Skip to main content

1981 | Buch

Universal Algebra

verfasst von: P. M. Cohn, F.R.S.

Verlag: Springer Netherlands

Buchreihe : Mathematics and Its Applications

insite
SUCHEN

Über dieses Buch

The present book was conceived as an introduction for the user of universal algebra, rather than a handbook for the specialist, but when the first edition appeared in 1965, there were practically no other books entir~ly devoted to the subject, whether introductory or specialized. Today the specialist in the field is well provided for, but there is still a demand for an introduction to the subject to suit the user, and this seemed to justify a reissue of the book. Naturally some changes have had to be made; in particular, I have corrected all errors that have been brought to my notice. Besides errors, some obscurities in the text have been removed and the references brought up to date. I should like to express my thanks to a number of correspondents for their help, in particular C. G. d'Ambly, W. Felscher, P. Goralcik, P. J. Higgins, H.-J. Hoehnke, J. R. Isbell, A. H. Kruse, E. J. Peake, D. Suter, J. S. Wilson. But lowe a special debt to G. M. Bergman, who has provided me with extensive comments. particularly on Chapter VII and the supplementary chapters. I have also con­ sulted reviews of the first edition, as well as the Italian and Russian translations.

Inhaltsverzeichnis

Frontmatter
Chapter I. Sets and Mappings
Abstract
The typical feature of a mathematical theory is that it deals with collections or sets of objects, where certain relations exist between the objects of these sets, or between different sets, while the nature of the objects is entirely immaterial. A simplification can be achieved by considering only objects which are themselves sets. At first sight this appears to lead to a vicious circle, but the difficulty may be resolved by beginning with the empty set. On the other hand it is necessary to restrict the sets which may appear as members of other sets, if one wants to avoid the contradictions arising from the consideration of ‘the set of all those sets which are not members of themselves’ (Russell’s paradox). One therefore introduces a different term, such as ‘class’, for general collections of objects, and distinguishes those classes which are themselves members of other classes by calling them sets. Without entering fully into the question of axiomatics here (for which the reader may be referred to more detailed accounts such as Bourbaki [54], Gödel [40], Kelley [55], and Wang & McNaughton [53]), we shall give a list of axioms, which in the main express the conditions under which a class is to be regarded as a set.
P. M. Cohn
Chapter II. Algebraic Structures
Abstract
An algebraic structure on a set A is essentially a collection of finitary operations on A; the set A with this structure is also called an algebra. Most of the notions introduced for sets, such as subset, mapping, equivalence, have analogues for algebras, namely subalgebra, homomorphism, congruence. The mapping theorems of I.3 then correspond to the isomorphism theorems, which are probably best known in the case of groups. The analogy is less complete for the Jordan-Hölder and Krull-Schmidt theorems, which are therefore first considered in their abstract setting in lattice theory, and then for algebras.
P. M. Cohn
Chapter III. Free Algebras
Abstract
Many important classes of algebras, among them groups, rings, and lattices, consist of all the homomorphic images of certain ‘free’ algebras in the class, which are essentially determined by the cardinal of a free generating set. These are the varieties of algebras, which form the subject of Chapter IV, but free algebras are also of importance in more general situations, and we therefore devote a chapter to the study of properties of free algebras which are independent of the notion of a variety. A free algebra is itself a special case of the notion of a universal functor in category theory, and so we shall first describe universal functors in general categories (cf. Samuel [48], MacLane [63]).
P. M. Cohn
Chapter IV. Varieties
Abstract
Many important classes of algebras occurring in practice, such as groups, rings, lattices, etc., may be completely described by identical relations. Such equational classes or varieties have many useful properties; in particular, they always possess free algebras, and the members of the variety may be characterized as homomorphic images of the free algebras. Any variety V of Ω-algebras gives rise to a subcategory of (Ω), namely the full subcategory whose objects are all the members of V. The resulting category is always local, residual, and hereditary, and admits homomorphic images and direct products. Conversely, the algebras of any residual category admitting homomorphic images form a variety. Thus most of the results of Chapter III apply to varieties; in addition, there are a number of features special to varieties, which also are discussed briefly.
P. M. Cohn
Chapter V. Relational Structures and Models
Abstract
The concept of an algebra developed in Chapters II–IV includes most of the algebraic structures encountered in practice, but there are some important exceptions. Thus, although groups, rings, and vector spaces are included, neither ordered groups nor fields satisfy the definition. To see what modifications are necessary, we note that an ordered group is a structure with certain operations, and besides, a relation. A field is a structure with ‘operations’ which are not everywhere defined. As we saw in II.2, it would be formally possible to define both ordered groups and fields as algebras, but only at the cost of some artificiality. For a natural development one needs to have relations as well as operations, or at least relations alone, since it turns out that operations may be obtained as a special case. Furthermore, in writing down the definition of particular structures it may be necessary to use inequalities as well as equations. This is made possible by introducing logical connectives, and it leads to the consideration of classes of algebras other than varieties.
P. M. Cohn
Chapter VI. Axiomatic Model Classes
Abstract
As we saw in Chapter V, some properties of Ω-structures can be expressed by means of elementary sentences, while others cannot. We now take the analysis one step further: we consider various properties of axiomatic model classes and enquire to what extent these may be characterized by the form of the defining sentences. The chapter concludes with an elegant characterization, due to Keisler [611, of axiomatic model classes in terms of ultraproducts.
P. M. Cohn
Chapter VII. Applications
Abstract
In the course of the first six chapters a number of applications to particular situations were obtained by specializing the general theory. However, it is much more common for specific problems to fall into two parts, of which one, involving universal algebra, is relatively simple, while the more substantial piece of work still remains to be done. A typical instance is the universal mapping problem, in which the proof that the universal functor is injective is often the most difficult part, and one where universal algebra has less to contribute. Nevertheless, the use of universal algebra often helps to simplify the proof by setting out the precise nature of what has to be proved. These points are illustrated by the applications given in this chapter.
P. M. Cohn
Chapter VIII. Category Theory and Universal Algebra
Abstract
One of the more notable features of the axioms for an abstract category is the complete duality; this plays an important role in simplifying proofs. However, most of the concrete categories such as Sets, Groups, Rings, and Modules are not self-dual. This means that not all the important features of these categories can be described by a self-dual set of axioms, and it is an interesting task to push the description in terms of self-dual axioms as far as possible. There is also the practical advantage that any result obtained as a consequence of these axioms may immediately be dualized.
P. M. Cohn
Chapter IX. Model Theory and Universal Algebra
Abstract
The relation between model theory and universal algebra has been summed up concisely by Chang and Keisler [73] in the equation universal algebra + logic = model theory. In this chapter we give some illustrations of the way in which the influence of model theory on our subject has grown in recent years; we shall be concerned particularly with various notions of algebraic closure. There are of course various other important aspects of the subject, such as stability theory (cf. Shelah [71′]), but this would require more tools from logic than we have at our disposal.
P. M. Cohn
Chapter X. Miscellaneous Further Results
Abstract
In this chapter we present a number of brief remarks or new results which have some relevance to the main text.
P. M. Cohn
Chapter XI. Algebra and Language Theory
Abstract
In the early days of high-speed computers there was a hope that it would be possible to program a computer to translate from one language to another, and this led to an intensive study of language structure. The result has been disappointing in that we are still far from making translations by computer, but that is no cause for despair. In the first place it shows that we have underestimated the richness and intricacy of our natural languages, even when used for quite prosaic ends. Secondly, this study of language has led to mathematical models of languages which admittedly are too simple to reflect all the complexities of a natural language like English, but - quite apart from their intrinsic interest — these models are found to give a good approximation to certain programming languages. And thirdly, there has been a vigorous interaction with some parts of noncommutative algebra, with benefit to ‘mathematical linguist’ and algebraist alike.
P. M. Cohn
Backmatter
Metadaten
Titel
Universal Algebra
verfasst von
P. M. Cohn, F.R.S.
Copyright-Jahr
1981
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Electronic ISBN
978-94-009-8399-1
Print ISBN
978-90-277-1254-7
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-8399-1