Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Public Choice 1-2/2020

17.10.2019

Why do military dictatorships become presidential democracies? Mapping the democratic interests of autocratic regimes

verfasst von: Christian Bjørnskov

Erschienen in: Public Choice | Ausgabe 1-2/2020

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Recent data show that virtually all military dictatorships that democratize become presidential democracies. I hypothesize that the reason is that military interests are able to coordinate on status-preserving institutional change prior to democratization and prefer political institutions with strong veto players. Civilian interests are more likely to suffer from coordination failure by being more diverse and less cohesive, implying that most military democratizations are planned partially while most democratization events from civilian autocracy are unforeseen or poorly planned. Exploring the characteristics of 111 democratization episodes between 1950 and 2017 illustrates features broadly consistent with further theoretical predictions.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Anhänge
Nur mit Berechtigung zugänglich
Fußnoten
1
An alternative way of categorizing autocracies, popularized by Geddes (1999), consists in distinguishing between personalist, military and single-party regimes. Historically, that distinction has been important in the transition from personalist to hereditary autocracy, and the consequent reduction in conflicts related to succession (Kurrild-Klitgaard 2000; Tullock 2001; Kokkonen and Sundell in press). In the following, most military dictatorships, as categorized by Cheibub et al. (2010) and Bjørnskov and Rode (in press) also would be categorized as military by Geddes (1999), and all communist regimes in the following likewise are single-party. The main difference is that civilian autocracies, in the present category, need not be personalist.
 
2
It is worth noting that the same transition appears in all regions of the world—it is thus not a Latin American phenomenon—and regardless of the country’s specific history. Bjørnskov and Rode (in press), for example, show that colonial ancestry (British, French or other colonial history) does not affect coup risks when countries become independent, although it does affect their likelihood of democratizing.
 
3
The single case is Peru in the 1990s, when the democratically elected President Alberto Fujimori disregarded the democratic institutions and eventually had to flee the country. After a de facto interim autocratic regime, the constitutional institutions proved robust enough to re-establish democracy without much ado.
 
4
In many cases, more than two parties exist or form around democratization. However, the assumption of two parties likely reflects reality when the party system either develops two dominant parties or two approximately coherent blocs of parties (the left and right), as appears to be the case (as documented in the online appendix). When the party system becomes characterized by lax party discipline, as in the United States, it might even form two identifiable groups of politicians across party lines with similar interests on issues of military interest. The assumption of two parties is likely to be problematic only in the case of multiple parties competing in a multi-dimensional issue space, or when the party system develops small pivot parties. Conversely, while an incumbent cannot know prior to democratization the extent to which the parliamentary system develops party discipline, assuming that it does appears to be a rationally conservative choice for both the incumbent government as well as for the present theoretical framework.
 
5
A further logical extension of this result is that the incumbent government may have a particular interest in choosing a policy mix that, for example, yields sufficient subsidies to a subset of industries—perhaps best thought of as what was once called the ‘commanding heights’ industries—while achieving the opposite for other industries. That policy mix can, for example, be one in which a subset of industries is protected by high import tariffs while other subsets that potentially could form an alternative majority are exposed to free trade. The mix would reduce their profit margins to the extent that they would have little interest in seeking subsidies—and, thus, represent a threat to the incumbent—because the coordination cost would be prohibitively high relative to the potential gain.
 
6
As noted above, in parliamentary systems with multiple parties in which coalitions are necessary to assemble a governing majority, partisan veto players can be effective. However, nothing assures that any constitutional provisions result in either a multiple-party system, a two-party system or a system with dominant parties. As such, presidentialism is the one certain constitutional choice with which to create institutional veto players.
 
7
It is worth noting that, theoretically, military competence [as in Eqs. (18) and (19)] may either strengthen or weaken the incentive to democratize, because the net effect depends on the coup risk when not democratizing relative to the risk of losing a democratic election.
 
8
An additional result here is that military competence makes it more likely that a presidential system is preferable whenever the condition \(\left( {1 - \mu } \right)\xi m_{0} < \Delta \left( {1 - \theta } \right)\left( {1 - \varphi } \right)m_{p}\) holds, essentially implying the intuitive condition that when the best military spending under autocracy is less than the best possible expected military spending under democracy, a more competent military regime will chose to democratize to a presidential system that minimizes its potential loss.
 
9
Conversely, many democratizations from civilian autocracy resulted in new or clearly amended constitutions drafted and introduced after the regime change: 30% introduced a new constitution that was negotiated after democratization. Among military dictatorships, the same pattern has been rare, with only five cases (8%)—Brazil in 1988, the Central African Republic in 1994, Greece in 1975, Poland in 1992 and Venezuela in 1961—in which drafting a new constitution was left to the new regime. The Brazilian case also differs owing to the special nature of the constitutional drafting process in which broad interests within the population were taken into formal account. Indeed, the particular way in which new constitutions were drafted also differs significantly across initially civilian and military regimes: 85% of the new constitutions of democratizing civilian autocracies were drafted by either the legislature or the executive branch, or with heavy influence from either. In military dictatorships that democratized, the drafting process of the more frequent new constitutions tended to be delegated to either a constitutional assembly appointed by the dictatorship or an elected special constitutional legislature assembly. Here, only 44% of the drafting processes included direct influence from either the executive or the legislature.
 
10
While it is extremely rare that the president can veto legislation formally, all but one of the military constitutions allow the president to initiate legislation. However, most constitutions also allow the parliament to do so, thereby effectively creating shared competencies. That feature is significantly rarer in democracies initiated by civilian autocracies. Conversely, the president in the former regime type almost never is given the right to dissolve parliament, while that feature is approximately twice as likely to be present in the constitution in the democracies initiated by civilian autocracies.
 
11
In addition, it may be worth emphasizing that presidential democracies do not appear more stable than parliamentary types. Although 66% of presidential democracies and only 58% of parliamentary democracies survived the first 10 years after democratization, the difference is far from being significant.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Acemoglu, D., & Johnson, S. (2006). Economic backwardness in political perspective. American Political Science Review, 100(1), 115–131.CrossRef Acemoglu, D., & Johnson, S. (2006). Economic backwardness in political perspective. American Political Science Review, 100(1), 115–131.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Acemoglu, D., Naidu, S., Restrepo, P., & Robinson, J. A. (2019). Democracy does cause growth. Journal of Political Economy, 127(1), 47–100.CrossRef Acemoglu, D., Naidu, S., Restrepo, P., & Robinson, J. A. (2019). Democracy does cause growth. Journal of Political Economy, 127(1), 47–100.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bell, C. (2016). Coup d’état and democracy. Comparative Political Studies, 49(9), 1167–1200.CrossRef Bell, C. (2016). Coup d’état and democracy. Comparative Political Studies, 49(9), 1167–1200.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bidner, C., & Francois, P. (2013). The emergence of political accountability. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 128(3), 1397–1448.CrossRef Bidner, C., & Francois, P. (2013). The emergence of political accountability. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 128(3), 1397–1448.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bjørnskov, C., & Pfaff, K. (2017). The effect of coups d’état on physical integrity rights. Working paper, Aarhus University. Bjørnskov, C., & Pfaff, K. (2017). The effect of coups d’état on physical integrity rights. Working paper, Aarhus University.
Zurück zum Zitat Bjørnskov, C., & Rode, M. (in press). Regimes and regime transitions: A new dataset on democracy, coups, and political institutions. Forthcoming in Review of International Organizations. Bjørnskov, C., & Rode, M. (in press). Regimes and regime transitions: A new dataset on democracy, coups, and political institutions. Forthcoming in Review of International Organizations.
Zurück zum Zitat Bjørnskov, C., & Voigt, S. (2018). Why do governments call a state of emergency? On the determinants of using emergency constitutions. European Journal of Political Economy, 54, 110–123.CrossRef Bjørnskov, C., & Voigt, S. (2018). Why do governments call a state of emergency? On the determinants of using emergency constitutions. European Journal of Political Economy, 54, 110–123.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Blanchard, O. J., & Fischer, S. (1989). Lectures on macroeconomics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Blanchard, O. J., & Fischer, S. (1989). Lectures on macroeconomics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Boix, C., Miller, M., & Rosatto, S. (2013). A complete dataset of political regimes, 1800–2007. Comparative Political Studies, 46(12), 1523–1554.CrossRef Boix, C., Miller, M., & Rosatto, S. (2013). A complete dataset of political regimes, 1800–2007. Comparative Political Studies, 46(12), 1523–1554.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Bueno de Mesquita, B., Smith, A., Siverson, R. M., & Morrow, J. D. (2003). The logic of political survival. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRef Bueno de Mesquita, B., Smith, A., Siverson, R. M., & Morrow, J. D. (2003). The logic of political survival. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cheibub, J. A., Gandhi, J., & Vreeland, J. R. (2010). Democracy and dictatorship revisited. Public Choice, 143(1–2), 67–101.CrossRef Cheibub, J. A., Gandhi, J., & Vreeland, J. R. (2010). Democracy and dictatorship revisited. Public Choice, 143(1–2), 67–101.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Congleton, R. D. (2010). Perfecting parliament. Constitutional reform, liberalism, and the rise of Western democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Congleton, R. D. (2010). Perfecting parliament. Constitutional reform, liberalism, and the rise of Western democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Debs, A. (2016). Living by the sword and dying by the sword? Leadership transitions in and out of dictatorships. International Studies Quarterly, 60, 73–84.CrossRef Debs, A. (2016). Living by the sword and dying by the sword? Leadership transitions in and out of dictatorships. International Studies Quarterly, 60, 73–84.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Elkins, Z., Ginsburg, T., & Melton, J. (2009). The endurance of national constitutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Elkins, Z., Ginsburg, T., & Melton, J. (2009). The endurance of national constitutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Geddes, B. (1999). What do we know about democratization after twenty years? Annual Review of Political Science, 2, 115–144.CrossRef Geddes, B. (1999). What do we know about democratization after twenty years? Annual Review of Political Science, 2, 115–144.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Grossman, G. M., & Helpman, E. (1994). Protection for sale. American Economic Review, 84(4), 833–850. Grossman, G. M., & Helpman, E. (1994). Protection for sale. American Economic Review, 84(4), 833–850.
Zurück zum Zitat Hillman, A. L. (1982). Declining industries and political-support protectionist motives. American Economic Review, 72(5), 1180–1187. Hillman, A. L. (1982). Declining industries and political-support protectionist motives. American Economic Review, 72(5), 1180–1187.
Zurück zum Zitat Ishak, P. W. (2019). Autocratic survival strategies: Does oil make a difference? Peace Economics, Peace Science and Public Policy, 25(2), 1–22.CrossRef Ishak, P. W. (2019). Autocratic survival strategies: Does oil make a difference? Peace Economics, Peace Science and Public Policy, 25(2), 1–22.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kokkonen, A., & Sundell, A. (in press). Leader succession and civil war. Forthcoming in Comparative Political Studies. Kokkonen, A., & Sundell, A. (in press). Leader succession and civil war. Forthcoming in Comparative Political Studies.
Zurück zum Zitat Kurrild-Klitgaard, P. (2000). The constitutional economics of autocratic succession. Public Choice, 103(1–2), 63–84.CrossRef Kurrild-Klitgaard, P. (2000). The constitutional economics of autocratic succession. Public Choice, 103(1–2), 63–84.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Lipset, S. M. (1959). Social requisites of democracy: Economic development and political legitimacy. American Political Science Review, 53(1), 69–105.CrossRef Lipset, S. M. (1959). Social requisites of democracy: Economic development and political legitimacy. American Political Science Review, 53(1), 69–105.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat North, D. (1991). Institutions. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5(1), 97–112.CrossRef North, D. (1991). Institutions. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5(1), 97–112.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat North, D., & Weingast, B. (1989). Constitutions and commitment: The evolution of institutions governing public choice in seventeenth-century England. Journal of Economic History, 49(4), 803–832.CrossRef North, D., & Weingast, B. (1989). Constitutions and commitment: The evolution of institutions governing public choice in seventeenth-century England. Journal of Economic History, 49(4), 803–832.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Olson, M. (1965). The logic of collective action: Public goods and the theory of groups. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Olson, M. (1965). The logic of collective action: Public goods and the theory of groups. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Olson, M. (1982). The rise and decline of nations: Economic growth, stagflation, and social rigidities. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Olson, M. (1982). The rise and decline of nations: Economic growth, stagflation, and social rigidities. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Persson, T., & Tabellini, G. (1999). The size and scope of government: Comparative politics with rational politicians. European Economic Review, 43(4–6), 699–735.CrossRef Persson, T., & Tabellini, G. (1999). The size and scope of government: Comparative politics with rational politicians. European Economic Review, 43(4–6), 699–735.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Persson, T., & Tabellini, G. (2006). Democracy and development: The devil is in the details. American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, 96(5), 319–324.CrossRef Persson, T., & Tabellini, G. (2006). Democracy and development: The devil is in the details. American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, 96(5), 319–324.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Przeworski, A. (1991). Democracy and the market: Political and economic reforms in Eastern Europe and Latin America. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Przeworski, A. (1991). Democracy and the market: Political and economic reforms in Eastern Europe and Latin America. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Treisman, D. (2017). Democracy by mistake. NBER Working Paper No. w23944. Treisman, D. (2017). Democracy by mistake. NBER Working Paper No. w23944.
Zurück zum Zitat Tullock, G. (1967). The welfare costs of tariffs, monopolies, and theft. Western Economic Journal, 5(3), 224–232. Tullock, G. (1967). The welfare costs of tariffs, monopolies, and theft. Western Economic Journal, 5(3), 224–232.
Zurück zum Zitat Tullock, G. (2001). Monarchies, hereditary and non-hereditary. In W. F. Shugart & L. Razzolini (Eds.), The Elgar companion to public choice (pp. 140–156). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. Tullock, G. (2001). Monarchies, hereditary and non-hereditary. In W. F. Shugart & L. Razzolini (Eds.), The Elgar companion to public choice (pp. 140–156). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Zurück zum Zitat Wintrobe, R. (1990). The tinpot and the totalitarian: An economic theory of dictatorship. American Political Science Review, 84(3), 849–872.CrossRef Wintrobe, R. (1990). The tinpot and the totalitarian: An economic theory of dictatorship. American Political Science Review, 84(3), 849–872.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Yu, S., & Jong-A-Pin, J. (2016). Political leader survival: Does competence matter? Public Choice, 166(1–2), 113–142.CrossRef Yu, S., & Jong-A-Pin, J. (2016). Political leader survival: Does competence matter? Public Choice, 166(1–2), 113–142.CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
Why do military dictatorships become presidential democracies? Mapping the democratic interests of autocratic regimes
verfasst von
Christian Bjørnskov
Publikationsdatum
17.10.2019
Verlag
Springer US
Erschienen in
Public Choice / Ausgabe 1-2/2020
Print ISSN: 0048-5829
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-7101
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00736-x

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 1-2/2020

Public Choice 1-2/2020 Zur Ausgabe

Premium Partner