1973). Democratic organization: A preliminary mathematical model. Public Choice, 16(1), 17–26.CrossRef Kazmann, R. G. (1973). Democratic organization: A preliminary mathematical model. Public Choice, 16(1), 17–26.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Klevorick, A. K., & Rothschild, M. (1979). A model of the jury decision process. Journal of Legal Studies, 8(1), 141–164.CrossRef Klevorick, A. K., & Rothschild, M. (1979). A model of the jury decision process. Journal of Legal Studies, 8(1), 141–164.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Koch, T., & Ridgley, M. (2000). The Condorcets jury theorem in a bioethical context: The dynamics of group decision making. Group Decision and Negotiation, 9(5), 379–392.CrossRef Koch, T., & Ridgley, M. (2000). The Condorcets jury theorem in a bioethical context: The dynamics of group decision making. Group Decision and Negotiation, 9(5), 379–392.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ladha, K. K. (1992). The Condorcet Jury Theorem, free speech, and correlated votes. American Journal of Political Science, 36(3), 617–634.CrossRef Ladha, K. K. (1992). The Condorcet Jury Theorem, free speech, and correlated votes. American Journal of Political Science, 36(3), 617–634.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Marselli, R., McCannon, B. C., & Vannini, M. (2015). Bargaining in the shadow of arbitration. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 117(3), 356–368.CrossRef Marselli, R., McCannon, B. C., & Vannini, M. (2015). Bargaining in the shadow of arbitration. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 117(3), 356–368.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Mahoney, J. M., Sundaramurthy, C., & Mahoney, J. T. (1996). The differential impact of stockholder wealth of various antitakeover provisions. Managerial and Decision Economics, 17(6), 531–549.CrossRef Mahoney, J. M., Sundaramurthy, C., & Mahoney, J. T. (1996). The differential impact of stockholder wealth of various antitakeover provisions. Managerial and Decision Economics, 17(6), 531–549.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Martinelli, C. (2006). Would rational voters acquire costly information? Journal of Economic Theory, 129(1), 225–251.CrossRef Martinelli, C. (2006). Would rational voters acquire costly information? Journal of Economic Theory, 129(1), 225–251.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat McCannon, B. C. (2011). Jury size in classical Athens: An application of the Condorcet Jury Theorem. Kyklos, 64(1), 106–121.CrossRef McCannon, B. C. (2011). Jury size in classical Athens: An application of the Condorcet Jury Theorem. Kyklos, 64(1), 106–121.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat McCannon, B. C. (2015). Condorcet Jury Theorems. In J. C. Heckelman & N. R. Miller (Eds.), Handbook of social choice and voting (pp. 140–162). Worcester: Edward Elgar.CrossRef McCannon, B. C. (2015). Condorcet Jury Theorems. In J. C. Heckelman & N. R. Miller (Eds.), Handbook of social choice and voting (pp. 140–162). Worcester: Edward Elgar.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat McCannon, B. C. (2016). Leadership and motivation for public goods contributions, Working Paper. McCannon, B. C. (2016). Leadership and motivation for public goods contributions, Working Paper.
Zurück zum Zitat Miller, N. R. (1986). Information, electorates, and democracy: Some extensions and interpretations of the Condorcet Jury Theorem. In B. Grofman & G. Owen (Eds.), Information pooling and group decision making (pp. 173–192). Greenwich: JAI Press. Miller, N. R. (1986). Information, electorates, and democracy: Some extensions and interpretations of the Condorcet Jury Theorem. In B. Grofman & G. Owen (Eds.), Information pooling and group decision making (pp. 173–192). Greenwich: JAI Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Miller, N. R. (1996). Information, individual errors, and collective performance: Empirical evidence on the Condorcet Jury Theorem. Group Decision and Negotiation, 5(1), 211–228.CrossRef Miller, N. R. (1996). Information, individual errors, and collective performance: Empirical evidence on the Condorcet Jury Theorem. Group Decision and Negotiation, 5(1), 211–228.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Mueller, D. C. (2003). Public choice III. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Mueller, D. C. (2003). Public choice III. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Nitzan, S., & Paroush, J. (1982). Optimal decision rules in uncertain dichotomous choice situation. International Economic Review, 23, 289–297.CrossRef Nitzan, S., & Paroush, J. (1982). Optimal decision rules in uncertain dichotomous choice situation. International Economic Review, 23, 289–297.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Nitzan, S., & Paroush, J. (1984). Are qualified majority rules special? Public Choice, 42(3), 257–272.CrossRef Nitzan, S., & Paroush, J. (1984). Are qualified majority rules special? Public Choice, 42(3), 257–272.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Nitzan, S., & Paroush, J. (1985). Collective decision making: An economic outlook. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nitzan, S., & Paroush, J. (1985). Collective decision making: An economic outlook. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Olson, M. (1965). The logic of collective action. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Olson, M. (1965). The logic of collective action. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Paroush, J. (1988). Stay away from fair coins: A Condorcet Jury Theorem. Social Choice and Welfare, 15(1), 15–20.CrossRef Paroush, J. (1988). Stay away from fair coins: A Condorcet Jury Theorem. Social Choice and Welfare, 15(1), 15–20.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Persico, N. (2003). Committee design and endogenous information. Review of Economic Studies, 70(1), 1–27.CrossRef Persico, N. (2003). Committee design and endogenous information. Review of Economic Studies, 70(1), 1–27.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Schumpeter, J. A. (1943). Capitalism, socialism, and democracy. London: Routledge. Schumpeter, J. A. (1943). Capitalism, socialism, and democracy. London: Routledge.
Zurück zum Zitat Tullock, G. (1967). Toward a mathematics of politics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Tullock, G. (1967). Toward a mathematics of politics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Tullock, G. (1971). Public decisions as public goods. Journal of Political Economy, 79(4), 913–918.CrossRef Tullock, G. (1971). Public decisions as public goods. Journal of Political Economy, 79(4), 913–918.CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
Endogenous competence and a limit to the Condorcet Jury Theorem
verfasst von
Bryan C. McCannon
Paul Walker
Publikationsdatum
02.09.2016
Verlag
Springer US
Erschienen in
Public Choice / Ausgabe 1-2/2016
Print ISSN: 0048-5829
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-7101
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-016-0366-z

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 1-2/2016

Public Choice 1-2/2016 Zur Ausgabe

OriginalPaper

Identity voting

Premium Partner