Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Journal of Business Ethics 2/2019

06.06.2019 | Original Paper

Technological Unemployment, Meaning in Life, Purpose of Business, and the Future of Stakeholders

verfasst von: Tae Wan Kim, Alan Scheller-Wolf

Erschienen in: Journal of Business Ethics | Ausgabe 2/2019

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

We offer a precautionary account of why business managers should proactively rethink about what kinds of automation firms ought to implement, by exploring two challenges that automation will potentially pose. We engage the current debate concerning whether life without work opportunities will incur a meaning crisis, offering an argument in favor of the position that if technological unemployment occurs, the machine age may be a structurally limited condition for many without work opportunities to have or add meaning to their lives. We term this the axiological challenge. This challenge, if it turns out to be persuasive, leads to a second challenge, to which managers should pay special attention: the teleological challenge, a topic especially relevant to the broad literature about corporate purpose and governance. We argue that both the shareholder profit-maximization model and its major alternative, stakeholder theory, are insufficient to address the meaning crisis. Unless rebutted, the two challenges compel business leaders to proactively rethink the purpose of business for future society. Otherwise, businesses will be contributors to a major ethical crisis and societal externality in the coming society.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
We use the terms “accountability” almost interchangeably with “role” or “responsibility.” Our uses of “accountability” are close to Scanlon’s (1998) uses of his term “substantive responsibility,” when he writes, “[t]o understand the conditions of responsibility in the first sense [responsibility as attributability] we need to consider the nature of moral appraisal, praise and blame. Judgments of responsibility in the second sense [substantive responsibility], by contrast, are substantive conclusions about what we owe to each other.”
 
2
Textile workers who lost jobs due to machines during the Industrial Revolution attacked mills under the leadership of a supposedly mystical figure called Ned Ludd. The workers in the riots were called “Luddites” (Jones 2006).
 
3
Friedrich A. Hayek also supported a basic income. Hayek (1981/1979, 5) writes, “The assurance of a certain minimum income for everyone, or a sort of floor below which nobody need fall even when he is unable to provide for himself, appears not only to be wholly legitimate protection against a risk common to all, but a necessary part of the Great Society…”
 
4
For details, see “Labor Force Statistics from the Current Population Survey” in the Bureau of Labor Statistics.
 
5
Although the reports already take into account job creation, to respectfully invite skeptics into our discussions, we add an additional 5% of job creation.
 
6
How much will be offered as a basic income, and what effect such universal payments might have on the economy and inflation are thorny questions. In any case, we do not think the amount would make much difference to our argument. If the reader desires details, we tentatively propose adding the statistic that everyone over 18 years old annually receives a fixed amount of cash equivalent to the value of, say, $12,500 in 2017 and anyone under 18 receives a quarter of that amount (given that an often proposed amount of an annual basic income by advocates in the current public discussions in the U.S. is usually around $10,000–13,000 per person; e.g., Murray 2016). As another possible benchmark, a recent proposal that would provide a basic monthly income of 2560 Swiss francs, or about $2600, to every adult and 625 francs to those under 18, was submitted for a referendum. On June 5, 2016, the Swiss people rejected the proposal.
 
7
We authors are extremely uncomfortable with using this example. We discussed whether to replace it. We opted to keep it, because the example exemplifies how we should be accordingly uncomfortable with subjectivism, in contrast to a commonly held view that meaningfulness of one’s life is always subjective.
 
8
In a similar vein, Kauppinen (2012, p. 356) writes “the Voluntarist [Subjectivist] view is far too permissive, once we remember to disambiguate the notion of a life being meaningful for someone. Just as a food can be unhealthy for a person even if she thinks it is healthy, a life can be meaningless for someone even if she thinks it is meaningful.”
 
9
There may be hard cases, but when those are cases of reasonably informed disagreements, the framework above submits that the form of life activity in the disagreement must be respectfully admitted as objectively worthy to the extent that no one could reasonably reject the informed argument in favor of the worthiness of the life.
 
10
Similarly, Ciulla (2000, pp. 225–226) writes: “Work has meaning because there is some good in it. The most meaningful jobs are those in which people directly help others or create products that make life better for people. Work makes life better if it helps others; alleviates suffering; eliminating difficult, dangerous, or tedious toil; makes someone healthier and happier; or aesthetically or intellectually enriches people and improves the environment in which we live.”
 
11
In response to counter-examples to the fitting-fulfillment view, Evers and van Smeden (2016) proposed modifying Wolf’s account to replace “love” with “valuing.” We believe Wolf’s is already inclusive of the suggestion.
 
12
Bernard Suits (2005) argues that work can never be meaning-creating and that game-playing is the only worthy activity. We take the message seriously, especially as we live in a workaholic society. Nevertheless, we maintain that Suits’ thesis is too strong. Not all cases of game playing are objectively meaningful (e.g., urinating in snow to melt it). Our argument submits that game playing or any activity is meaningful only if it realizes and contributes to self-development and the good of society. Thus, employed work, when it becomes a vehicle that empowers individuals to capably realize their agency and contribute to others, is meaning-creating. Consistently, Thomas Hurka, who wrote the introduction to Suits’s book, argues that economic activity is itself often a process of intrinsic value-creating activity in the modern life (Hurka & Suits, 1978). We are indebted to Joanne B. Ciulla for pressing us to discuss Suits’ work.
 
13
Of course this is not to say that everything that pharmaceutical companies engage in can be seen as beneficial and meaningful. This point is actually immaterial to our argument—the axiological challenge does not require work that is invariably meaningful, but rather work that is sufficiently meaningful. The precise definition of sufficiently in this context is a difficult question and beyond the scope of this paper.
 
14
The venture was suggested by Dr. William Campbell—who discovered that a veterinary drug, once reformulated for humans, could easily cure onchocerciasis or “river blindness”—and executed by CEO P. Roy Vagelos to provide the drug to anyone who needed it for as long as it was needed, for free (Hanson & Weiss, 1991).
 
15
For a detailed analysis of “participant” in a chain of “collective value creation” see Donaldson and Walsh (2015).
 
16
Another salient example is provided by sanitation workers, who may be looked down upon in society due to the dirty nature of their work. But there are few other occupations that do more to ensure the public good or the public health.
 
17
Of course, paid employment is not the only form of work by which one can contribute to the good of society. Those who take care of housework and raise children significantly contribute to the good. We do not deny this at all. Instead, our argument is that for very many in society, paid employment is often the best potential option present for fulfillment.
 
18
Moriarty (2009, 15), in his analysis of Rawls’s works writes: “In identifying the OMW [the opportunity for meaningful work] as a social basis of self-respect in PL [Political Liberalism, paperback edition], Rawls abandons th[e] laissez-faire approach. His new view seems to be: we cannot merely hope that if people cannot find meaningful work, they can get self-respect from other activities, such as chess or softball…This has the effect of privileging the work association over other associations as a source of self-respect.”
 
19
As Nozick (1968/1974, 247) says, “The issue of meaningful and satisfying work is often merged with discussions of self-esteem…Such an individual, it is said, can take pride in what he’s doing and in doing it well; he can feel that he is a person of worth, making a contribution of value.”
 
20
Arneson’s primary claim in his broad project about meaningful work was a public policy thesis that there is no compelling argument for the government to intervene to increase the degree of meaningful work.
 
21
Conceptually, there can be two other categories: c) those who have economic roles but do not participate in activities outside of work and d) those who do not have work opportunities and do not participate in activities outside of the economic realm.
 
22
We think this is likely evolutionary—humans who derive utility from work that is societally beneficial are more likely to form strong societies. Similarly, animals in zoos often become neurotic, because they are denied the ability to roam the broad spaces they evolved to roam and to engage in the hunting and gathering activities they evolved to engage in. Zoos have recognized this, and now work to hide a polar bear’s food, for example, to give them some poor relative substitute for the “gainful employment” they would see in the wild.
 
23
We authors are once again extremely uncomfortable with using this analogy, but opted to use it, because in romanticizing the opportunities available through leisure activities we run the risk of ignoring the societal disadvantages those without employment opportunity may face. This is not to say that those without employment opportunities cannot find fulfillment, or even thrive, in our society. Rather, we argue that their opportunities to thrive may be curtailed, and we question whether this is just. Likewise, there are countless examples of those who are disadvantaged thriving in our society. But this does not mean that the barriers to their thriving that currently exist in our society are in any way just.
 
24
Accordingly, the competing intellectual camp attempts to show that many of the jobs essential for human society are so complex in perception and manipulation that even advanced robots cannot automate them.
 
25
For instance, Frey and Osborne (2013, p. 43) write, “labour saving inventions may only be adopted if the access to cheap labour is scarce or prices of capital are relatively high. We do not account for future wage levels, capital prices or labour shortages. While these factors will impact on the timeline of our predictions, labour is the scarce factor, implying that in the long-run wage levels will increase relative to capital prices, making computerization increasingly profitable.”
 
26
To see the prescriptive aspect of social scientific research and how the prescriptive dimension could be strengthened by normative moral reasoning, see Donaldson (2012) and Kim and Donaldson (2018).
 
27
For our interpretation of libertarianism, we are indebted to Jason Brennan, who writes, “Many libertarians believe that property rights—including the right to run our businesses as we see fit—can be justified only if they systematically benefit everyone who is asked to respect those rights. If property rights end up systematically leaving some people behind, it may be unreasonable to demand that those left behind respect those property rights” (Brennan, 2012, p. 204).
 
28
In a relevantly similar manner, Tomasi writes, “Rather than being simply derivative from the public norms in a liberal society, this [the criteria of good citizen conduct] is a substantive or eudaimonistically directed understanding of liberal good citizen conduct…to be a good citizen means far more than being merely just, or law-abiding, or consistent in the performance of one’s politics duties. Liberal citizenship imposes far heavier burdens: citizenship involves the very center of one’s life” (Tomasi, 2001, pp. 67, 70).
 
29
According to the Stanford Research Institute’s memorandum, from which the theory was originally developed, a stakeholder is defined as “those groups without whose support the organization would cease to exist” (Freeman and Reed, 1983, p. 89).
 
30
A similar challenge was made to the stakeholder theory by Orts and Strudler (2002), who argued that stakeholder theory is futile for sustainability because the natural environment cannot be a stakeholder.
 
31
Macey and Miller (1993) criticize the stakeholder theory’s lack of a rigorous balancing procedure, because without such a tool, managers “can justify virtually any decision they make on the grounds that it benefits some constituency of the firm.” We do not accept this type of anything-goes criticism against stakeholder theory but acknowledge that stakeholder theory as it is does not have clear resources to prove its usefulness to address the axiological challenge.
 
32
Donaldson and Walsh (2015) added what they call the “Dignity Threshold” to the stakeholder framework. The Threshold demands minimum ethical respect to participants in collective value creation. This is a promising step forward for businesses to pay more attention to the axiological aspect of humans, and it deserves further discussion. Does business’ minimum respect for a person’s intrinsic worth mandate business’ accountability to pay attention to the challenge of meaning? Are those who seek work opportunities to contribute to the good of society participants in collective value creation?
 
33
It is possible this is just coincidence. It is also possible that these sessions are contemporary echoes of ancient Aristotelian ideals; ideals that still resonate with us and that will continue to resonate into our machine-age future.
 
34
Although the anticipated rise in Massively Open Online Communities—MOOCs—has yet to transform education as first anticipated, it is clear that crowdsourcing, community ratings sites, and, yes, Facebook have transformed how we as a society gather and transmit information, form beliefs and make decisions. We think it is important that our proposal—the corporate agora—be flexible enough to adapt to these changes.
 
35
Our premise is that some of the technologically unemployed will desire fulfilling engagement in meaningful work. Thus in our vision membership in an agora would be competitive—it presumes that members would actively want to exert effort within their community to help their “team.” Participation could be further motivated through the distribution of tokens from their agora community—Pepsi or Nike gear could serve the same identity-fulfilling purpose as a Steelers or Yankees jersey does now. This could be supplemented by distributing small shares of the company to the most productive and loyal members of the agora.
 
36
Reflecting on this example, one could argue that firms already have sufficient incentive to initiate the formation of agora. As society becomes more able to form virtual communities, and in the face of increasing technological unemployment, firms may find still more value from a dedicated band of followers. Thus forward–looking firms might be well served to explore the formation of agora presently.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Ales, L., Cho, S.-H., & Körpeoglu, E. (2017). Optimal award scheme in innovation tournaments. Operations Research,65, 693–702.CrossRef Ales, L., Cho, S.-H., & Körpeoglu, E. (2017). Optimal award scheme in innovation tournaments. Operations Research,65, 693–702.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Alzola, M. (2012). The possibility of virtue. Business Ethics Quarterly,22, 377–404.CrossRef Alzola, M. (2012). The possibility of virtue. Business Ethics Quarterly,22, 377–404.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Aristotle. (2006). Nichomachean ethics (R. Crisp, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Aristotle. (2006). Nichomachean ethics (R. Crisp, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Arneson, R. (1987). Meaningful work and market socialism. Ethics,97, 517–545.CrossRef Arneson, R. (1987). Meaningful work and market socialism. Ethics,97, 517–545.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Arneson, R. (1990). Is work special? Justice and the redistribution of employment. American Political Science Review,84, 1127–1147.CrossRef Arneson, R. (1990). Is work special? Justice and the redistribution of employment. American Political Science Review,84, 1127–1147.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Arneson, R. (2009). Meaningful work and market socialism revisited. Analysis & Kritik,31(139–151), 139. Arneson, R. (2009). Meaningful work and market socialism revisited. Analysis & Kritik,31(139–151), 139.
Zurück zum Zitat Autor, D. H. (2015). Why are there still so many jobs? The history and future of workplace automation. Journal of Economic Perspectives,29, 3–30.CrossRef Autor, D. H. (2015). Why are there still so many jobs? The history and future of workplace automation. Journal of Economic Perspectives,29, 3–30.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bhargava, V., & Kim, T. W. (2017). Autonomous vehicles and moral uncertainty. In O. Lin, K. Abney, & R. Jenkins (Eds.), Robot Ethics 2.0: New challenges in philosophy, law, and society. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bhargava, V., & Kim, T. W. (2017). Autonomous vehicles and moral uncertainty. In O. Lin, K. Abney, & R. Jenkins (Eds.), Robot Ethics 2.0: New challenges in philosophy, law, and society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Blair, M. M., & Stout, L. A. (1999). A team production theory of corporate law. Virginia Law Review,5, 247–328.CrossRef Blair, M. M., & Stout, L. A. (1999). A team production theory of corporate law. Virginia Law Review,5, 247–328.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Boatright, J. (1994). Fiduciary duties and the shareholder-management relation: Or, what’s so special about shareholders? Business Ethics Quarterly,4, 393–407.CrossRef Boatright, J. (1994). Fiduciary duties and the shareholder-management relation: Or, what’s so special about shareholders? Business Ethics Quarterly,4, 393–407.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bowie, N. E. (1990). Empowering people as an end for business. In G. Enderle, B. Almond, & A. Argandoña (Eds.), People in corporations (pp. 105–112). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRef Bowie, N. E. (1990). Empowering people as an end for business. In G. Enderle, B. Almond, & A. Argandoña (Eds.), People in corporations (pp. 105–112). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Breen, K. (2016). In defense of meaningful work as a public policy concern. In A. Fives & K. Breen (Eds.), Philosophy and political engagement: Reflection in the public sphere (pp. 139–161). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRef Breen, K. (2016). In defense of meaningful work as a public policy concern. In A. Fives & K. Breen (Eds.), Philosophy and political engagement: Reflection in the public sphere (pp. 139–161). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Brennan, J. (2012). Libertarianism: What everyone needs to know. New York: Oxford University Press. Brennan, J. (2012). Libertarianism: What everyone needs to know. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Brynjolfsson, E., & McAfee, A. (2014). The second machine age: Work, progress, and prosperity in a time of brilliant technology. New York: W.W. Norton. Brynjolfsson, E., & McAfee, A. (2014). The second machine age: Work, progress, and prosperity in a time of brilliant technology. New York: W.W. Norton.
Zurück zum Zitat Brynjolfsson, E., & McAfee, A. (2015). Will humans go the way of horses? Labor and the second machine age. Foreign Affairs,94(4), 8–14. Brynjolfsson, E., & McAfee, A. (2015). Will humans go the way of horses? Labor and the second machine age. Foreign Affairs,94(4), 8–14.
Zurück zum Zitat Brynjolfsson, E., & McAfee, A. (2016). Human work in the robotic future: Policy for the Age of Automation. Foreign Affairs,95(4), 139–150. Brynjolfsson, E., & McAfee, A. (2016). Human work in the robotic future: Policy for the Age of Automation. Foreign Affairs,95(4), 139–150.
Zurück zum Zitat Ciulla, J. (2000). The working life: The promise and betrayal of modern work. New York: Three Rivers Press. Ciulla, J. (2000). The working life: The promise and betrayal of modern work. New York: Three Rivers Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Cunliffe, J., & Erreygers, G. (2003). Basic income? Basic capital! Origins and issues of a debate. Journal of Political Philosophy,11, 89–110.CrossRef Cunliffe, J., & Erreygers, G. (2003). Basic income? Basic capital! Origins and issues of a debate. Journal of Political Philosophy,11, 89–110.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Danaher, J. (2017). Will life be worth living in a world without work? Technological unemployment and the meaning of life. Science and Engineering Ethics,23, 41–64.CrossRef Danaher, J. (2017). Will life be worth living in a world without work? Technological unemployment and the meaning of life. Science and Engineering Ethics,23, 41–64.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Davenport, T. H., & Kirby, J. (2016). Only humans need apply: Winners and losers in the age of smart machines. New York: Harper Business. Davenport, T. H., & Kirby, J. (2016). Only humans need apply: Winners and losers in the age of smart machines. New York: Harper Business.
Zurück zum Zitat Dodd, E. M., Jr. (1932). For whom are corporate managers trustees? Harvard Law Review,45, 1145–1163.CrossRef Dodd, E. M., Jr. (1932). For whom are corporate managers trustees? Harvard Law Review,45, 1145–1163.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Donaldson, T. (1994). When integration fails: The logic of prescription and description in business ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly,4, 157–169.CrossRef Donaldson, T. (1994). When integration fails: The logic of prescription and description in business ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly,4, 157–169.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Donaldson, T. (2012). The epistemic fault line in corporate governance. Academy of Management Review,37, 256–271.CrossRef Donaldson, T. (2012). The epistemic fault line in corporate governance. Academy of Management Review,37, 256–271.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Donaldson, T., & Walsh, J. P. (2015). Toward a theory of business. Research in Organizational Behavior,35, 181–207.CrossRef Donaldson, T., & Walsh, J. P. (2015). Toward a theory of business. Research in Organizational Behavior,35, 181–207.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Dunham, L., Freeman, R. E., & Liedtka, J. (2006). Enhancing stakeholder practice: A particularized exploration of community. Business Ethics Quarterly,16, 23–42.CrossRef Dunham, L., Freeman, R. E., & Liedtka, J. (2006). Enhancing stakeholder practice: A particularized exploration of community. Business Ethics Quarterly,16, 23–42.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Evan, W. M., & Freeman, R. E. (1988). A stakeholder theory of the modern corporation: Kantian capitalism. In T. Beauchamp & N. Bowie (Eds.), Ethical theory and business. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall. Evan, W. M., & Freeman, R. E. (1988). A stakeholder theory of the modern corporation: Kantian capitalism. In T. Beauchamp & N. Bowie (Eds.), Ethical theory and business. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.
Zurück zum Zitat Evers, D., & van Smeden, F. E. (2016). Meaning in life: In defense of the hybrid view. Southern Journal of Philosophy,54, 355–371.CrossRef Evers, D., & van Smeden, F. E. (2016). Meaning in life: In defense of the hybrid view. Southern Journal of Philosophy,54, 355–371.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Floridi, L. (2014). Technological unemployment, leisure occupation, and the human project. Philosophy of Technology,27, 143–150.CrossRef Floridi, L. (2014). Technological unemployment, leisure occupation, and the human project. Philosophy of Technology,27, 143–150.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Frankish, K., & Ramsey, W. M. (Eds.). (2014). The Cambridge handbook of artificial intelligence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Frankish, K., & Ramsey, W. M. (Eds.). (2014). The Cambridge handbook of artificial intelligence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Freeman, R. E. (1984). Strategic management: A stakeholder approach. Boston: Pitman. Freeman, R. E. (1984). Strategic management: A stakeholder approach. Boston: Pitman.
Zurück zum Zitat Freeman, R. E. (1994). The politics of stakeholder theory: Some future directions. Business Ethics Quarterly,4, 157–169.CrossRef Freeman, R. E. (1994). The politics of stakeholder theory: Some future directions. Business Ethics Quarterly,4, 157–169.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Freeman, R. E. (2009). Managing for stakeholders. In T. L. Beauchamp & N. E. Bowie (Eds.), Ethical theory and business (8th ed., pp. 39–53). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson/Prentice-Hall. Freeman, R. E. (2009). Managing for stakeholders. In T. L. Beauchamp & N. E. Bowie (Eds.), Ethical theory and business (8th ed., pp. 39–53). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson/Prentice-Hall.
Zurück zum Zitat Freeman, R. E., & Reed, D. L. (1983). Stockholders and stakeholders: A new perspective on corporate governance. California Management Review,25, 88–106.CrossRef Freeman, R. E., & Reed, D. L. (1983). Stockholders and stakeholders: A new perspective on corporate governance. California Management Review,25, 88–106.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Frey, C. B., & Osborne, M. A. (2013). The future of employment: How susceptible are jobs to computerization? Oxford: The Oxford Martin Programme on the Impacts of Future Technology (The University of Oxford). Frey, C. B., & Osborne, M. A. (2013). The future of employment: How susceptible are jobs to computerization? Oxford: The Oxford Martin Programme on the Impacts of Future Technology (The University of Oxford).
Zurück zum Zitat Friedman, M. (1962). Capitalism and freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Friedman, M. (1962). Capitalism and freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Gheaus, A., & Herzog, L. (2016). The goods of work (other than money!). Journal of Social Philosophy,47, 70–89.CrossRef Gheaus, A., & Herzog, L. (2016). The goods of work (other than money!). Journal of Social Philosophy,47, 70–89.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Grün, C., Hauser, W., & Rhein, T. (2010). Is any job better than no job? Life satisfaction and re-employment. Journal of Labor Research,31, 285–306.CrossRef Grün, C., Hauser, W., & Rhein, T. (2010). Is any job better than no job? Life satisfaction and re-employment. Journal of Labor Research,31, 285–306.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hanson, K. O., & Weiss, S. (1991). Merck & Co., Inc. case series (A, B, C, D, video). Stanford, CA: Business Enterprise Trust. Hanson, K. O., & Weiss, S. (1991). Merck & Co., Inc. case series (A, B, C, D, video). Stanford, CA: Business Enterprise Trust.
Zurück zum Zitat Hart, O., & Zingales, L. (2017). Companies should maximize shareholder welfare not market value. Journal of Law, Finance, and Accounting,2, 247–274.CrossRef Hart, O., & Zingales, L. (2017). Companies should maximize shareholder welfare not market value. Journal of Law, Finance, and Accounting,2, 247–274.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hart, O., & Zingales, L. (unpublished manuscript). Should a company pursue a shareholder value? Hart, O., & Zingales, L. (unpublished manuscript). Should a company pursue a shareholder value?
Zurück zum Zitat Hartman, E. (1996). Organizational ethics and the good life. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hartman, E. (1996). Organizational ethics and the good life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Hayek, F. A. (1979). The political order of a free people. In Law, legislation, and liberty (Vol. 3) (1981). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Hayek, F. A. (1979). The political order of a free people. In Law, legislation, and liberty (Vol. 3) (1981). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Hsieh, N.-h. (2008). Survey article: Justice in production. Journal of Political Philosophy, 16(1), 72–100.CrossRef Hsieh, N.-h. (2008). Survey article: Justice in production. Journal of Political Philosophy, 16(1), 72–100.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hurka, T., & Suits, B. (1978). Introduction. In The grasshopper: Games, life, and utopia. Broadview Press. Hurka, T., & Suits, B. (1978). Introduction. In The grasshopper: Games, life, and utopia. Broadview Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Hussain, W. (2018). The common good. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Hussain, W. (2018). The common good. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Zurück zum Zitat Jensen, M. C. (2002). Value maximization, stakeholder theory, and the corporate objective function. Business Ethics Quarterly,2, 235–256.CrossRef Jensen, M. C. (2002). Value maximization, stakeholder theory, and the corporate objective function. Business Ethics Quarterly,2, 235–256.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Jones, T. M. (1995). Instrumental stakeholder theory: A synthesis of ethics and economics. Academy of Management Review,20, 404–437.CrossRef Jones, T. M. (1995). Instrumental stakeholder theory: A synthesis of ethics and economics. Academy of Management Review,20, 404–437.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Jones, S. E. (2006). Against technology: From the Luddites to neo-liberalism. New York: Routledge. Jones, S. E. (2006). Against technology: From the Luddites to neo-liberalism. New York: Routledge.
Zurück zum Zitat Jones, T. M., & Wicks, A. C. (1999). Convergent stakeholder theory. Academy of Management Review,24, 206–221.CrossRef Jones, T. M., & Wicks, A. C. (1999). Convergent stakeholder theory. Academy of Management Review,24, 206–221.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kauppinen, A. (2012). Meaningfulness and time. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,2, 345–377.CrossRef Kauppinen, A. (2012). Meaningfulness and time. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,2, 345–377.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kennedy, J. A., Kim, T., & Strudler, A. (2016). Hierarchies and dignity: A Confucian communitarian approach. Business Ethics Quarterly,26, 479–502.CrossRef Kennedy, J. A., Kim, T., & Strudler, A. (2016). Hierarchies and dignity: A Confucian communitarian approach. Business Ethics Quarterly,26, 479–502.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Keynes, J. M. (1930). Economic possibilities for our grandchildren. In Essays in persuasion (pp. 358–373) (1963). New York: W. W. Norton & Co. Keynes, J. M. (1930). Economic possibilities for our grandchildren. In Essays in persuasion (pp. 358–373) (1963). New York: W. W. Norton & Co.
Zurück zum Zitat Kim, T. W., & Donaldson, T. (2018). Rethinking right: Moral epistemology in management research. Journal of Business Ethics,148, 1–16.CrossRef Kim, T. W., & Donaldson, T. (2018). Rethinking right: Moral epistemology in management research. Journal of Business Ethics,148, 1–16.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Korner, A., Reitzle, M., & Silbereisen, R. K. (2012). Work-related demands and life satisfaction: The effects of engagement and disengagement among employed and long-term unemployed people. Journal of Vocational Behavior,80, 187–196.CrossRef Korner, A., Reitzle, M., & Silbereisen, R. K. (2012). Work-related demands and life satisfaction: The effects of engagement and disengagement among employed and long-term unemployed people. Journal of Vocational Behavior,80, 187–196.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Levy, F., & Murnane, R. J. (2004/2005). The division of lab. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Levy, F., & Murnane, R. J. (2004/2005). The division of lab. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Macey, J. R., & Miller, G. (1993). Corporate stakeholders: A contractual perspective. The University of Toronto Law Journal,43, 401–424.CrossRef Macey, J. R., & Miller, G. (1993). Corporate stakeholders: A contractual perspective. The University of Toronto Law Journal,43, 401–424.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Martin, K. (2016). Do privacy notices matter? Comparing the impact of violating formal privacy notices and informal privacy norms on consumer trust online. Journal of Legal Studies,45, 191–211.CrossRef Martin, K. (2016). Do privacy notices matter? Comparing the impact of violating formal privacy notices and informal privacy norms on consumer trust online. Journal of Legal Studies,45, 191–211.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat McKee-Ryan, F. M., Song, Z., Wanberg, C. R., & Kinicki, A. J. (2005). Psychological and physical well-being during unemployment: A meta-analytic study. Journal of Applied Psychology,90, 53–76.CrossRef McKee-Ryan, F. M., Song, Z., Wanberg, C. R., & Kinicki, A. J. (2005). Psychological and physical well-being during unemployment: A meta-analytic study. Journal of Applied Psychology,90, 53–76.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat McMahon, C. (2010). The public authority of the managers or private organizations. In G. G. Brenkert & T. L. Beauchamp (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of business ethics (pp. 100–125). New York: Oxford University Press. McMahon, C. (2010). The public authority of the managers or private organizations. In G. G. Brenkert & T. L. Beauchamp (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of business ethics (pp. 100–125). New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Metz, T. (2013). Meaning in life: An analytic study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Metz, T. (2013). Meaning in life: An analytic study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Michaelson, C. (2005). Dialogue: Meaningful motivation and work motivation theory. Academy of Management Review,30, 235–238.CrossRef Michaelson, C. (2005). Dialogue: Meaningful motivation and work motivation theory. Academy of Management Review,30, 235–238.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Mitchell, T. R., Agle, B. R., & Wood, D. J. (1997). Toward a theory of stakeholder identification and salience: Defining the principle of who and what really counts. Academy of Management Review,22, 853–886.CrossRef Mitchell, T. R., Agle, B. R., & Wood, D. J. (1997). Toward a theory of stakeholder identification and salience: Defining the principle of who and what really counts. Academy of Management Review,22, 853–886.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Moore, G. E. (1903/1993). Principia ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Moore, G. E. (1903/1993). Principia ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Moriarty, J. (2009). Rawls, self-respect, and the opportunity for meaningful work. Social Theory and Practice,35, 441–459.CrossRef Moriarty, J. (2009). Rawls, self-respect, and the opportunity for meaningful work. Social Theory and Practice,35, 441–459.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Müller, V. C. (Ed.). (2016). Fundamentals issues of artificial intelligence. Berlin: Springer. Müller, V. C. (Ed.). (2016). Fundamentals issues of artificial intelligence. Berlin: Springer.
Zurück zum Zitat Nozick, R. (1968/1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books. Nozick, R. (1968/1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Orts, E. (2012). Business person: A legal theory of the firm. New York: Oxford University Press. Orts, E. (2012). Business person: A legal theory of the firm. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Orts, E. W., & Strudler, A. (2002). The ethical and environmental limits of stakeholder theory. Business Ethics Quarterly,12, 215–233.CrossRef Orts, E. W., & Strudler, A. (2002). The ethical and environmental limits of stakeholder theory. Business Ethics Quarterly,12, 215–233.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Orts, E., & Strudler, A. (2009). Putting a stake in stakeholder theory. Journal of Business Ethics,88, 615–650.CrossRef Orts, E., & Strudler, A. (2009). Putting a stake in stakeholder theory. Journal of Business Ethics,88, 615–650.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Parmar, B. L., Freeman, R., Harrison, J. S., Wicks, A. C., & de Colle, S. (2010). Stakeholder theory: The state of the art. Academy of Management Annals, 4(1), 403–445.CrossRef Parmar, B. L., Freeman, R., Harrison, J. S., Wicks, A. C., & de Colle, S. (2010). Stakeholder theory: The state of the art. Academy of Management Annals, 4(1), 403–445.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Phillips, R. A. (1997). Stakeholder theory and a principle of fairness. Business Ethics Quarterly,7, 51–56.CrossRef Phillips, R. A. (1997). Stakeholder theory and a principle of fairness. Business Ethics Quarterly,7, 51–56.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Phillips, R. A. (2003). Stakeholder legitimacy. Business Ethics Quarterly,13, 25–41.CrossRef Phillips, R. A. (2003). Stakeholder legitimacy. Business Ethics Quarterly,13, 25–41.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Phillips, R., & Freeman, R. E. (2002). Stakeholder theory: A libertarian defense. Business Ethics Quarterly,12, 331–349.CrossRef Phillips, R., & Freeman, R. E. (2002). Stakeholder theory: A libertarian defense. Business Ethics Quarterly,12, 331–349.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Phillips, R., Freeman, R. E., & Wicks, A. C. (2003). What stakeholder theory is not. Business Ethics Quarterly,13, 479–502.CrossRef Phillips, R., Freeman, R. E., & Wicks, A. C. (2003). What stakeholder theory is not. Business Ethics Quarterly,13, 479–502.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Remus, D., & Levy, F. S. (2017). Can robots be lawyers? Computers, lawyers, and the practice of law. Georgetown Journal of Legal Ethics,30, 501–558. Remus, D., & Levy, F. S. (2017). Can robots be lawyers? Computers, lawyers, and the practice of law. Georgetown Journal of Legal Ethics,30, 501–558.
Zurück zum Zitat Rorty, R. (1989). Contingency, irony, and solidarity. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Rorty, R. (1989). Contingency, irony, and solidarity. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Sen, A. K. (1999). Development as freedom. New York: Oxford University Press. Sen, A. K. (1999). Development as freedom. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Simon, H. A. (1957). Authority. In E. D. Arensberg (Ed.), Research in industrial human relations (pp. 103–118). New York: Harper and Brothers. Simon, H. A. (1957). Authority. In E. D. Arensberg (Ed.), Research in industrial human relations (pp. 103–118). New York: Harper and Brothers.
Zurück zum Zitat Sison, A. J. (2015). Happiness and virtue ethics in business: The ultimate value proposition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sison, A. J. (2015). Happiness and virtue ethics in business: The ultimate value proposition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Smith, J. (Unpublished manuscript). On the market’s plurality of aims: Implications for corporate responsibility. The Zicklin Center Normative Business Ethics Workshop Series (presented on March 17 2017). Smith, J. (Unpublished manuscript). On the market’s plurality of aims: Implications for corporate responsibility. The Zicklin Center Normative Business Ethics Workshop Series (presented on March 17 2017).
Zurück zum Zitat Solomon, R. (1992a). Corporate roles, personal virtues: An Aristotelian approach to business ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly,2, 317–339.CrossRef Solomon, R. (1992a). Corporate roles, personal virtues: An Aristotelian approach to business ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly,2, 317–339.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Solomon, R. (1992b). Ethics and excellence. New York: Oxford University Press. Solomon, R. (1992b). Ethics and excellence. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Stout, L. A. (2002). Bad and not-so-bad arguments for shareholder primacy. Southern California Law Review,75, 1189–1209. Stout, L. A. (2002). Bad and not-so-bad arguments for shareholder primacy. Southern California Law Review,75, 1189–1209.
Zurück zum Zitat Stout, L. A. (2012). The problem of corporate purpose. Issues in Governance Studies,48, 1–12. Stout, L. A. (2012). The problem of corporate purpose. Issues in Governance Studies,48, 1–12.
Zurück zum Zitat Strudler, A. (2017). What to do with corporate wealth. Journal of Political Philosophy,25, 108–126.CrossRef Strudler, A. (2017). What to do with corporate wealth. Journal of Political Philosophy,25, 108–126.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Suits, B. (2005). The grasshopper: Games, life and utopia. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Suits, B. (2005). The grasshopper: Games, life and utopia. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Terwiesch, C., & Ulrich, K. (2009). Innovation tournaments: Creating and selecting exceptional opportunities. Boston: Harvard Business Press. Terwiesch, C., & Ulrich, K. (2009). Innovation tournaments: Creating and selecting exceptional opportunities. Boston: Harvard Business Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Tomasi, J. (2001). Liberalism beyond justice: Citizens and the boundaries of political theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Tomasi, J. (2001). Liberalism beyond justice: Citizens and the boundaries of political theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Ufberg, D. D. (2017). Business ethics in the age of robotics lecture features Wharton business professor. Miami Law News Articles. Ufberg, D. D. (2017). Business ethics in the age of robotics lecture features Wharton business professor. Miami Law News Articles.
Zurück zum Zitat Van Parijs, P. (1992). Arguing for basic income. London: Verso. Van Parijs, P. (1992). Arguing for basic income. London: Verso.
Zurück zum Zitat Van Parijs, P. (2004). Basic income: A simple and powerful idea for the twenty-first century. Politics and Society,32, 7–39.CrossRef Van Parijs, P. (2004). Basic income: A simple and powerful idea for the twenty-first century. Politics and Society,32, 7–39.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Veltman, A. (2014). Meaningful work. New York: Oxford University Press. Veltman, A. (2014). Meaningful work. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Walsh, A. C. (1994). Meaningful work as a distributive good. Southern Journal of Philosophy,32, 233–250.CrossRef Walsh, A. C. (1994). Meaningful work as a distributive good. Southern Journal of Philosophy,32, 233–250.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Wicks, A. C., & Freeman, R. E. (1998). Organization studies and the new pragmatism: Positivism, anti-positivism, and the search for ethics. Organization Science,9, 123–140.CrossRef Wicks, A. C., & Freeman, R. E. (1998). Organization studies and the new pragmatism: Positivism, anti-positivism, and the search for ethics. Organization Science,9, 123–140.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Williamson, O. E. (1975). Markets and hierarchies: Analysis and antitrust implications. New York: Free Press. Williamson, O. E. (1975). Markets and hierarchies: Analysis and antitrust implications. New York: Free Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Wolf, S. (1997a). Happiness and meaning: Two aspects of the good life. Social Philosophy and Policy,14, 207–225.CrossRef Wolf, S. (1997a). Happiness and meaning: Two aspects of the good life. Social Philosophy and Policy,14, 207–225.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Wolf, S. (1997). Meaning and morality. Proceeds of the Aristotelian society, XCVII, 299–315. Wolf, S. (1997). Meaning and morality. Proceeds of the Aristotelian society, XCVII, 299–315.
Zurück zum Zitat Wolf, S. (2007). The meanings of lives. In J. Perry, M. Bratman, & J. M. Fischer (Eds.), Introduction to philosophy (pp. 62–73). New York: Oxford University Press. Wolf, S. (2007). The meanings of lives. In J. Perry, M. Bratman, & J. M. Fischer (Eds.), Introduction to philosophy (pp. 62–73). New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Wolf, S. (2010). Meaning in life and why it matters. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef Wolf, S. (2010). Meaning in life and why it matters. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Wolf, S. (2014). Happiness and meaning: A plurality of values rather than a conflict of norms. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society,158, 18–24. Wolf, S. (2014). Happiness and meaning: A plurality of values rather than a conflict of norms. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society,158, 18–24.
Zurück zum Zitat Yeoman, R. (2014). Meaningful work and workplace democracy. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRef Yeoman, R. (2014). Meaningful work and workplace democracy. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Zingales, L. (1998). Corporate governance. In P. Newman (Ed.), The new Palgrave dictionary of economics and the law (pp. 497–502). London: MacMillan Reference Ltd. Zingales, L. (1998). Corporate governance. In P. Newman (Ed.), The new Palgrave dictionary of economics and the law (pp. 497–502). London: MacMillan Reference Ltd.
Metadaten
Titel
Technological Unemployment, Meaning in Life, Purpose of Business, and the Future of Stakeholders
verfasst von
Tae Wan Kim
Alan Scheller-Wolf
Publikationsdatum
06.06.2019
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Erschienen in
Journal of Business Ethics / Ausgabe 2/2019
Print ISSN: 0167-4544
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-0697
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-019-04205-9

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 2/2019

Journal of Business Ethics 2/2019 Zur Ausgabe

Premium Partner