Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Social Choice and Welfare 1/2020

23.08.2019 | Original Paper

Single-crossing choice correspondences

verfasst von: Matheus Costa, Paulo Henrique Ramos, Gil Riella

Erschienen in: Social Choice and Welfare | Ausgabe 1/2020

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

We characterize choice correspondences that can be justified by a collection of preferences that satisfy the single-crossing and/or single-peak properties. These are properties vastly used in the applied literature, often in the context of parametric families of objective (utility) functions that satisfy them. Apesteguia et al. (Econometrica 85(2):661–674, 2017) characterize random utility models that satisfy those properties, and we provide similar results in the context of choice correspondences that admit a pseudo-rational or justifiable choice representation. These results might be useful for researchers in situations where it is not possible to work with random utility models or parametric families of objective (utility) functions. In addition, we use them to discuss some aspects of the connection between deterministic and stochastic choice.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Anhänge
Nur mit Berechtigung zugänglich
Fußnoten
1
We discuss this small literature in Sect. 4.
 
2
Martin and Merlin define a social choice correspondence (SCC) as a mapping from collections of individual preferences (strict linear orders) to the set of possible choices. In the context of majority voting, if, for each possible profile of individual preferences, the set of alternatives that are not dominated in pairwise majority voting by any other alternative is not empty, then the mapping from the preference profiles to these winner sets can be seen as a SCC. This winner set may, though, be empty for a given profile of preferences. In this sense, as is well known, single-peakedness and single-crossingness are sufficient conditions over the profile of preferences to ensure that this will not happen (i.e. there will always be a Condorcet winner) and majority voting can be represented as a SCC.
 
3
Investigating the implications of single-crossingness on social choice, Saporiti and Tohmé (2006) explore the impact of this property in a strategic voting environment, showing that it is capable of ensuring not only the existence of majority voting equilibria but also of non-manipulable choice rules.
 
4
Bredereck et al. (2013) explore the characterization of a single-crossing profile of preferences, exposing some forbidden structures and allowing a computationally viable way to test if a preference profile satisfies single-crossingness when the ordering of voters is given, but not necessarily the exogenous ordering of the alternatives. This result relates to our work in the sense that we explore the characterization of choice correspondences that derive from a single-crossing profile, though here we specify the ordering of the alternatives but not the ordering of voters or, in our case, individual preferences.
 
5
That is, \(x\succsim y\) and \(y\succsim x\) imply that \(x=y\), for every \(x,y\in X\).
 
6
For any binary relation \(\succsim \subseteq X\times X\) and choice problem \(A\in \Omega _{X}\), the set of maximum elements of \(\succsim \) in A is defined as \( max (A,\succsim ):=\{x\in A:x\succsim y,\forall y\in A\}\)
 
7
We are making a slight abuse of notation here. Since \(\succcurlyeq _{i}\) is a linear order, we are writing \(\max (X,\succcurlyeq _{i})\) to represent the unique element \(x^{*}\in X\) such that \(x^{*}\succcurlyeq _{i}z\) for every \(z\in X\).
 
8
We again make an abuse of notation here. We are writing \(\min (X,\succcurlyeq _{i})\) to represent the unique element \(x^{*}\in X\) such that \(z\succcurlyeq _{i}x^{*}\) for every \(z\in X\).
 
9
By \(\hat{w}\) being the successor of w with respect to \(\succcurlyeq _{n}\) we mean that \(\hat{w}\succ _{n}w\) and for no \(\tilde{w}\in X\) it is true that \(\hat{w}\succ _{n}\tilde{w}\succ _{n}w\).
 
10
Notice that if \(x\succ ^{*}y\) and \(y\succ x\), then \(y\succ _{j}x\) for every \(j\in \{1,\dots ,n\}\).
 
11
Since \(x\notin \max (A,\succcurlyeq _{i^{*}-1})\), such z must exist.
 
12
Otherwise we would have \(\max (A,\succcurlyeq _{i^{*}-1})\succcurlyeq _{i^{*}-1}z\succ _{i^{*}-1}w\) for every \(w\in X{\setminus } A\), contradicting Claim 1.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Aizerman MA, Malishevski AV (1981) General theory of best variants choice: some aspects. IEEE Trans Autom Control 26(5):1030–1040CrossRef Aizerman MA, Malishevski AV (1981) General theory of best variants choice: some aspects. IEEE Trans Autom Control 26(5):1030–1040CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Apesteguia J, Ballester MA, Lu J (2017) Single-crossing random utility models. Econometrica 85(2):661–674CrossRef Apesteguia J, Ballester MA, Lu J (2017) Single-crossing random utility models. Econometrica 85(2):661–674CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Berry S, Levinsohn J, Pakes A (1995) Automobile prices in market equilibrium. Econometrica 63(4):841–890CrossRef Berry S, Levinsohn J, Pakes A (1995) Automobile prices in market equilibrium. Econometrica 63(4):841–890CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bredereck R, Chen J, Woeginger GJ (2013) A characterization of the single-crossing domain. Soc Choice Welf 41(4):989–998CrossRef Bredereck R, Chen J, Woeginger GJ (2013) A characterization of the single-crossing domain. Soc Choice Welf 41(4):989–998CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Chernoff H (1954) Rational selection of decision functions. Econometrica 22(4):422–443CrossRef Chernoff H (1954) Rational selection of decision functions. Econometrica 22(4):422–443CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat DeDonder P (2013) Majority voting and the single-crossing property when voters belong to separate groups. Econ Lett 118(3):523–525CrossRef DeDonder P (2013) Majority voting and the single-crossing property when voters belong to separate groups. Econ Lett 118(3):523–525CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fishburn PC (1978) Choice probabilities and choice functions. J Math Psychol 18:205–219CrossRef Fishburn PC (1978) Choice probabilities and choice functions. J Math Psychol 18:205–219CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Furtado BA, Nascimento L, Riella G (2019) Rational choice with full-comparability domains. Universidade de Brasília (unpublished manuscript) Furtado BA, Nascimento L, Riella G (2019) Rational choice with full-comparability domains. Universidade de Brasília (unpublished manuscript)
Zurück zum Zitat Gans J, Smart M (1996) Majority voting with single crossing preferences. J Public Econ 2:219–237CrossRef Gans J, Smart M (1996) Majority voting with single crossing preferences. J Public Econ 2:219–237CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Halldin C (1974) The choice axiom, revealed preference, and the theory of demand. Theory Decis 5:139–160CrossRef Halldin C (1974) The choice axiom, revealed preference, and the theory of demand. Theory Decis 5:139–160CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Martin M, Merlin V (2002) The stability set as a social choice correspondence. Math Soc Sci 44(1):91–113CrossRef Martin M, Merlin V (2002) The stability set as a social choice correspondence. Math Soc Sci 44(1):91–113CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Milgrom P, Shannon C (1994) Monotone comparative statics. Econometrica 62(1):157–180CrossRef Milgrom P, Shannon C (1994) Monotone comparative statics. Econometrica 62(1):157–180CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Moulin H (1985) Choice functions over a finite set: a summary. Soc Choice Welf 2(2):147–160CrossRef Moulin H (1985) Choice functions over a finite set: a summary. Soc Choice Welf 2(2):147–160CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ok EA, Tserenjigmid G (2019) Deterministic rationality of stochastic choice behavior. New York University (unpublished manuscript) Ok EA, Tserenjigmid G (2019) Deterministic rationality of stochastic choice behavior. New York University (unpublished manuscript)
Zurück zum Zitat Saporiti A, Tohmé F (2006) Single-crossing, strategic voting and the median choice rule. Soc Choice Welf 26(2):363–383CrossRef Saporiti A, Tohmé F (2006) Single-crossing, strategic voting and the median choice rule. Soc Choice Welf 26(2):363–383CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
Single-crossing choice correspondences
verfasst von
Matheus Costa
Paulo Henrique Ramos
Gil Riella
Publikationsdatum
23.08.2019
Verlag
Springer Berlin Heidelberg
Erschienen in
Social Choice and Welfare / Ausgabe 1/2020
Print ISSN: 0176-1714
Elektronische ISSN: 1432-217X
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-019-01212-7

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 1/2020

Social Choice and Welfare 1/2020 Zur Ausgabe