Skip to main content

2016 | OriginalPaper | Buchkapitel

3. Justice, Property and Law in Post-communist Transformations of Property

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

This chapter extends the discussion of the theoretical underpinnings of the dominant ‘transitional’ measures deployed in post-communist Central Eastern Europe, which aimed to transform property regime(s). As shown in the previous chapter measures transforming state property into private property in post-communist CEE were distributive in character and not easily justifiable accordingly to a transitional justice framework. However, as they could still be justifiable in accordance with the major theories of justice, an overview of the main justifications for private property offered by classical liberal theory is provided, since these justifications were imported directly into post-communist CEE political discourses to rationalise the transformation of state property. On examination of these justifications it results, nevertheless, that none of them offer compelling arguments and responses to the question why the regime of property should be changed. That means that there is no theory of justice which could support changes in property regimes of the scale and type done in Central Eastern Europe during the transitional period. Nevertheless, this is not the only problem plaguing the theorisation of the CEE post-communist transformation of property, since there are further difficulties with the Anglo-American concept of property as a ‘bundle of rights’ when this concept is applied to explain post-communist transformations of property. As this concept obscures more than it illuminates how the changes in property regimes occurred during the post-communist transitional period (and what these changes have achieved), this chapter shows why is not appropriate to use the ‘bundle of rights’ idea to describe communist and post-communist property. Similarly, as the neoliberal ideology inspiring the CEE post-communist measures transforming property presents a number of inconsistencies, this chapter provides an analysis of this ideology and of its impact on CEE transformation of property. Finally, the capacity of the transitional post-communist law and of judicial institutions to correct administrative abuses during the transitional period is critically examined, and it is shown that contrary to the neoliberal assumptions, the judicial institutions lacked any propensity to deliver a just distribution of property.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
For example, with respect to administrative justice (lustration) measures, the former GDR, which was absorbed into the unified Germany, or the former Czechoslovakia.
 
2
Such dominance could be appreciated, for example, by taking in consideration the volume of legislative activity related to ‘retribution,’ in comparison with the volume of legislative activity related to property transformation(s) (privatisation and restitution).
 
3
In reality, even the arbitrary regimes appear to bend to the rule of giving (at least some sort of) reasons for their enactments or intended societal changes.
 
4
On the relationship between reason, justification and authority in democratic politics generally, see Raz (1990, 115–64).
 
5
Such an argument that transitional measures are justified as they are ‘transitional justice’ measures would be circular, at it would use the conclusion it whishes to proved as a premise for proving it.
 
6
Thus eschewing any assessment of the justness of such measure on the basis of the known ideas and theories of justice.
 
7
The reference if here to major theories of justice elaborated before a theory of transitional justice.
 
8
Supra, text to n 11–13 in Chap. 1; Arthur (2009, 326).
 
9
Part of the problem is related to the fact that in moral and political philosophy concepts such as ‘good’, ‘right’, or ‘just’ are what W.B. Gallie called “essentially contested concepts,” (Gallie 1955) or concepts which even though they appear to have some shared common meaning, the criteria for their application are contested in ways that could not be resolved.
 
10
For a discussion about the varieties of ‘liberalisms,’ the unifying themes and points of departure between various theorists of liberal tradition see Alan Ryan, ‘Liberalism,’ in Goodin et al. (2009, 360–382), and Gray (1995, XIII). For a discussion of differences between liberal orientations, East and West, see Suda and Musil (2000).
 
11
See e.g. Jeremy Waldron, ‘Liberalism, Political and Comprehensive,’ in Gaus and Kukathas (2004, 89–100).
 
12
See e.g. Williamson (1990, 2002), Rodrik (2006), Kanbur (2009) and Åslund (2007, 31–57).
 
13
The classic work on the myth of ‘self-regulating,’ ‘natural evolving’ market is Karl Polanyi’s, Great Transformation. (Polanyi 2001/1944). For more recent discussions of Polanyi’s central ideas, see Buğra and Ağartan (2007), Hann and Hart (2009). For the fallacious assumption that markets and their establishment are ‘cost free,’ see e.g. Van Brabant (1998, 109).
 
14
Here and in the next sentence, I use ‘utility’ as a shorthand word for economic growth, measurable in terms of the GDP, which arguably the politics pursued in the post-communist world were supposed to deliver. But see the critical assessment of such construction of ‘utility’ in Robinson (1962, 48).
 
15
See e.g. Blanchard (1997, iv), Berend (2009, 50–78), Widding (2001, 11–18).
 
16
Apparently, the prediction of increase in ‘welfare’ was based on ‘economic science’ in the neo-liberal dogma. However, for the point that the neoclassical economics had little to offer as scientific insight to the post-communist ‘transformation’ and for its inadequacy as a basis for systemic change by design, see Pickel (2001, 471–2). For the point that the post-communist transformations theories were political and not at all “scientific” see Pickel (2002, 105–114).
 
17
And as a consequence of ‘utility’.
 
18
The literature on this subject, and on the more general topic about the speed, depth and path of reform, is too wide to be even tentatively cited here, and in many ways resemble the earlier Ludwig von Misses exchanges with Karl Polyani. See with a title of example Havrylyshyn (2006), Mau: ‘Rossiiskie ekonomicheskie reformy glazami zapadnykh kritikov’ [Russian Economic Reforms in the Eyes of Western Critics], Voprosy ekonomiki 71 (11): 4–23 (1999), cited by Åslund (2007, 55). For one of the most outspoken and articulate critics see Stiglitz (2002). For an insightful analysis of the early debates, see Van Brabant (1998, 102–105).
 
19
Which cannot be easily defined in positive and specific terms. See e.g. Frank Knight, ‘On the Meaning of Justice,’ in Friedrich and Chapman (1963, 2–3); Peter Vallentyne, ‘Distributive Justice,’ in Goodin et al. (2009, 548).
 
20
See e.g. Campbell (2010), for a discussion of grounding justice ideas on concepts such as contract, right, entitlement, efficiency, desert or empowerment.
 
21
See e. g, Bernard Cullen, ‘Philosophical Theories of Justice,in Scherer (1992, 15–65).
 
22
When I refer to “Rawls,” I refer to the ideas developed by John Rawls in a series of essays starting with ‘Justice as Fairness’ in 1958 (Rawls 1958) and culminating with A Theory of Justice (Rawls 1999).
 
23
See Nozick (1974). For a discussion of libertarian themes, including those of Nozick, see e.g. Brighouse (2004, 84–105).
 
24
Assuming that the requirements of a given theory of justice are valid, and ignoring any substantial criticism to which any theory of justice could be submitted. For the major contemporary theories of justice see e.g. Habermas (1996), Rawls (1999), Nozick (1974), Barry (1989).
 
25
Respectively the discussion related to the challenges posed by post-communist property’s transformations to a theory of Transitional Justice.
 
26
John Bell, ‘Justice and the Law,’ in Scherer (1992, 140–141).
 
27
See for example Tebbit (2005, 6–9). Kuti (2009, 81) adds “Transitional Justice” to the major conceptions of justice in legal theory, without elaborating much about why it should be added.
 
28
See e.g. infra, text to n 4–11 in Chap. 5.
 
29
Weber defined this type of justice as the formalisation of just procedure. See Weber (1978, 809–15) See also Hart (1997, 157–67); Brad W. Hooker, ‘Justice,’ in Audi (1999, 456); Bell, ‘Justice and the Lawin Scherer (1992, 119); Solum (2004).
 
30
Brad W. Hooker, Justice, in Audi (1999, 456).
 
31
Hooker in Audi (1999, 457). Another species of justice, related to distributive justice is commutative justice, which concerns the fairness of wages, prices, and exchanges. In modern philosophy, however, “the debate about commutative justice has been overshadowed by the larger question of what constitutes a just distribution of resources”. Hooker, Ibid.
 
32
John Bell and Erik Schokkaert, ‘Interdisciplinary theory and research on justice,’ in Scherer (1992, 237).
 
33
See e.g. Sanders and Hamilton (2001, 31–65), Coleman (1992, 348–54).
 
34
Aristotle (2004, 81).
 
35
Fleischacker (2004). Accordingly to Fleischacker: “while Rawls’s secular understanding of justice and politics has ancient roots, what he includes in the content of justice does not. When Rawls tells us that retributive justice must be concerned with a person’s character but distributive justice should not be so concerned …, he almost reverses the view Aristotle had proposed of these two types of justice.He does not, however, seem aware of that.” Fleischacker (2004, 26).
 
36
Fleischacker (2004, 27).
 
37
See e.g. Brockner and Wisenfeld (1996), Van den Bos and Wilke (1997), Van den Bos et al. (1998), Fox (1999), Skitka (2009).
 
38
As for example, preferential treatment for one of the bidders or the selection of the winners by criteria which are not public, or change repeatedly, according to obscure reasons, etc.
 
39
For the CEE jurists the validity of the title is the first threshold question when discussing problems of ownership. In the case of state takings, which also apply to the communist era takings, the determination of the validity of state ownership consist in examining whether the taking was carried accordingly to the dispositions of a law valid and in vigor at the time of the taking. What is examined is not as much if the state had to power to enact the taking itself, but if the administrative act of taking was carried within the limits and with the powers specifically determined by the act of taking.
 
40
The property taken by the communist state in breach of its own decrees of nationalisation was held by the communist state with a ‘precarious’ title, and it was vulnerable to an action in recovery of the former owner of such property.
 
41
Arguably the main ‘game’ in post-communist property transformations.
 
42
See e.g. infra, text to n 78–79 in Chap. 4.
 
43
See for example ‘A Forum on Restitution,’ 2 E. Eur. Const. Rev. 30 (1993) 30–40, in particular Claus Offe and Frank Bönker’s contribution to the forum (Offe and Bönker 1993, 30–32).
 
44
For examples of arguments derived directly from the classical liberal theory in favor of private property developed by post-communist legislatures and constitutional courts, see Kuti (2009, 11, 29, 52).
 
45
LiCC, Ruling of 27 May 1994 ‘On the restoration of citizens’ ownership rights to land, quoted and commented by Kuti (2009, 52–54). Nevertheless, the Lithuanian Constitutional Court (as well the local post-communist governments) could not manage to remain until the end, on this “Lockean path,” as it noted that “restoration” meant partial reparation Kuti (2009, 52–53).
 
46
I owe this clarification to István Pogány.
 
47
Locke (1988).
 
48
Macpherson (1962, 199). Macpherson also observes that: “Locke’s astonishing achievement was to base property right on natural right and natural law, and then to remove all the natural law limits from the property right”. Macpherson Ibid. A second, legacy, more sinister, was related to the justification of European takings of Indian Lands. See e.g. Singer (1991, 18–19), Williams (1983, 3), Arneil (1996).
 
49
See e.g. Carter (1989, 13–26), for a critique of Locke’s attempt to derive property from labour.
 
50
It includes derivation from Desert, from Liberty, from Efficiency, from First Occupancy, from Personality, from Moral Development and from Human Nature. For the general discussion of all of them, see Carter (1989). Also, for a brief but comprehensive description of the philosophical problems posed by the methodological individualism for the liberal foundational themes, see Gray (1995, 45–55).
 
51
Carter (1989). One may wonder why choose Carter’s critique and ignore two other major contribution to the contemporary property theory, those of Waldron (1988) and Munzer (1990), that appeared almost in the same period with Carter’s work and are often critical of various justificatory arguments advanced in classical liberal theories of property. The foremost reason is that Carter critically evaluated all major arguments advanced for property in liberal thought. An indirect reason is that authors of pluralistic justificatory theories, such as Munzer, still have to show, “in a more rigorous manner that anyone so far has, that there are in fact multiple, independent and equally fundamental moral principles underlying the justification of private property.” Becker (1992, 199).
 
52
Carter (1989, 13).
 
53
Ibid, 15–24.
 
54
Ibid, 15–24 for examples of ambiguous uses of ‘labour’ by Locke, leading to fallacious argumentation in favour of basing property on labour.
 
55
Ibid.
 
56
Carter (1989, 26–36), Munzer (1990, 266–291), proposes a revised version of the labour—dessert theory, partially based on idea of labour as social activity i, but again, his theory seems limited to a justification of labour property, and not of property in general, and is prone to same criticism as that developed below. Because of restrictions of space I chose to treat Munzer’s ideas as a variant of Becker’s theory.
 
57
Also relied on by Bentham.
 
58
Carter (1989, 27).
 
59
Ibid. See also Becker (1977), for a variant of this argument.
 
60
Carter (1989, 28).
 
61
Ibid.
 
62
In this line of argument, labour is defined as what is above what is morally required to do for others. In order to justify private property under this line of argument, labour has to produce a thing which would not exist without labour, and others would lose nothing by being excluded from the product of labour.
 
63
I observe in passing that the acquirement of property and the giving away which characterised the post-communist early phase do not satisfy Nozick’s “entitlement theory” which assumes that is “just” a distribution which has arisen by means of just procedures.
 
64
See e.g. Carter (1989, 43). Or, in the words of Onora O’Neil, Nozick’s argument “presupposes, so does not demonstrate, that is wrong to interfere to restore disturbed patterns or end-states, and that such restorations are always distributive and violate individual property rights. But it is just these property rights which have yet to be established.” Onora O’Neil, ‘Nozick’s Entitlements,’ in Paul (1981, 308–309).
 
65
The negative freedom is freedom from interference of others with what one owns. The exclusive focus on negative liberty also lead to the establishment of a low baseline for freedom, which raise in turn question related to the justifiability of the bases chosen.
 
66
Carter (1989, 51–65). Albeit John Stuart Mill is the most famous classical utilitarian, Jeremy Bentham presents “the first and most compelling attempt” to found property rights upon utility (Carter 1989, 51).
 
67
See generally Ryan (1984).
 
68
Limitations of space do not allow me to discuss in more depth the problems related to the proof of ‘utility,’ or the fallacy of ‘composition’ (all individuals desire their own happiness versus all individuals desire the happiness of everyone) on which the concept of happiness is based in utilitarian though. See for such a discussion Solomon and Martin (2004, 346–52).
 
69
Carter (1989, 53–54).
 
70
Marx and Engels reject the rhetoric of necessity of property for labour to take place as follows: “It has been objected that upon the abolition of private property all work will cease, and universal laziness will overtake us. Accordingly to this, bourgeois society ought long ago to have gone to the dogs through sheer idleness; for those of its members who work, acquire nothing, and those who acquire anything do not work” Marx and Engels (1970, 49).
 
71
See e.g. Macpherson (1977, 33–34), observing that “To say that security of property, while perpetuating inequality, maximizes productivity, is not to say that it maximizes aggregate pleasure or utility. Bentham has…shifted his ground…from aggregate utility to aggregate wealth. But these are different. The shift is illegitimate, by his own principles, of diminishing utility, a smaller national wealth, equally distributed, could yield a larger aggregate utility than a larger national wealth, unequal distributed.” Macpherson, Ibid.
 
72
Carter (1989, 52–55).
 
73
Ibid., at 57–59, for the Rawlsian reformulation based upon cooperation.
 
74
Carter, Ibid, Persky (2010, 81). Following Leslie (1900/1950), Persky observes that the Utilitarian emphasis on experience never produced the broad social science it would seem to require.
 
75
Persky (2010, 78), following Hont’s (2005) observation that: “The economic efficacy of inequality was a paradox because it drove a wedge between the traditional egalitarian intuitions of Western moral thought and the guiding assumptions of modern political economy’’.
 
76
Carter (1989, 60).
 
77
Ibid.
 
78
Demsetz (1967, 350–53).
 
79
Carter (1989, 64).
 
80
Ibid.
 
81
Ibid, 64–65.
 
82
Ibid, 66–69. Carter provides a similar alternative explanation in response to Richard Posner’s variant of ‘efficiency of private property’ argument (Posner 1973).
 
83
Ibid, 70–71.
 
84
Carter (1989, 72). Instead of internalising externalities, private property can often externalise what would otherwise be internalities. Carter exemplifies with the situation of the capitalist owner factory that place on social welfare the workers she makes redundant. The post-communist privatisation is full of such externalisations.
 
85
Carter (1989, 74–75).
 
86
Ibid, 78–88. It is worthy to note the influence Kant plays in modern approaches to property.
 
87
Kant (1965).
 
88
Ibid, 34.
 
89
Carter (1989, 82).
 
90
Kant (1965, 51–53). This follows from the postulate of Kant that every object might be yours or mine, a permissive law of practical reason.
 
91
See Carter (1989, 82), for a more detailed argument on these lines.
 
92
See Carter (1989, 83). This also implies that Kant is wrong when assuming that universality is not only a necessary condition for establishing what is just, but also a sufficient condition.
 
93
See e.g. Carter (1989, 89) and Davies (2007, 86–112), (the latter for a discussion on Hegel’s & Locke’s theories of property from the perspective of critical legal studies school. For more recent contributions on Hegel’s theory of property rights, see e.g. Penner (1997, 169–186), Radin (1982, 1013–15), Radin (1993), Schnably (1993).
 
94
Hegel (1967). The presentation of the will is similar to that introduced in Hegel’s Phenomenology of the Spirit.
 
95
Hegel (1967, 235).
 
96
Hegel (1967, 236). Accordingly to Hegel: “In property my will is the will of a person; but a person is a unit and so property becomes the personality of this unitary will. Since property is the means whereby I give my will an embodiment, property must also have the character of being “this” or “mine” This is the important doctrine of the necessity of the private property.”.
 
97
Hegel (1967, 45).
 
98
Carter (1989, 98), citing Z.A Pelczynski and noting the influence of Roman law in the elaboration of Hegel’s ‘Abstract Right’ theory, and the March through civil society to the state of “the actuality of the ethical Idea”.
 
99
Carter (1989, 90), citing the obvious example of graffiti artists who reveal their personality through messages marked on the walls which they not own.
 
100
Carter (1989, 91–93).
 
101
Ibid, 94.
 
102
Ibid, 94–95, citing the famous master/slave dialectic of Hegel.
 
103
Carter (1989, 97) and Patten (1995), for the idea that Hegel’s argument, even successful, would only demonstrate that private property is a sufficient condition for developing and sustaining one’s personality, but not that is superior to other kinds of property arrangements that might accomplish the same objective.
 
104
Carter (1989, 102).
 
105
Ibid, 103–105.
 
106
Ibid, 107.
 
107
Carter (1989, 107).
 
108
Ibid, 112.
 
109
Ibid, 113–114.
 
110
Ibid, 114.
 
111
Hume (1972, 220).
 
112
Carter (1989, 115; 119).
 
113
Ibid, 118, for a discussion of these selfish inclinations in propertied societies. In terms of argumentation, this reasoning suffers from what is called ‘Inductive fallacy.’
 
114
Ibid.
 
115
Ibid, 120.
 
116
Ibid, 126.
 
117
Hohfeld (1966, 72). For a general discussion of Hohfeld’s conception of rights, see e.g. Edmunson (2004, 87–102). For developments of Hohfeldian themes, see e.g. Rainbolt (2006).
 
118
Carter (1989, 128–129).
 
119
This is the basic coherence problem affecting liberal justifications of property, discussed by Becker (1992, 200).
 
120
And “the failure to pay attention of this later aspect by individualist undermine “justification” of private property.” Carter (1989, 130).
 
121
Ibid, 139.
 
122
For a cogent critique of these analogies and their limitations, see Van Brabant (1998, 102–108).
 
123
When speaking about disputed boundaries, I had in mind examples such as the famous Fuller/Hart debate. See Hart (1958) and Fuller (1958).
 
124
See e.g. Appel (2000) for an analysis of the discourses of Vaclav Klaus, one of the arguably most successful CEE politicians claiming moral superiority of the new arrangements, and for a comparison between the Czech successful strategies of attaching the transformations to a new, forged “Euro-Czech” identity and the Russian unsuccessful ones.
 
125
See e.g. Edmunson (2004, 119), for a discussion related to the distinction between conceptual questions and justificatory questions related to rights.
 
126
See Penner (1995, 712). Penner later went on to criticise this understanding and advanced his own idea of property as a right in rem, in which the use and exclusion rights are linked (See e.g. Penner 1997, 68–73), but a full description or analysis of his vision is beyond my task in this context.
 
127
Penner (1995). This standard view is more pronounced in the U.S., where even the Restatement of Property begins with a Hohfeldian outline of rights and duties, although it is dominant also in Britain (Penner 1995, 714).
 
128
Similar to what Harris (1996, 29–32) calls ‘full-blooded ownership’.
 
129
Blacks Law Dictionary defines Propriété as: The French law term corresponding to our “property”: or the right of enjoying and of disposing of things in most absolute manner, subject only to the laws. See Black’s Law Dictionary (Fifth Ed., West Publishing Co, St.Paul Minn, 1979) 1088. For a description of the classic French property view of the Révolutionnaires, see e.g. Carbonnier (2001, 345–352), Gordley (1994) and Merryman (1973).
 
130
Penner (1995, 714). But see Ross (1957), for the most radical criticism of ownership idea as an intermediate legal concept (the latter being for Ross semantically just an insignificant conceptual ‘dummy.’).
 
131
See e.g. Thomas C. Grey, ‘The Disintegration of Property,’ in Pennock and Chapman (1980, 69–82).
 
132
See e.g. Underkuffler (2003, 11–14), discussing and reviewing several such approaches and ideas about property in legal theory.
 
133
Philbrick (1938). For the most condensed expression of the legal realists’ view of property as a contingent bundle of rights inextricably bound up with politics see Cohen (1935, 816). For the American constitutional developments in relation to property, see generally Ely (2007). Also. Hargreaves (1956, 17) and Vandevelde (1980).
 
134
I will have more to say about this nature, and about the differences between restitution and privatisation in the fourth chapter of this book. (see e.g. text to n 73–93 in Chap. 4).
 
135
See e.g. Campeanu (1986, 50–51), for the idea of property vacuum in communism, and for the idea of Stalinist replacement of an historical efficacious form of property with a form lacking any real definition and Frydman and Raoaczynski (1994).
 
136
See infra, text to n 65–101 in Chap. 3.
 
137
A. M. Honoré, ‘Ownership,’ in Guest (1961, 107–147).
 
138
Katherine Verdery, ‘The Obligations of Ownership: Restoring Rights to Land in Postsocialist Transylvania,’ in Verdery and Humphrey (2004, 139).
 
139
See e.g. Catherine Alexander, ‘Value, Relations, and Changing Bodies: Privatization and Property Rights in Kazakhstan,’ in Verdery and Humphrey (2004, 251); David Sneath, ‘Proprietary Regimes and Sociotechnical Systems: Rights over Land in Mongolia’s “Age of the Market,” in Verdery and Humphrey (2004, 161–184).
 
140
The multiple and significant problems posed by systemic transformations in more stable legal systems are discussed for example by Alexander (2003), Wonnell (2003), Kaplow (2003), Schauer (2003).
 
141
Verdery and Humphrey (2004, 139). This avoidance to control the process of fixing value partially explains, in addition to the priority given in the civil law to in kind restitution in comparison to compensation, the insistence for in kind restitution of the majority of laws of restitution in the post-communist CEE, with the notable exception of Hungary. Evidently these principles were not necessarily respected when property was ‘restituted’ to former owners. On this point, see e.g. Heller and Dagan (1999, 1407). Also, Richard (2005) for the development of ideas on fair value.
 
142
Offe and Bönker (1993, 32). But see Holmes (1993).
 
143
For the definition of ‘cultural trauma’ as a sociological concept, see Jeffrey C. Alexander, ‘Towards a Theory of Cultural Trauma,’ in Alexander et al. (2004) and Sztompka (2000a).
 
144
See e.g. Burawoy (1997); P. Abbott, M. Beck, ‘The post-Soviet health crisis: a sociological explanation,’ in Haerpfer et al. (2003).
 
145
See e.g. Piotr Sztompka, ‘The Trauma of Social Change: A Case of Post-Communist Societies,’ In Alexander et al. (2004).
 
146
See e.g. Benda-Beckmann and Eckert (2009), Thelen (2006), Peleikis (2006), Magoska (1993).
 
147
See e.g. Watson (1974), Watson (2001 193–218), Mattei (1994), Markovits (2004).
 
148
Although post-communist privatisation was by excellence a ‘distribution’ matter, as I have argued, the adversaries of ‘distributive’ policies supported it nonetheless with great enthusiasm.
 
149
Hart (1997, 89). Also Scott Shapiro: ‘What is the Internal Point of View?,’ on line at Social Science Research Network: http://​papers.​ssrn.​com/​sol3/​papers.​cfm?​abstract_​id=​937337 (last visited November 2014), and Patterson (1999).
 
150
For the point that neoclassical economics has little to offer for the scientific understanding of systemic transformations, as its preoccupations are abstract and far remote from ‘society’ see Pickel (2001, 471–72), and Bunge (1999). For the fallacious and empirical untested or contradicted conventional wisdom of economist and development scholars that strong formal property rights are necessary for economic growth, see Trebilcock and Veel (2008).
 
151
See e.g. Kornhauser (2001).
 
152
For the possible links between positive and normative theories of law, see Vermeule (2007).
 
153
Supra, Introduction, text to n 1–2.
 
154
Ibid.
 
155
See e.g. Davis and Trebilcock (2008), Trubek and Santos (2006).
 
156
See e.g. Davis and Trebilcock (2008), Trubek and Santos (2006), Gordon and Sylvester (2004), Antons (2003).
 
157
Ziauddin Sardar, ‘Development and the Locations of Eurocentrism,’ in Munck and O’Hearn (1999, 53). See also Pieterse (2010, 6), for an argument that the theorisation of economic growth came first at the core of development thinking while modernisation came afterwards and produced a theory of political modernisation in development thinking.
 
158
Preston (1996, 166–174), Gordon and Sylvester (2004).
 
159
Gordon and Sylvester (2004, 10–14), Preston (1996).
 
160
David Kennedy, ‘Political Choices and Development Common Sense,’ in Trubek and Santos (2006, 103–4).
 
161
Ibid, 115–17.
 
162
David M. Trubek, ‘The “Rule of Law” in Development Assistance: Past, Present, and Future,’ in Trubek and Santos (2006, 74–94, 76–78).
 
163
See e.g. Harvey (2005, 1, 20–30, 47–55); Kennedy, in Trubek and Santos (2006, 129–150). Although neoliberalism was increasingly dominant during the period, it was not the only thinking about development elaborated during the 1980s. Amartya Sen’s understanding of development as “capacitation” elaborated during the period was also influential, and this influence reflected for example in the Human Development Reports of UNDP, or in the post-development thinking. Pieterse (2010, 7).
 
164
See e.g. Harvey (2005, 1, 20–30, 47–55).
 
165
See e.g. Centeno and Cohen (2012), Broad (2006), Harvey (2005, 13–30).
 
166
Trubek, The Rule of Law in Trubek and Santos (2006, 81). The best known definition of neo-liberalism is that developed by David Harvey. Accordingly to Harvey, neo liberalism is: “A theory of political economic practices that proposes that human wellbeing can best be advanced by liberating individual entrepreneurial freedoms and skills within an institutional framework characterised by strong private property rights, free market, and free trade. The role of the state is to create and preserve an institutional framework appropriate to such practices.” Harvey (2005, 2).
 
167
Kennedy, Political Choices in Trubek and Santos (2006, 138).
 
168
See generally Turner (2008).
 
169
Kennedy, Political Choices in Trubek and Santos (2006, 138, 146–7).
 
170
See e.g. Lovett (2002) (noting the vagueness and imprecision of the descriptive accounts of the Rule of Law); Fallon Jr. (1997) (noting the imprecision of the meaning of Rule of Law), Radin (1989), (noting that the contestation of the Rule of Law ideal and the lack of a canonical formulation of its meaning).
 
171
Duncan Kennedy, ‘Three Globalizations of Law and Legal Thought: 1850–2000,’ in Trubek and Santos (2006, 19–73, 66–7).
 
172
Ibid.
 
173
See e.g. Frank Bönker, Klaus Müller, Andreas Pickel, ‘Cross-Disciplinary Approaches to Postcommunist Transformation: Context and Agenda’ in Bönker et al. (2002, 15–16).
 
174
The New Institutional Economics (“NIE”) is rooted in the work of Ronald Coase and identified most closely with that of Douglass North. See e.g. Richter (2005, 161), Knieper (2010, 115–18).
 
175
See e.g. Krever (2011); Julio Faundez, ‘Rule of Law or Washington Consensus: The Evolution of the World Bank’s Approach to Legal and Judicial Reform,’ in Kessaris (2009, 180–202); Alvaro Santos, ‘The World Bank’s Uses of the “Rule of Law” Promise in Economic Development,’ in Trubek and Santos (2006, 253–300).
 
176
See e.g. Krever (2011), arguing that the emergence of a new rule of law orthodoxy within World Bank’s development model is just a rhetorical shift and a continuation of neoliberalism’s core tenets, and Fine (2009).
 
177
Rodrik (2006, 978), suggesting the original Washington Consensus has been ‘augmented’ by additional reforms that are “heavily institutional in nature”.
 
178
Europenisation, another contested concept, is understood here in the first of its five meanings, respectively as the “extension of the policies, rules, institutional requirements and values in the new member states which acceded in 2004” and in 2007. See Simon Butler, ‘Theorizing Europenization,’ in Graziano and Vink (2008, 47).
 
179
Jan Drahokoupil, Bastiaan van Apeldoorn and Laura Horn, ‘Introduction: Towards a Critical Political Economy of European Governance’ in Apeldoorn et al. (2009, 4), Bohle (2006), Cafruny and Ryner (2003).
 
180
See e.g. Schwartz (2000), Procházka (2002).
 
181
See e.g. Scheppele (2001, 1–3). For an example of creative developments of western law ideas by the Hungarian Constitutional Court in the post-communist constitutional context the Hungarian constitutional court see e.g. Dupré (2003).
 
182
Wojciech Sadurski, ‘Post-communist Constitutional Courts in Search of Political Legitimacy,’ EUI Working Paper (2001).
 
183
Ibid, also for a list of early scholarship praising the role of constitutional courts.
 
184
Ibid.
 
185
Sweet (2000), Burley and Mattli (1993), Slaughter (2003), Ferejohn (2002).
 
186
Sadurski, Post communist Constitutional Courts; Bugaric (2001).
 
187
See e.g. Ramseyer (1994), showing that the ‘judicial activism’ in a country depends on the internal political conditions of that country, Ginsburg (2002), Smithey and Ishiyama (2002), Scheppele (1999), for the study of different variables influences on the ‘judicial activism’ of a court.
 
188
Hirschl (2004), Hirschl (2000), Ginsburg (2003).
 
189
Ganev (2007, 96–151).
 
190
András Sajó, ‘Social Rights as Middle Class Entitlements in Hungary,’ in Gargarella et al. (2006, 83–106), questioning the Hungarian court’s capacity to render progressive social change; Rosenberg (1993).
 
191
Sajó, Ibid.
 
192
Allen (2006). For the first fifteen post-communist years see also Karadjova (2004), stating that: “The bodies of the ECHR have managed to avoid problems related to restitution and reparations for past injustices by arguing that the right of restitution is not guaranteed by art 1 of Protocol 1 to the ECHR”, and it is debatable if the situation changed at all since then.
 
193
Pogány (2010).
 
194
Ganev (2009, 271).
 
195
The communist property, which has to be transformed, and the private property, which would be obtained by transformations.
 
196
The main legal devices used for transformation of property in post-communism.
 
197
Which we will adopt when discussing the court’s dealings with post-communist “restitution” in Poland and Romania in the seventh chapter of the study.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Alexander, J.C., 2002. On the Social Construction of Moral Universals The Holocaust’ from War Crime to Trauma Drama. European Journal of Social Theory, 5(1), pp. 5–85. Alexander, J.C., 2002. On the Social Construction of Moral Universals The Holocaust’ from War Crime to Trauma Drama. European Journal of Social Theory, 5(1), pp. 5–85.
Zurück zum Zitat Alexander, L., 2003. Introduction to the conference on legal transitions. J. Contemp. Legal Issues, 13, p. 1. Alexander, L., 2003. Introduction to the conference on legal transitions. J. Contemp. Legal Issues, 13, p. 1.
Zurück zum Zitat Alexander, J.C., Eyerman, R., Giesen, B., Smelser, N.J. and Sztompka, P., 2004. Cultural trauma and collective identity. Univ of California Press. Alexander, J.C., Eyerman, R., Giesen, B., Smelser, N.J. and Sztompka, P., 2004. Cultural trauma and collective identity. Univ of California Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Allen, T., 2006. Restitution and Transitional Justice in the European Court of Human Rights. Colum. J. Eur. L., 13, p. 1. Allen, T., 2006. Restitution and Transitional Justice in the European Court of Human Rights. Colum. J. Eur. L., 13, p. 1.
Zurück zum Zitat Antons, C. ed., 2003. Law and Development in East and South-East Asia. Routledge Antons, C. ed., 2003. Law and Development in East and South-East Asia. Routledge
Zurück zum Zitat Apeldoorn, B.V., Drahokoupil, J. and Horn, L., 2009. Contradictions and limits of neoliberal European governance: from Lisbon to Lisbon. Palgrave Macmillan. Apeldoorn, B.V., Drahokoupil, J. and Horn, L., 2009. Contradictions and limits of neoliberal European governance: from Lisbon to Lisbon. Palgrave Macmillan.
Zurück zum Zitat Appel, H., 2000. The ideological determinants of liberal economic reform: the case of privatization. World Politics, 52(04), pp. 520–549. Appel, H., 2000. The ideological determinants of liberal economic reform: the case of privatization. World Politics, 52(04), pp. 520–549.
Zurück zum Zitat Aristotle’s Nicomachean ethics. Cambridge University Press, 2004. Aristotle’s Nicomachean ethics. Cambridge University Press, 2004.
Zurück zum Zitat Arneil, B., 1996. John Locke and America: the defence of English colonialism. Oxford University Press. Arneil, B., 1996. John Locke and America: the defence of English colonialism. Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Arthur, P., 2009. How “Transitions” Reshaped Human Rights: A Conceptual History of Transitional Justice. Human Rights Quarterly, 31(2), pp. 321–367 Arthur, P., 2009. How “Transitions” Reshaped Human Rights: A Conceptual History of Transitional Justice. Human Rights Quarterly, 31(2), pp. 321–367
Zurück zum Zitat Åslund, A., 2007. How Capitalism Was Built. The Transformation of Central and Eastern Europe, Russia, and Central Asia. Cambridge University Press. Åslund, A., 2007. How Capitalism Was Built. The Transformation of Central and Eastern Europe, Russia, and Central Asia. Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Audi, R. ed., 1999. The Cambridge dictionary of philosophy. Cambridge university press. Audi, R. ed., 1999. The Cambridge dictionary of philosophy. Cambridge university press.
Zurück zum Zitat Banner, S., 2002. Transitions between property regimes. The Journal of Legal Studies, 31(S2), pp. S359–S371. Banner, S., 2002. Transitions between property regimes. The Journal of Legal Studies, 31(S2), pp. S359–S371.
Zurück zum Zitat Barry, B., 1989. Theories of justice (Vol. 1). Univ of California Press. Barry, B., 1989. Theories of justice (Vol. 1). Univ of California Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Becker, L.C., 1977. Property Rights : Philosophic Foundations.Routledge and Kegan Paul Becker, L.C., 1977. Property Rights : Philosophic Foundations.Routledge and Kegan Paul
Zurück zum Zitat Becker, L.C., 1992. Review: Too Much Property. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 21 (2), pp. 196–206 Becker, L.C., 1992. Review: Too Much Property. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 21 (2), pp. 196–206
Zurück zum Zitat Benda-Beckmann, F.V., Benda-Beckmann, K.V. and Eckert, J., 2009. Rules of law and laws of ruling: on the governance of law. Ashgate Publishing. Benda-Beckmann, F.V., Benda-Beckmann, K.V. and Eckert, J., 2009. Rules of law and laws of ruling: on the governance of law. Ashgate Publishing.
Zurück zum Zitat Bentham, J., 1970. An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. The Athlone Press. Bentham, J., 1970. An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. The Athlone Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Berend, T.I., 2009. From the Soviet bloc to the European Union: the economic and social transformation of Central and Eastern Europe since 1973. Cambridge University Press Berend, T.I., 2009. From the Soviet bloc to the European Union: the economic and social transformation of Central and Eastern Europe since 1973. Cambridge University Press
Zurück zum Zitat Blake, R.C., 2000. World Bank’s Draft Comprehensive Development Framework and the Micro-Paradigm of Law and Development, The. Yale Hum. Rts. & Dev. LJ, 3, p. 158. Blake, R.C., 2000. World Bank’s Draft Comprehensive Development Framework and the Micro-Paradigm of Law and Development, The. Yale Hum. Rts. & Dev. LJ, 3, p. 158.
Zurück zum Zitat Blanchard, O., 1997. The economics of post-communist transition. Oxford: Clarendon Press Blanchard, O., 1997. The economics of post-communist transition. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Zurück zum Zitat Bohle, D., 2006. Neoliberal hegemony, transnational capital and the terms of the EU’s eastward expansion. Capital & Class, 30(1), pp. 57–86. Bohle, D., 2006. Neoliberal hegemony, transnational capital and the terms of the EU’s eastward expansion. Capital & Class, 30(1), pp. 57–86.
Zurück zum Zitat Bönker, F., Müller, K., and Pickel, A. 2002. Postcommunist transformation and the social sciences: cross-disciplinary approaches. Rowman & Littlefield. Bönker, F., Müller, K., and Pickel, A. 2002. Postcommunist transformation and the social sciences: cross-disciplinary approaches. Rowman & Littlefield.
Zurück zum Zitat Brighouse, H., 2004. Justice. Cambridge: Polity. Brighouse, H., 2004. Justice. Cambridge: Polity.
Zurück zum Zitat Broad, R., 2006. Research, knowledge, and the art of ‘paradigm maintenance’: the World Bank’s Development Economics Vice-Presidency (DEC). Review of International Political Economy, 13(3), pp. 387–419. Broad, R., 2006. Research, knowledge, and the art of ‘paradigm maintenance’: the World Bank’s Development Economics Vice-Presidency (DEC). Review of International Political Economy, 13(3), pp. 387–419.
Zurück zum Zitat Brockner, J. and Wiesenfeld, B.M., 1996. An integrative framework for explaining reactions to decisions: interactive effects of outcomes and procedures. Psychological bulletin, 120(2), p. 189. Brockner, J. and Wiesenfeld, B.M., 1996. An integrative framework for explaining reactions to decisions: interactive effects of outcomes and procedures. Psychological bulletin, 120(2), p. 189.
Zurück zum Zitat Bugaric, B., 2001. Courts as policy-makers: Lessons from transition. Harv. Int’l LJ, 42, p. 247. Bugaric, B., 2001. Courts as policy-makers: Lessons from transition. Harv. Int’l LJ, 42, p. 247.
Zurück zum Zitat Buğra, A. and Ağartan, K. eds., 2007. Reading Karl Polanyi for the twenty-first century: market economy as a political project. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Buğra, A. and Ağartan, K. eds., 2007. Reading Karl Polanyi for the twenty-first century: market economy as a political project. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Zurück zum Zitat Bunge, M., 1999. Social science under debate: a philosophical perspective. University of Toronto Press. Bunge, M., 1999. Social science under debate: a philosophical perspective. University of Toronto Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Burawoy, M., 1997. Review Essay: The Soviet Descent into Capitalism. American Journal of Sociology, 102(5), pp. 1430–1444. Burawoy, M., 1997. Review Essay: The Soviet Descent into Capitalism. American Journal of Sociology, 102(5), pp. 1430–1444.
Zurück zum Zitat Burley, A.M. and Mattli, W., 1993. Europe before the Court: a political theory of legal integration. International organization, 47, pp. 41–41. Burley, A.M. and Mattli, W., 1993. Europe before the Court: a political theory of legal integration. International organization, 47, pp. 41–41.
Zurück zum Zitat Cafruny, A.W. and Ryner, M., 2003. A ruined fortress?: neoliberal hegemony and transformation in Europe. Rowman & Littlefield. Cafruny, A.W. and Ryner, M., 2003. A ruined fortress?: neoliberal hegemony and transformation in Europe. Rowman & Littlefield.
Zurück zum Zitat Campeanu, P., 1986. The origins of Stalinism: from Leninist revolution to Stalinist society. ME Sharpe. Campeanu, P., 1986. The origins of Stalinism: from Leninist revolution to Stalinist society. ME Sharpe.
Zurück zum Zitat Campbell, T., 2010. Justice: Issues in political theory. Palgrave Macmillan Campbell, T., 2010. Justice: Issues in political theory. Palgrave Macmillan
Zurück zum Zitat Carbonnier, J., 2001. Flexible droit pour une sociologie du droit sans rigueur. Paris: LGDJ. Carbonnier, J., 2001. Flexible droit pour une sociologie du droit sans rigueur. Paris: LGDJ.
Zurück zum Zitat Carter, A.B., 1989. The philosophical foundations of property rights. Harvester, Wheatsheaf. Carter, A.B., 1989. The philosophical foundations of property rights. Harvester, Wheatsheaf.
Zurück zum Zitat Centeno, M.A. and Cohen, J.N., 2012. The arc of neoliberalism. Annual Review of Sociology, 38, pp. 317–340 Centeno, M.A. and Cohen, J.N., 2012. The arc of neoliberalism. Annual Review of Sociology, 38, pp. 317–340
Zurück zum Zitat Cohen, F.S., 1935. Transcendental nonsense and the functional approach. Columbia Law Review, 35(6), pp. 809–849. Cohen, F.S., 1935. Transcendental nonsense and the functional approach. Columbia Law Review, 35(6), pp. 809–849.
Zurück zum Zitat Coleman, J.T., 1992. Risks and wrongs. Cambridge University Press. Coleman, J.T., 1992. Risks and wrongs. Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Davies, M., 2007. Property: Meanings, histories, theories. Routledge. Davies, M., 2007. Property: Meanings, histories, theories. Routledge.
Zurück zum Zitat Davis, K. and Trebilcock, M., 2008. The relationship between law and development: optimists versus skeptics. American Journal of Comparative Law, 56(4), pp. 895–946. Davis, K. and Trebilcock, M., 2008. The relationship between law and development: optimists versus skeptics. American Journal of Comparative Law, 56(4), pp. 895–946.
Zurück zum Zitat Demsetz, H., 1967. Toward a theory of property rights. The American economic review, pp. 347–359 Demsetz, H., 1967. Toward a theory of property rights. The American economic review, pp. 347–359
Zurück zum Zitat Dupré, C., 2003. Importing the law in post-communist transitions. Portland, OR: Hart Publishing. Dupré, C., 2003. Importing the law in post-communist transitions. Portland, OR: Hart Publishing.
Zurück zum Zitat Edmundson, W.A., 2004. An introduction to rights. Cambridge University Press. Edmundson, W.A., 2004. An introduction to rights. Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Ely Jr, J.W., 2007. The Guardian of Every Other Right: A Constitutional History of Property Rights. Oxford University Press. Ely Jr, J.W., 2007. The Guardian of Every Other Right: A Constitutional History of Property Rights. Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Fallon Jr, R.H., 1997. “The Rule of Law” as a Concept in Constitutional Discourse. Columbia Law Review, pp. 1–56. Fallon Jr, R.H., 1997. “The Rule of Law” as a Concept in Constitutional Discourse. Columbia Law Review, pp. 1–56.
Zurück zum Zitat Ferejohn, J., 2002. Judicializing politics, politicizing law. Law and Contemporary Problems, 65(3), pp. 41–68. Ferejohn, J., 2002. Judicializing politics, politicizing law. Law and Contemporary Problems, 65(3), pp. 41–68.
Zurück zum Zitat Fine, B., 2009. Development as Zombieconomics in the Age of Neoliberalism. Third World Quarterly, 30(5), pp. 885–904. Fine, B., 2009. Development as Zombieconomics in the Age of Neoliberalism. Third World Quarterly, 30(5), pp. 885–904.
Zurück zum Zitat Fleischacker, S., 2004. A short history of distributive justice. Harvard University Press. Fleischacker, S., 2004. A short history of distributive justice. Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Fox, D.R., 1999. Psycholegal scholarship’s contribution to false consciousness about injustice. Law and Human Behavior, 23(1), p. 9. Fox, D.R., 1999. Psycholegal scholarship’s contribution to false consciousness about injustice. Law and Human Behavior, 23(1), p. 9.
Zurück zum Zitat Friedman, L.M., 1967. Legal rules and the process of social change. Stanford Law Review, pp. 786–840. Friedman, L.M., 1967. Legal rules and the process of social change. Stanford Law Review, pp. 786–840.
Zurück zum Zitat Friedrich, C.J. and Chapman, J.W., 1963. Nomos VI: Justice. New York Friedrich, C.J. and Chapman, J.W., 1963. Nomos VI: Justice. New York
Zurück zum Zitat Frydman, R. and Rapaczynski, A., 1994. Privatization in Eastern Europe: Is the state withering away?. Central European University Press. Frydman, R. and Rapaczynski, A., 1994. Privatization in Eastern Europe: Is the state withering away?. Central European University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Fuller, L.L., 1958. Positivism and fidelity to law: A reply to Professor Hart. Harvard law review, pp. 630–672. Fuller, L.L., 1958. Positivism and fidelity to law: A reply to Professor Hart. Harvard law review, pp. 630–672.
Zurück zum Zitat Gallie, W.B., 1955, January. Essentially contested concepts. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian society (pp. 167–198). Harrison & Sons, Ltd. Gallie, W.B., 1955, January. Essentially contested concepts. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian society (pp. 167–198). Harrison & Sons, Ltd.
Zurück zum Zitat Ganev, V.I., 2007. Preying on the state: The transformation of Bulgaria after 1989. Cornell University Press Ganev, V.I., 2007. Preying on the state: The transformation of Bulgaria after 1989. Cornell University Press
Zurück zum Zitat Ganev, V.I., 2009. The rule of law as an institutionalized wager: constitutions, courts and transformative social dynamics in Eastern Europe. Hague Journal on the Rule of Law, 1(2), pp. 263–283. Ganev, V.I., 2009. The rule of law as an institutionalized wager: constitutions, courts and transformative social dynamics in Eastern Europe. Hague Journal on the Rule of Law, 1(2), pp. 263–283.
Zurück zum Zitat Gargarella, R., Domingo, P. and Roux, T. eds., 2006. Courts and Social Transformation in New Democracies: an institutional voice for the poor?. Ashgate Publishing, Ltd. Gargarella, R., Domingo, P. and Roux, T. eds., 2006. Courts and Social Transformation in New Democracies: an institutional voice for the poor?. Ashgate Publishing, Ltd.
Zurück zum Zitat Gaus, G.F. and Kukathas, C. eds., 2004. Handbook of political theory. Sage. Gaus, G.F. and Kukathas, C. eds., 2004. Handbook of political theory. Sage.
Zurück zum Zitat Ginsburg, T., 2002. Economic analysis and the design of constitutional courts. Theoretical Inquiries in Law, 3(1). Ginsburg, T., 2002. Economic analysis and the design of constitutional courts. Theoretical Inquiries in Law, 3(1).
Zurück zum Zitat Ginsburg, T., 2003. Judicial review in new democracies: Constitutional courts in Asian cases. Cambridge University Press. Ginsburg, T., 2003. Judicial review in new democracies: Constitutional courts in Asian cases. Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Goodin, R.E., Pettit, P. and Pogge, T.W. eds., 2009. A companion to contemporary political philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. Goodin, R.E., Pettit, P. and Pogge, T.W. eds., 2009. A companion to contemporary political philosophy. John Wiley & Sons.
Zurück zum Zitat Gordon, R.E. and Sylvester, J.H., 2004. Deconstructing development. Wis. Int’l LJ, 22, p. 1. Gordon, R.E. and Sylvester, J.H., 2004. Deconstructing development. Wis. Int’l LJ, 22, p. 1.
Zurück zum Zitat Gordley, J., 1994. Myths of the French Civil Code. The American Journal of Comparative Law, 42(3), pp. 459–505. Gordley, J., 1994. Myths of the French Civil Code. The American Journal of Comparative Law, 42(3), pp. 459–505.
Zurück zum Zitat Graziano, P. and Vink, M., 2008. Europeanization: new research agendas. Palgrave MacMillan Graziano, P. and Vink, M., 2008. Europeanization: new research agendas. Palgrave MacMillan
Zurück zum Zitat Gray, J., 1995. Liberalism. U of Minnesota Press Gray, J., 1995. Liberalism. U of Minnesota Press
Zurück zum Zitat Green, T.H. 1911. Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation. London, Longmans, Green and Co Green, T.H. 1911. Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation. London, Longmans, Green and Co
Zurück zum Zitat Guest, A.G., 1961. Oxford essays in jurisprudence. Oxford University Press Guest, A.G., 1961. Oxford essays in jurisprudence. Oxford University Press
Zurück zum Zitat Habermas, J., 1996. Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, Cambridge: Polity Press. Habermas, J., 1996. Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Haerpfer, C., Rotman, D., Turmov, S., eds. 2003, Living Conditions, Lifestyles and Health in Post-Soviet Societies. Minsk University Press Haerpfer, C., Rotman, D., Turmov, S., eds. 2003, Living Conditions, Lifestyles and Health in Post-Soviet Societies. Minsk University Press
Zurück zum Zitat Hargreaves, A.D.(1956), Modern Real Property, The Modern Law Review, 19:(1),pp. 14–25 Hargreaves, A.D.(1956), Modern Real Property, The Modern Law Review, 19:(1),pp. 14–25
Zurück zum Zitat Hayek, F.A., 1991. The road to serfdom. The University of Chicago Press. Hayek, F.A., 1991. The road to serfdom. The University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Halliday, S. and Schmidt, P., 2009. Conducting law and society research: reflections on methods and practices. Cambridge University Press. Halliday, S. and Schmidt, P., 2009. Conducting law and society research: reflections on methods and practices. Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Hann, C.M., 1993. From production to property: decollectivization and the family-land relationship in contemporary Hungary. Man, pp. 299–320. Hann, C.M., 1993. From production to property: decollectivization and the family-land relationship in contemporary Hungary. Man, pp. 299–320.
Zurück zum Zitat Hann, C. and Hart, K., eds. 2009. Market and society: The Great Transformation today. Cambridge University Press Hann, C. and Hart, K., eds. 2009. Market and society: The Great Transformation today. Cambridge University Press
Zurück zum Zitat Harris, J.W., 1996. Property and justice. OUP Oxford. Harris, J.W., 1996. Property and justice. OUP Oxford.
Zurück zum Zitat Hart, H.L.A., 1958. Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals. Harvard law review, pp. 593–629. Hart, H.L.A., 1958. Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals. Harvard law review, pp. 593–629.
Zurück zum Zitat Hart, H.L.A., 1997. The concept of law. Oxford University Press. Hart, H.L.A., 1997. The concept of law. Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Harvey, D., 2005. A brief history of neoliberalism. OUP Oxford. Harvey, D., 2005. A brief history of neoliberalism. OUP Oxford.
Zurück zum Zitat Havrylyshyn, O., 2006. Divergent paths in post-communist transformation. Palgrave Macmillan Havrylyshyn, O., 2006. Divergent paths in post-communist transformation. Palgrave Macmillan
Zurück zum Zitat Hegel, G.W.F., 1967. Philosophy of right, trans. TM Knox. Oxford: Oxford University Press Hegel, G.W.F., 1967. Philosophy of right, trans. TM Knox. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Zurück zum Zitat Heller, M., Serkin, C. and Dagan, H., 1999. Revaluing Restitution: From the Talmud to Postsocialism. Michigan Law Review 97, p. 1385 Heller, M., Serkin, C. and Dagan, H., 1999. Revaluing Restitution: From the Talmud to Postsocialism. Michigan Law Review 97, p. 1385
Zurück zum Zitat Hirschl, R., 2000. The political origins of judicial empowerment through constitutionalization: Lessons from four constitutional revolutions. Law & Social Inquiry, 25(1), pp. 91–149. Hirschl, R., 2000. The political origins of judicial empowerment through constitutionalization: Lessons from four constitutional revolutions. Law & Social Inquiry, 25(1), pp. 91–149.
Zurück zum Zitat Hirschl, R., 2004. Towards juristocracy: the origins and consequences of the new constitutionalism. Harvard University Press. Hirschl, R., 2004. Towards juristocracy: the origins and consequences of the new constitutionalism. Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Hohfeld, W.N. and Cook, W.W., 1966. Fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning. Yale University Press Hohfeld, W.N. and Cook, W.W., 1966. Fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning. Yale University Press
Zurück zum Zitat Holmes, S., 1993. A Forum on Restitution: essays on the efficiency and Justice of Returning Property to Its Former Owners. East European Constitutional Review 2(3), pp. 32–34. Holmes, S., 1993. A Forum on Restitution: essays on the efficiency and Justice of Returning Property to Its Former Owners. East European Constitutional Review 2(3), pp. 32–34.
Zurück zum Zitat Hont, I., 2005. Jealousy of trade: international competition and the nation-state in historical perspective. Harvard University Press. Hont, I., 2005. Jealousy of trade: international competition and the nation-state in historical perspective. Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Hume, D., 1972. A treatise of human nature. London: Fontana. Hume, D., 1972. A treatise of human nature. London: Fontana.
Zurück zum Zitat Kanbur, R., 2009. The co-evolution of the Washington Consensus and the economic development discourse. Macalester International, 24(1), 8 Kanbur, R., 2009. The co-evolution of the Washington Consensus and the economic development discourse. Macalester International, 24(1), 8
Zurück zum Zitat Kant, I. 1965. The Metaphysics of morals, trans. Ladd, J. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Kant, I. 1965. The Metaphysics of morals, trans. Ladd, J. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill
Zurück zum Zitat Kaplow, L., 2003. Transition Policy: A Conceptual Framework. The. J. Contemp. Legal Issues, 13, p. 161 Kaplow, L., 2003. Transition Policy: A Conceptual Framework. The. J. Contemp. Legal Issues, 13, p. 161
Zurück zum Zitat Karadjova, M., 2004. Property restitution in Eastern Europe: Domestic and international human rights law responses. Review of Central and East European Law, 29(3), pp. 325–363. Karadjova, M., 2004. Property restitution in Eastern Europe: Domestic and international human rights law responses. Review of Central and East European Law, 29(3), pp. 325–363.
Zurück zum Zitat Kessaris, A.P. ed., 2009. Law in the pursuit of development: principles into practice?. Routledge. Kessaris, A.P. ed., 2009. Law in the pursuit of development: principles into practice?. Routledge.
Zurück zum Zitat Kornhauser, L., 2001. The Economic Analysis of Law. Kornhauser, L., 2001. The Economic Analysis of Law.
Zurück zum Zitat Knieper, R., 2010. Pulls and pushes of legal reform in post-communist states. Hague Journal on the Rule of Law, 2(1), pp. 111–126. Knieper, R., 2010. Pulls and pushes of legal reform in post-communist states. Hague Journal on the Rule of Law, 2(1), pp. 111–126.
Zurück zum Zitat Krever, T., 2011. The legal turn in late development theory: the rule of law and the World Bank’s development model. Harvard International Law Journal, 52(1). Krever, T., 2011. The legal turn in late development theory: the rule of law and the World Bank’s development model. Harvard International Law Journal, 52(1).
Zurück zum Zitat Kuti, C., 2009. Post-communist Restitution and the Rule of Law. Central European University Press. Kuti, C., 2009. Post-communist Restitution and the Rule of Law. Central European University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Leslie, S., [1900]/1950. The English Utilitarians. London: The London School of Economics and Political Science Leslie, S., [1900]/1950. The English Utilitarians. London: The London School of Economics and Political Science
Zurück zum Zitat Locke, J. and Laslett, P., 1988. Locke: Two Treatises of Government Student Edition. Cambridge University Press. Locke, J. and Laslett, P., 1988. Locke: Two Treatises of Government Student Edition. Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Lovett, F., 2002. A positivist account of the rule of law. Law & Social Inquiry, 27(1), pp. 41–78. Lovett, F., 2002. A positivist account of the rule of law. Law & Social Inquiry, 27(1), pp. 41–78.
Zurück zum Zitat Macklem, P., 2005. Rybná 9, Praha 1: Restitution and Memory in International Human Rights Law. European Journal of International Law, 16(1), pp. 1–23. Macklem, P., 2005. Rybná 9, Praha 1: Restitution and Memory in International Human Rights Law. European Journal of International Law, 16(1), pp. 1–23.
Zurück zum Zitat Macpherson, C.B., 1962. The political theory of possessive individualism: Hobbes to Locke. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Macpherson, C.B., 1962. The political theory of possessive individualism: Hobbes to Locke. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Macpherson, C.B., 1977. The life and times of liberal democracy (Vol. 83). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Macpherson, C.B., 1977. The life and times of liberal democracy (Vol. 83). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Magoska, M., 1993. The Socio-Cultural Background of Legal Conflicts: A Study of Two Rural Communities in Poland. The Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law, 25(33), pp. 107–117 Magoska, M., 1993. The Socio-Cultural Background of Legal Conflicts: A Study of Two Rural Communities in Poland. The Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law, 25(33), pp. 107–117
Zurück zum Zitat Markovits, I., 2004. Exporting Law Reform-But Will It Travel. Cornell Int’l LJ, 37, p. 95. Markovits, I., 2004. Exporting Law Reform-But Will It Travel. Cornell Int’l LJ, 37, p. 95.
Zurück zum Zitat Marx, K. and Engels, F., 1970. Selected works: In one volume. Lawrence and Wishart. Marx, K. and Engels, F., 1970. Selected works: In one volume. Lawrence and Wishart.
Zurück zum Zitat Mattei, U., Reimann, M., Lutter, M., Stiefel, E.C. and Hoeflich, M.H., 1994. Why the Wind Changed: Intellectual Leadership in Western Law. American Journal of Comparative Law 42(1), pp. 195–218 Mattei, U., Reimann, M., Lutter, M., Stiefel, E.C. and Hoeflich, M.H., 1994. Why the Wind Changed: Intellectual Leadership in Western Law. American Journal of Comparative Law 42(1), pp. 195–218
Zurück zum Zitat Mau, V., 1999. Rossiiskie ekonomicheskie reformy glazami zapadnykh kritikov. Voprosy ekonomiki, 11, pp. 4–23. Mau, V., 1999. Rossiiskie ekonomicheskie reformy glazami zapadnykh kritikov. Voprosy ekonomiki, 11, pp. 4–23.
Zurück zum Zitat Merrill, T.W. and Smith, H.E., 2006. Morality of Property, The. Wm. & Mary L. Rev., 48, p. 1849. Merrill, T.W. and Smith, H.E., 2006. Morality of Property, The. Wm. & Mary L. Rev., 48, p. 1849.
Zurück zum Zitat Merryman, J.H., 1973. Ownership and Estate (Variations on a Theme by Lawson). Tul. L. Rev., 48, p. 916. Merryman, J.H., 1973. Ownership and Estate (Variations on a Theme by Lawson). Tul. L. Rev., 48, p. 916.
Zurück zum Zitat Merryman, J.H., 1977. Comparative Law and Social Change: On the Origins, Style, Decline & Revival of the Law and Development Movement. The American Journal of Comparative Law, pp. 457–491. Merryman, J.H., 1977. Comparative Law and Social Change: On the Origins, Style, Decline & Revival of the Law and Development Movement. The American Journal of Comparative Law, pp. 457–491.
Zurück zum Zitat Mill, J.S., 1973. Principles of Political Economy With Some of Their Applications to Social Philosophy. Clifton; Augustus M. Kelley. Mill, J.S., 1973. Principles of Political Economy With Some of Their Applications to Social Philosophy. Clifton; Augustus M. Kelley.
Zurück zum Zitat Munck, R. and O’Hearn, D., 1999. Critical development theory: Contributions to a new paradigm. Zed Books Munck, R. and O’Hearn, D., 1999. Critical development theory: Contributions to a new paradigm. Zed Books
Zurück zum Zitat Munzer, S.R., 1990. A theory of property. Cambridge University Press. Munzer, S.R., 1990. A theory of property. Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Nozick, R., 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York basic book. Nozick, R., 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York basic book.
Zurück zum Zitat Offe, C. and Bönker, F., 1993. A Forum on Restitution. E. European Const. Rev., 2(3), pp. 30–32. Offe, C. and Bönker, F., 1993. A Forum on Restitution. E. European Const. Rev., 2(3), pp. 30–32.
Zurück zum Zitat Patten, A., 1995. Hegel’s Justification of Private Property. History of Political Thought 16 (04), pp. 576–600 Patten, A., 1995. Hegel’s Justification of Private Property. History of Political Thought 16 (04), pp. 576–600
Zurück zum Zitat Patterson, D., 1999. Explicating the Internal Point of View. Southern Methodist University Law Review, 52, p 67 Patterson, D., 1999. Explicating the Internal Point of View. Southern Methodist University Law Review, 52, p 67
Zurück zum Zitat Paul, J., 1981. Reading Nozick: Essays on Anarchy. State, and Utopia. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Paul, J., 1981. Reading Nozick: Essays on Anarchy. State, and Utopia. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Zurück zum Zitat Peleikis, A., 2006. Whose heritage? Legal pluralism and the politics of the past. A case study from the Curonian Spit (Lithuania). The Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law, 38(53–54), pp. 209–237. Peleikis, A., 2006. Whose heritage? Legal pluralism and the politics of the past. A case study from the Curonian Spit (Lithuania). The Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law, 38(53–54), pp. 209–237.
Zurück zum Zitat Penner, J.E., 1995. Bundle of Rights Picture of Property, The. Ucla L. Rev., 43, p. 711. Penner, J.E., 1995. Bundle of Rights Picture of Property, The. Ucla L. Rev., 43, p. 711.
Zurück zum Zitat Penner, J.E., 1997. The idea of property in law. Oxford University Press. Penner, J.E., 1997. The idea of property in law. Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Pennock, J.R. and Chapman, J.W., 1980. Property: Nomos XXII. New York University Press. Pennock, J.R. and Chapman, J.W., 1980. Property: Nomos XXII. New York University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Persky, J., 2010. On the Thinness of the Utilitarian Defense of Private Property. Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 32(01), pp. 63–83. Persky, J., 2010. On the Thinness of the Utilitarian Defense of Private Property. Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 32(01), pp. 63–83.
Zurück zum Zitat Philbrick, F.S., 1938. Changing conceptions of property in law. University of Pennsylvania Law Review and American Law Register, 86(7), pp. 691–732. Philbrick, F.S., 1938. Changing conceptions of property in law. University of Pennsylvania Law Review and American Law Register, 86(7), pp. 691–732.
Zurück zum Zitat Pickel, A., 2001. Between Social Science and Social Technology Toward a Philosophical Foundation for Post-Communist Transformation Studies. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 31(4), pp. 459–487. Pickel, A., 2001. Between Social Science and Social Technology Toward a Philosophical Foundation for Post-Communist Transformation Studies. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 31(4), pp. 459–487.
Zurück zum Zitat Pickel, A., 2002. Transformation theory: scientific or political?. Communist and Post-Communist Studies, 35(1), pp. 105–114. Pickel, A., 2002. Transformation theory: scientific or political?. Communist and Post-Communist Studies, 35(1), pp. 105–114.
Zurück zum Zitat Pieterse. J. N., 2010. Development Theory. Sage Pieterse. J. N., 2010. Development Theory. Sage
Zurück zum Zitat Pogány, I., 2010. International human rights law, reparatory justice and the re-ordering of memory in Central and Eastern Europe. Human Rights Law Review, 10(3), pp. 397–428. Pogány, I., 2010. International human rights law, reparatory justice and the re-ordering of memory in Central and Eastern Europe. Human Rights Law Review, 10(3), pp. 397–428.
Zurück zum Zitat Polanyi, K., 2001/1944. The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins of Our Times. Polanyi, K., 2001/1944. The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins of Our Times.
Zurück zum Zitat Posner, R.A., 1973. Economic analysis of law. Little Brown and Company Posner, R.A., 1973. Economic analysis of law. Little Brown and Company
Zurück zum Zitat Preston, P.W., 1996. Development theory: An introduction. Blackwell Publishers. Preston, P.W., 1996. Development theory: An introduction. Blackwell Publishers.
Zurück zum Zitat Procházka, R., 2002. Mission Accomplished. On Founding Constitutional Adjudication in Central Europe. Budapest, New York. Procházka, R., 2002. Mission Accomplished. On Founding Constitutional Adjudication in Central Europe. Budapest, New York.
Zurück zum Zitat Radin, M.J., 1982. Property and Personhood, 34 Stan. L. Rev, 957 Radin, M.J., 1982. Property and Personhood, 34 Stan. L. Rev, 957
Zurück zum Zitat Radin, M.J., 1989. Reconsidering the rule of law. BUL Rev., 69, p. 781. Radin, M.J., 1989. Reconsidering the rule of law. BUL Rev., 69, p. 781.
Zurück zum Zitat Radin, M.J., 1993. Reinterpreting property. University of Chicago Press. Radin, M.J., 1993. Reinterpreting property. University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Rainbolt, G.W., 2006. The concept of rights (Vol. 73). Springer Science & Business Media. Rainbolt, G.W., 2006. The concept of rights (Vol. 73). Springer Science & Business Media.
Zurück zum Zitat Ramseyer, J.M., 1994. The puzzling (in) dependence of courts: A comparative approach. The Journal of Legal Studies, 23(2), pp. 721–747. Ramseyer, J.M., 1994. The puzzling (in) dependence of courts: A comparative approach. The Journal of Legal Studies, 23(2), pp. 721–747.
Zurück zum Zitat Rawls, J., 1958. Justice as fairness. Philosophical Review, pp. 164–194 Rawls, J., 1958. Justice as fairness. Philosophical Review, pp. 164–194
Zurück zum Zitat Rawls, J., 1999. A theory of justice. Harvard university press. Rawls, J., 1999. A theory of justice. Harvard university press.
Zurück zum Zitat Richard, J., 2005. The concept of fair value in French and German accounting regulations from 1673 to 1914 and its consequences for the interpretation of the stages of development of capitalist accounting. Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 16(6), pp. 825–850. Richard, J., 2005. The concept of fair value in French and German accounting regulations from 1673 to 1914 and its consequences for the interpretation of the stages of development of capitalist accounting. Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 16(6), pp. 825–850.
Zurück zum Zitat Richter, R., 2005. The new institutional economics: its start, its meaning, its prospects. European Business Organization Law Review, 6(02), pp. 161–200. Richter, R., 2005. The new institutional economics: its start, its meaning, its prospects. European Business Organization Law Review, 6(02), pp. 161–200.
Zurück zum Zitat Robinson, J., 1962. Economic philosophy. Penguin Books. Robinson, J., 1962. Economic philosophy. Penguin Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Rodrik, D., 2006. Goodbye Washington consensus, hello Washington confusion? A review of the World Bank’s economic growth in the 1990s: learning from a decade of reform. Journal of Economic literature, 44(4), pp. 973–987. Rodrik, D., 2006. Goodbye Washington consensus, hello Washington confusion? A review of the World Bank’s economic growth in the 1990s: learning from a decade of reform. Journal of Economic literature, 44(4), pp. 973–987.
Zurück zum Zitat Rosenberg, G.N., 1993. The hollow hope: Can courts bring about social change?. University of Chicago Press. Rosenberg, G.N., 1993. The hollow hope: Can courts bring about social change?. University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Ross, A., 1957. Tû-Tû. Harvard Law Review, 70, pp. 812–812. Ross, A., 1957. Tû-Tû. Harvard Law Review, 70, pp. 812–812.
Zurück zum Zitat Ryan, A., 1984. Property and political theory. Oxford: Blackwell. Ryan, A., 1984. Property and political theory. Oxford: Blackwell.
Zurück zum Zitat Sanders, J. and Hamilton, V.L. eds., 2001. Handbook of justice research in law. New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers Sanders, J. and Hamilton, V.L. eds., 2001. Handbook of justice research in law. New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers
Zurück zum Zitat Schauer, F., 2003. Legal Development and the Problem of Systemic Transition. The. J. Contemp. Legal Issues, 13, p. 261 Schauer, F., 2003. Legal Development and the Problem of Systemic Transition. The. J. Contemp. Legal Issues, 13, p. 261
Zurück zum Zitat Scheppele, K.L., 1999. New Hungarian Constitutional Court, The. E. Eur. Const. Rev., 8, p. 81. Scheppele, K.L., 1999. New Hungarian Constitutional Court, The. E. Eur. Const. Rev., 8, p. 81.
Zurück zum Zitat Scheppele, K.L., 2001. Democracy by judiciary (or why courts can sometimes be more democratic than parliaments). Rethinking the rule of law after communism, pp. 22–60. Scheppele, K.L., 2001. Democracy by judiciary (or why courts can sometimes be more democratic than parliaments). Rethinking the rule of law after communism, pp. 22–60.
Zurück zum Zitat Scherer, K.R. ed., 1992. Justice: interdisciplinary perspectives. Cambridge University Press. Scherer, K.R. ed., 1992. Justice: interdisciplinary perspectives. Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Schnably, S.J., 1993. Property and Pragmatism: A Critique of Radin’s Theory of Property and Personhood. Stanford Law Review, pp. 347–407. Schnably, S.J., 1993. Property and Pragmatism: A Critique of Radin’s Theory of Property and Personhood. Stanford Law Review, pp. 347–407.
Zurück zum Zitat Schwartz, H., 2000. The struggle for constitutional justice in post-communist Europe. University of Chicago Press. Schwartz, H., 2000. The struggle for constitutional justice in post-communist Europe. University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Singer, J.W., 1991. Sovereignty and Property. Nw. UL Rev., 86, p. 1. Singer, J.W., 1991. Sovereignty and Property. Nw. UL Rev., 86, p. 1.
Zurück zum Zitat Skitka, L.J., 2009. Exploring the “lost and found” of justice theory and research. Social Justice Research, 22(1), pp. 98–116 Skitka, L.J., 2009. Exploring the “lost and found” of justice theory and research. Social Justice Research, 22(1), pp. 98–116
Zurück zum Zitat Slaughter, A.M., 2003. Global Community of Courts, A. Harv. Int’l LJ, 44, p. 191. Slaughter, A.M., 2003. Global Community of Courts, A. Harv. Int’l LJ, 44, p. 191.
Zurück zum Zitat Smithey, S.I. and Ishiyama, J., 2002. Judicial activism in post-communist politics. Law and Society Review, pp. 719–742. Smithey, S.I. and Ishiyama, J., 2002. Judicial activism in post-communist politics. Law and Society Review, pp. 719–742.
Zurück zum Zitat Solomon, R.C. and Martin, C. 2004. Morality and the good life. New York: McGraw-Hill, 4th ed. Solomon, R.C. and Martin, C. 2004. Morality and the good life. New York: McGraw-Hill, 4th ed.
Zurück zum Zitat Solum, L.B., 2004. Procedural justice. 78 S. Cal. L. Rev, 181, pp. 192–224 Solum, L.B., 2004. Procedural justice. 78 S. Cal. L. Rev, 181, pp. 192–224
Zurück zum Zitat Stiglitz, J., 2002. Globalization and Its Discontents. New York: Norton. Stiglitz, J., 2002. Globalization and Its Discontents. New York: Norton.
Zurück zum Zitat Suda, Z. and Musil, J. eds., 2000. The meaning of liberalism: East and West. Central European University Press Suda, Z. and Musil, J. eds., 2000. The meaning of liberalism: East and West. Central European University Press
Zurück zum Zitat Sztompka, P., 2000a. Cultural trauma the other face of social change. European journal of social theory, 3(4), pp. 449–466. Sztompka, P., 2000a. Cultural trauma the other face of social change. European journal of social theory, 3(4), pp. 449–466.
Zurück zum Zitat Sztompka, P., 2000b. The Ambivalence of Social Change Triumph or Trauma?. Polish Sociological Review, pp. 275–290. Sztompka, P., 2000b. The Ambivalence of Social Change Triumph or Trauma?. Polish Sociological Review, pp. 275–290.
Zurück zum Zitat Sweet, A.S., 2000. Governing with Judges: Constitutional Politics in Europe: Constitutional Politics in Europe. OUP Oxford. Sweet, A.S., 2000. Governing with Judges: Constitutional Politics in Europe: Constitutional Politics in Europe. OUP Oxford.
Zurück zum Zitat Tebbit, M., 2005. Philosophy of law: An introduction. Routledge. Tebbit, M., 2005. Philosophy of law: An introduction. Routledge.
Zurück zum Zitat Thelen, T., 2005. Violence and social (dis) continuity: comparing collectivization in two East European villages. Social History, 30(1), pp. 25–44. Thelen, T., 2005. Violence and social (dis) continuity: comparing collectivization in two East European villages. Social History, 30(1), pp. 25–44.
Zurück zum Zitat Thelen, T., 2006. Law and mutual assistance in families: A comparison of socialist legacies in Hungary and Eastern Germany. The Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law, 38(53–54), pp. 177–207. Thelen, T., 2006. Law and mutual assistance in families: A comparison of socialist legacies in Hungary and Eastern Germany. The Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law, 38(53–54), pp. 177–207.
Zurück zum Zitat Thomas, C., 2011. Law and neoclassical economic development in theory and practice: toward an institutionalist critique of institutionalism. Cornell Law Review, 96, p. 967. Thomas, C., 2011. Law and neoclassical economic development in theory and practice: toward an institutionalist critique of institutionalism. Cornell Law Review, 96, p. 967.
Zurück zum Zitat Trebilcock, M. and Veel, P.E., 2008. Property rights and development: The contingent case for formalization. U. Pa. J. Int’l L., 30, p. 397. Trebilcock, M. and Veel, P.E., 2008. Property rights and development: The contingent case for formalization. U. Pa. J. Int’l L., 30, p. 397.
Zurück zum Zitat Trubek, D.M. and Galanter, M., 1974. Scholars in self-estrangement: some reflections on the crisis in law and development studies in the United States. Wis. L. Rev., p. 1062. Trubek, D.M. and Galanter, M., 1974. Scholars in self-estrangement: some reflections on the crisis in law and development studies in the United States. Wis. L. Rev., p. 1062.
Zurück zum Zitat Trubek, D.M. and Santos, A. eds., 2006. The new law and economic development: a critical appraisal. Cambridge University Press. Trubek, D.M. and Santos, A. eds., 2006. The new law and economic development: a critical appraisal. Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Turner, R.S., 2008. Neo-liberal ideology: History, concepts and policies. Edinburgh University Press. Turner, R.S., 2008. Neo-liberal ideology: History, concepts and policies. Edinburgh University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Underkuffler, L.S., 2003. The idea of property: its meaning and power. Oxford University Press. Underkuffler, L.S., 2003. The idea of property: its meaning and power. Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Van Alstine, M.P., 2002. The Costs of Legal Change, 49 UCLA L. Rev, 789, p. 823. Van Alstine, M.P., 2002. The Costs of Legal Change, 49 UCLA L. Rev, 789, p. 823.
Zurück zum Zitat Van Brabant, J.M., 1998. The political economy of transition. Coming to Grips with History and Methodology. Routledge, London Van Brabant, J.M., 1998. The political economy of transition. Coming to Grips with History and Methodology. Routledge, London
Zurück zum Zitat Van den Bos, K., Vermunt, R. and Wilke, H.A., 1997. Procedural and distributive justice: what is fair depends more on what comes first than on what comes next. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 72(1), p. 95 Van den Bos, K., Vermunt, R. and Wilke, H.A., 1997. Procedural and distributive justice: what is fair depends more on what comes first than on what comes next. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 72(1), p. 95
Zurück zum Zitat Van den Bos, K., Wilke, H.A., Lind, E.A. and Vermunt, R., 1998. Evaluating outcomes by means of the fair process effect: Evidence for different processes in fairness and satisfaction judgments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 74(6), p. 1493. Van den Bos, K., Wilke, H.A., Lind, E.A. and Vermunt, R., 1998. Evaluating outcomes by means of the fair process effect: Evidence for different processes in fairness and satisfaction judgments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 74(6), p. 1493.
Zurück zum Zitat Vandevelde, K.J., 1980. New Property of the Nineteenth Century: The Development of the Modern Concept of Property, The. Buff. L. Rev., 29, p. 325. Vandevelde, K.J., 1980. New Property of the Nineteenth Century: The Development of the Modern Concept of Property, The. Buff. L. Rev., 29, p. 325.
Zurück zum Zitat Verdery, K., 2001. Inequality as temporal process Property and time in Transylvania’s land restitution. Anthropological theory, 1(3), pp. 373–392. Verdery, K., 2001. Inequality as temporal process Property and time in Transylvania’s land restitution. Anthropological theory, 1(3), pp. 373–392.
Zurück zum Zitat Verdery, K., 2002. Seeing Like a Mayor Or, How Local Officials Obstructed Romanian Land Restitution. Ethnography, 3(1), pp. 5–33. Verdery, K., 2002. Seeing Like a Mayor Or, How Local Officials Obstructed Romanian Land Restitution. Ethnography, 3(1), pp. 5–33.
Zurück zum Zitat Verdery, K., 2003. The vanishing hectare: property and value in postsocialist Transylvania. Cornell University Press. Verdery, K., 2003. The vanishing hectare: property and value in postsocialist Transylvania. Cornell University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Verdery, K., Caroline Humphrey, eds. 2004 Property in Question: Value Transformation in the Global Economy. Berg: London. Verdery, K., Caroline Humphrey, eds. 2004 Property in Question: Value Transformation in the Global Economy. Berg: London.
Zurück zum Zitat Vermeule, A., 2007. Connecting Positive and Normative Legal Theory. U. Pa. J. Const. L., 10, p. 387. Vermeule, A., 2007. Connecting Positive and Normative Legal Theory. U. Pa. J. Const. L., 10, p. 387.
Zurück zum Zitat Waldron, J., 1988. The right to private property. Clarendon Press. Waldron, J., 1988. The right to private property. Clarendon Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Watson, A., 1974. Legal transplants: An approach to comparative law. University of Georgia Press. Watson, A., 1974. Legal transplants: An approach to comparative law. University of Georgia Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Watson, A., 2001. The Evolution of Western Private Law (Expanded edition). The John Hopkins University Press Watson, A., 2001. The Evolution of Western Private Law (Expanded edition). The John Hopkins University Press
Zurück zum Zitat Weber, M., 1978. Economy and society: An outline of interpretive sociology. Univ of California Press. Weber, M., 1978. Economy and society: An outline of interpretive sociology. Univ of California Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Widdig, B., 2001. Culture and inflation in Weimar Germany. Univ of California Press. Widdig, B., 2001. Culture and inflation in Weimar Germany. Univ of California Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Williams Jr, R.A., 1983. Medieval and Renaissance Origins of the Status of the American Indian in Western Legal Thought, The. S. Cal. L. Rev., 57, p. 1. Williams Jr, R.A., 1983. Medieval and Renaissance Origins of the Status of the American Indian in Western Legal Thought, The. S. Cal. L. Rev., 57, p. 1.
Zurück zum Zitat Williamson, J., 1990. What Washington means by policy reform. Latin American adjustment: How much has happened, 1 Williamson, J., 1990. What Washington means by policy reform. Latin American adjustment: How much has happened, 1
Zurück zum Zitat Williamson, J., 2002. Speeches, Testimony, Papers Did the Washington Consensus Fail?. Institute for International Economics. Williamson, J., 2002. Speeches, Testimony, Papers Did the Washington Consensus Fail?. Institute for International Economics.
Zurück zum Zitat Wonnell, C.T., 2003. Noncompensation Thesis and Its Critics: A Review of This Symposium’s Challenges to the Argument for Not Compensating Victims of Legal Transitions, The. J. Contemp. Legal Issues, 13, p. 293. Wonnell, C.T., 2003. Noncompensation Thesis and Its Critics: A Review of This Symposium’s Challenges to the Argument for Not Compensating Victims of Legal Transitions, The. J. Contemp. Legal Issues, 13, p. 293.
Metadaten
Titel
Justice, Property and Law in Post-communist Transformations of Property
verfasst von
Liviu Damşa
Copyright-Jahr
2016
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-48530-0_3

Premium Partner