Skip to main content

2018 | OriginalPaper | Buchkapitel

The Priority of Social Morality

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

In a number of works, I have argued that social morality—a system of internalized “social-moral rules”—is fundamental to human social cooperation. Russell Hardin disputed this, arguing instead for the primacy of conventions, based largely on self-interest, in developing cooperative social order. This chapter considers three challenges for my view raised by Hardin. The chapter commences by considering small-scale cooperation; I believe that the evidence indicates that even in very small groups of face-to-face cooperators, the internalization of moral rules is fundamental to their cooperation and cheater suppression. I then consider Hardin’s charge that accounts of social cooperation based on moral rules, in which individuals act on the rules despite their interests, are stuck with invoking a variety of somewhat dubious and weak “claims of moral commitment or shared values through [to] Rawls’s magical ‘addition of the sense of justice and moral sentiment’ to make justice work at a large scale.” I argue that the evidence in support of internalized rule compliance, even in the face of high costs to personal interests, is impressive, and the underlying mechanisms are not mysterious. Lastly, I briefly turn to the fundamental issue of how social morality functions in large-scale settings and, importantly, whether it is largely displaced by formal legal and political institutions.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
David Estlund (2011, 2014) explicitly accepts that the true theory of justice may well have no practical value.
 
2
Shaun Nichols and I have argued for this, with special reference to Bodo ethics, in Gaus and Nichols (2017).
 
3
For a different sort of claim that purely instrumental reasoning is in some way more basic than the notion of a rule-based social morality, see Moehler (2014).
 
4
Moving a bit beyond classic coordination problems, think of a “coordination” interaction such as a Stag Hunt. Even if we have achieved “hunt stag” equilibrium—which might be maintained simply by self-interest—a rule that makes it a moral requirement to hunt stag may stabilize cooperation in the face of trembling hands and other uncertainties.
 
5
Let us say that for a rule R to be a genuine social-moral rule for Betty, Betty must (i) recognize R as rule that applies to C circumstances; (ii) typically have motivating reason to conform to R rather than act simply on her own goals in C circumstances; (iii) her personal normative convictions endorse R; (iv) she believes that a sufficiently large subset of her group G conforms to R; (v) she believes that a sufficiently large subset of G expects her to conform to R. See further Gaus (2011: 163–181). In this chapter, I shall not distinguish the rules of social morality from social norms. They are not, however, equivalent; the rules of social morality are parts of practices of accountability and sustain the moral emotions of guilt, resentment and indignation; not all social norms do so.
 
6
See also Hardin (2013: 411ff; 2003: 98).
 
7
The rules are external in the sense that while agents understand them to be social guidelines that serve a purpose, their motivation to comply is simply that sanctions will be applied by others. I consider the contrast to “internalized” moral rules in more detail in section “The Internalization of Moral Rules” below.
 
8
See, however, the wider characterization of a convention in Bowles and Gintis (2011: 111).
 
9
Much depends on what is meant by a “closed” society. Marriage networks, for example, can make the group much more porous than first inspection would indicate.
 
10
This is one reason why “direct reciprocity” (e.g., “tit-for-tat” responses) is often a poor basis for social cooperation, engendering cycles of conflicts. See further, Boehm (2012: 60ff).
 
11
Boehm reports that in his database about half the hunter-gather societies are coded as having practiced capital punishment; there is strong reason to think that the number may be much higher, as central governments treat band and tribal executions as murder (2012: 84).
 
12
While females seldom participate in the executions, they do typically participate in the deliberation leading to execution.
 
13
As Bowles and Gintis point out, in large-scale societies too, anti-social punishment (counter-punishment) is real: experiments show great differences in societies to the extent to which punishment is accepted or evokes counter-sanctioning (Ibid.). As we shall see below that in experiments in “Power-to-Take” games, Takers who were sanctioned by their partners for taking the partner’s endowments but who did not see these takings as unfair, did not decrease their takings in a second round; in contrast, those who were sanctioned and did think their initial taking unfair (but hoped to get away with it) responded to sanctioning by decreasing their takings.
 
14
Boehm (2012: 44–45) muses that Cephu may have been something of an amoral psychopath, and so unable to internalize moral rules.
 
15
For a striking case, see Boehm (1999: 51–59).
 
16
In Boehm’s database, of the societies that engaged in capital punishment, a repeat murder was the second most reported capital offense.
 
17
It is generally thought that young children see harm to others as violating a basic moral requirement. See Turiel et al. (1987: 174). Guilt is especially associated with violation of rules against harm and the rights of others (Prinz 2007: 77).
 
18
Bowles and Gintis devote much care to analyzing how internalization of social morality can be modeled (Chap. 10). As they stress, the internalization of norms is an aspect of cultural transmission that affects preferences or values. On the general phenomenon of cultural transmission, see Richerson and Boyd (2005).
 
19
Daniel Friedman points to 150, with much larger numbers when groups fused (Friedman 2008: 16). See also David C. Rose, who mentions 200 as the typical size of the groups in which humans evolved (Rose 2011: chp. 3). Closer examination shows that group size may be understood differently: average band size may differ from typical group size (Bowles and Gintis 2011: 95).
 
20
For doubts, see Richerson and Boyd (2013).
 
21
On the other hand, it could well have been such instability that increased the benefits of cooperation (Bowles and Gintis 2011: 93ff).
 
22
To what extent genes have evolved during this period is a highly controversial question. 10,000 years is far less than the 1000 generations, which is the rule-of-thumb for the evolution of major traits. But this is a highly controversial matter that is being debated (Cochran and Harpending 2009). For a rather more widely accepted view of the relation of genetic and cultural evolution, see Henrich (2016).
 
23
Though I have argued that it is surprisingly so (Gaus 2015).
 
24
Thus the common depiction of Hobbes as somehow the father of rational choice theory (even though Hobbes himself had a much more sophisticated view of human motivation). See, for example, Hartmut Kliemt, Philosophy and Economics I: Methods and Models (Munich: Oldenbourg, 2009), pp. 46ff.
 
25
On the importance of reasons, see Bicchieri and Mercier (2014).
 
26
Plausible models of internalization often yield polymorphic results, with a population divided between internalizers and more opportunistic types. See, for example, Andrighetto et al. (2010).
 
27
See, for example, Gaus (2016: chap. IV).
 
28
Bicchieri and her co-workers have shown how subjects exploit normative ambiguity in order to provide wiggle room to advance their interests. See Bicchieri and Chavez (2013a) and Bicchieri and Mercier (2013b).
 
29
As in the folk theorem, Binmore (2005: chap. 5).
 
30
Indirect reciprocity, or reputation, might seem to underwrite cooperation in larger groups by encouraging “boycotts” of violators, but indirect reciprocity turns out to be very sensitive to the quality of information about people. See Henrich and Henrich (2007: chap. 4), Bowles and Gintis (2011: 68–70) and Vanderschraaf (2007: 167–195).
 
31
In Bowles and Gintis’s agent-based modeling allowing even for small rates of errors in reciprocation, groups over 10 seldom, and over 15 essentially never, evolved cooperation (2011: 64–68). Even in small group forager bands, direct reciprocity does not explain most cooperation (Boehm 2012: 179–180).
 
32
The experimental work on strong reciprocity and altruistic punishment is now extensive. The pioneering work was done by Ernst Fehr and his colleagues. See, for example, Fehr and Fischbacher (2005) and Fehr and Gächter (2000a, b).
 
33
The now famous Ultimatum Game is a single-play game between two anonymous subjects, Proposer and Responder, who have X amount of some endowment (say, money) to distribute between them. In the classic version of the game, Proposer makes the first move, and gives an offer of the form, “I will take n amount of X, leaving you with Xn,” where n is not greater than X. If Responder accepts, each gets what Proposer offers; if Responder rejects, each receives nothing. For a recent overview see Eric van Damme et al. (2014).
 
34
Here some small-scale societies are outliers. See Heinrich and Smith (2004).
 
35
See Hoffman et al. (1996).
 
36
See, for example, Slonim and Roth (1998). In one study with an endowment worth three month’s wages still displayed Responder rejection of lower offers (Bicchieri 2006: 114n).
 
37
One possible explanation—one that Russell sees as partaking of the magical—is that people may be moved by a sense of justice (Rawls 1999: chap. VIII). I do not think it is magical, and some evidence indicates that impartial concern for justice may be a motivational factor (Carlsmith et al. 2002: 284–299). Third-party punishment might be seen as based on an impartial sense of justice, and there is certainly considerable evidence for such punishment. See also Fehr Fischbacher (2004). However, I do not think the evidence indicates this to be a critical factor, once we have factored out the reactive moral emotions, such as anger. In an interesting experiment Simon Knight sought to determine whether Responders were upholding such a sense of justice—whether “the concern is with unfair offers in general”—or were responding not to the Proposer’s general status as a sharer or miser, but specifically what the Proposer did to her—whether the Proposer gave her a high or low offer. Knight finds that Responders’ behavior supports the latter hypothesis—that Responder Betty’s action is more strongly influenced by what has been done to her, so she will be apt to accept a high offer from a generally unfair Proposer or reject one from a generally fair one (Knight 2012).
 
38
See, for example, Hopfensitz and Reuben (2009).
 
39
Thus my focus at present is second-party, not third-party, punishment.
 
40
Another cost to which punishers appear insensitive is the number of violators; even if defection is “the norm”—there are many defectors—punishment does not generally decrease (Bone, Silva, and Raihani).
 
41
See, for example, Knight (2012: 7–8). As we shall see in the next section, expectations count.
 
42
To drastically oversimplify, The Reactive Emotion View can be modeled as claiming the decisions are based on a two-part value function. Letting Xn be an offer in an Ultimatum Game, where X is the total endowment and n is the amount Proposer reserves for himself, then Responder’s total value of the Xn offer will be V MGV RE, where V MG is the value of the absolute monetary gain, and V RE is the value based on the reactive emotions, a value arising from the negative emotions, which focus on the ratio of X to n, as mediated by expectations of what is to be expected. A Responder will accept if total value is positive, reject if it is negative.
 
43
In the so-called “Dictator Game” Proposer simply decides on the two shares, and that’s the end of the game (not much of a game).
 
44
The variability of destruction is meant to uncover the relation of degree of emotional response to degree of punishment; I discuss presently a version of Power-to-Take that gives only limited punishment options which, not too surprisingly, considerably blunts the importance of emotions.
 
45
This is typical of takings in Power-to-Take Games; see Reuben and van Winden (2010: 912.)
 
46
“In both conditions, the sequence of actions was as follows. Before subjects played the one-shot PTT-game, they were randomly divided into two groups. One group was referred to as participants A (the take authorities) and the other as participants B (the responders). Subsequently, random pairs of a responder and a take authority were formed by letting take authorities draw a coded envelope from a box. The envelope contained a form on which the endowment of both participant A and participant B was stated. The take authorities then had to fill in a take rate and put the form back in the envelope again. After the envelopes were collected, we asked the take authorities to report their emotions as well as their expectation of what the responder would do. The envelopes were brought to the matched responders who filled in the part of their endowments to be destroyed. The envelopes containing the forms were then returned to the take authorities for their information. Meanwhile, responders were asked to indicate which take rate they had expected and how intensely they had experienced several emotions after having learned about the take rate. After completing the questionnaires and collecting all envelopes, subjects were privately paid outside the laboratory by the cashier who was not present during the experiment. Experimenters were not able to see what decisions subjects made in the game and how much they earned” (Bosman et al. 2005: 415).
 
47
That contempt is a significant emotion in almost all experiments suggests that pride is an important explanatory character trait.
 
48
On the relation of guilt to interpersonal harm, see Berndsen et al. (2004).
 
49
It is important that Thulin and Bicchieri’s target emotion appears distinctly moral; in one study emotions were measured, for example, on a 7-point scale from “Strongly Disagree” to “Strongly Agree” with statements such as “I feel angry when I learn about people suffering from unfairness” and “I think it’s shameful when injustice is allowed to occur.” These emotions are moral emotions, presupposing a normative content, thus in my terms they appear to function as moral rules.
 
50
The tale of Cephu seems to manifest both the “steaming up” and “cooling down” dynamics.
 
51
In some contexts, Russell intimated that the problem with all rule systems is that, because they depend on identification of a set of act-types, they cannot be usefully scaled up to regulate dynamic societies with constantly changing act-types. Nichols and I analyze this idea in Gaus and Nichols (2017).
 
52
I have expanded upon this point in Gaus (2018).
 
53
In addition to Mackie (2017), see Bicchieri (2016) and Bicchieri and Mercier (2014).
 
54
For a short description of this experiment, see Mockus (2012). For an in-depth treatment, see Mockus (2017).
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Andersen, Steffen, Seda Ertaç, Uri Gneezy, Moshe Hoffman, and John A. List. 2011. Stakes Matter in Ultimatum Games. The American Economic Review 101: 3427–3439.CrossRef Andersen, Steffen, Seda Ertaç, Uri Gneezy, Moshe Hoffman, and John A. List. 2011. Stakes Matter in Ultimatum Games. The American Economic Review 101: 3427–3439.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Andrighetto, Giulia, Daniel Villatoro, and Rosaria Conte. 2010. Norm Internalization in Artificial Societies. AI Communications 23: 325–339. Andrighetto, Giulia, Daniel Villatoro, and Rosaria Conte. 2010. Norm Internalization in Artificial Societies. AI Communications 23: 325–339.
Zurück zum Zitat Berndsen, Mariëtte, Joop van der Pligt, Bertjan Doosje, and Antony Manstead. 2004. Guilt and Regret: The Determining Role of Interpersonal and Intrapersonal Harm. Cognition and Emotion 18: 55–70.CrossRef Berndsen, Mariëtte, Joop van der Pligt, Bertjan Doosje, and Antony Manstead. 2004. Guilt and Regret: The Determining Role of Interpersonal and Intrapersonal Harm. Cognition and Emotion 18: 55–70.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bicchieri, Cristina. 2006. The Grammar of Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bicchieri, Cristina. 2006. The Grammar of Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2016. Norms in the Wild: How to Diagnose, Measure and Change Social Norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ———. 2016. Norms in the Wild: How to Diagnose, Measure and Change Social Norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Bicchieri, Cristina, and Alex Chavez. 2013. Norm Manipulation, Norm Evasion: Experimental Evidence. Economics and Philosophy 29: 175–198.CrossRef Bicchieri, Cristina, and Alex Chavez. 2013. Norm Manipulation, Norm Evasion: Experimental Evidence. Economics and Philosophy 29: 175–198.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bicchieri, Cristina, and Hugo Mercier. 2013. Self-Serving Biases and Public Justifications in Trust Games. Synthese 190: 909–922.CrossRef Bicchieri, Cristina, and Hugo Mercier. 2013. Self-Serving Biases and Public Justifications in Trust Games. Synthese 190: 909–922.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2014. Norms and Beliefs: How Change Occurs. In The Complexity of Social Norms, ed. Maria Xenitidou and Bruce Edmonds, 37–54. New York: Springer.CrossRef ———. 2014. Norms and Beliefs: How Change Occurs. In The Complexity of Social Norms, ed. Maria Xenitidou and Bruce Edmonds, 37–54. New York: Springer.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Binmore, Ken. 2005. Natural Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Binmore, Ken. 2005. Natural Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Boehm, Christopher. 1999. Hierarchy in the Forest: The Evolution of Egalitarian Behavior. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Boehm, Christopher. 1999. Hierarchy in the Forest: The Evolution of Egalitarian Behavior. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2012. Moral Origins: The Evolution of Virtue, Altruism and Shame. New York: Basic Books. ———. 2012. Moral Origins: The Evolution of Virtue, Altruism and Shame. New York: Basic Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Bone, Jonathan, Antonio S. Silva, and Nichola J. Raihani. 2014. Defectors, Not Norm Violators, are Punished by Third-Parties. Biology Letters 10. doi:10.1098/rsbl.2014.0388. Bone, Jonathan, Antonio S. Silva, and Nichola J. Raihani. 2014. Defectors, Not Norm Violators, are Punished by Third-Parties. Biology Letters 10. doi:10.1098/rsbl.2014.0388.
Zurück zum Zitat Bosman, Ronald, and Frans van Winden. 2002. Emotional Hazard in a Power-to-Take Experiment. The Economic Journal 112: 147–169.CrossRef Bosman, Ronald, and Frans van Winden. 2002. Emotional Hazard in a Power-to-Take Experiment. The Economic Journal 112: 147–169.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bosman, Ronald, Matthias Sutter, and Frans van Winden. 2005. The Impact of Real Effort and Emotions in the Power-To-Take Game. Journal of Economic Psychology 26: 407–429.CrossRef Bosman, Ronald, Matthias Sutter, and Frans van Winden. 2005. The Impact of Real Effort and Emotions in the Power-To-Take Game. Journal of Economic Psychology 26: 407–429.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bowles, Samuel, and Herbert Gintis. 2011. A Cooperative Species: Human Reciprocity and Its Evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef Bowles, Samuel, and Herbert Gintis. 2011. A Cooperative Species: Human Reciprocity and Its Evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Carlsmith, Kevin M., John M. Darley, and Paul H. Robinson. 2002. Why Do We Punish?: Deterrence and Just Deserts as Motives for Punishment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 83: 284–299.CrossRef Carlsmith, Kevin M., John M. Darley, and Paul H. Robinson. 2002. Why Do We Punish?: Deterrence and Just Deserts as Motives for Punishment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 83: 284–299.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cochran, Gregory, and Henry Harpending. 2009. The 10,000 Year Explosion: How Civilization Accelerated Human Evolution. New York: Basic Books. Cochran, Gregory, and Henry Harpending. 2009. The 10,000 Year Explosion: How Civilization Accelerated Human Evolution. New York: Basic Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Cummins, Denise Dellarosa. 1996a. Evidence for the Innateness of Deontic Reasoning. Mind and Language 11: 160–190.CrossRef Cummins, Denise Dellarosa. 1996a. Evidence for the Innateness of Deontic Reasoning. Mind and Language 11: 160–190.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 1996b. Evidence of Deontic Reasoning in 3- and 4-Year-Olds. Memory and Cognition 24: 823–829.CrossRef ———. 1996b. Evidence of Deontic Reasoning in 3- and 4-Year-Olds. Memory and Cognition 24: 823–829.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Darwin, Charles. 2004 [1879]. The Descent of Man. 2nd ed. New York: Penguin. Darwin, Charles. 2004 [1879]. The Descent of Man. 2nd ed. New York: Penguin.
Zurück zum Zitat Estlund, David. 2011. Human Nature and the Limits (if Any) of Political Philosophy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 39 (2011): 207–235.CrossRef Estlund, David. 2011. Human Nature and the Limits (if Any) of Political Philosophy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 39 (2011): 207–235.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2014. Utopophobia. Philosophy and Public Affairs 42: 114–134.CrossRef ———. 2014. Utopophobia. Philosophy and Public Affairs 42: 114–134.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fehr, Ernst, and Urs Fischbacher. 2004. Third-Party Punishment and Social Norms. Evolution and Human Behavior 25: 63–87.CrossRef Fehr, Ernst, and Urs Fischbacher. 2004. Third-Party Punishment and Social Norms. Evolution and Human Behavior 25: 63–87.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2005. The Economics of Strong Reciprocity. In Moral Sentiments and Material Interests: The Foundations of Cooperation in Economic Life, ed. Herbert Gintis, Samuel Bowles, Robert Boyd, and Ernst Fehr, 151–191. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ———. 2005. The Economics of Strong Reciprocity. In Moral Sentiments and Material Interests: The Foundations of Cooperation in Economic Life, ed. Herbert Gintis, Samuel Bowles, Robert Boyd, and Ernst Fehr, 151–191. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Fehr, Ernst, and Simon Gächter. 2000a. Cooperation and Punishment in Public Goods Experiments. American Economic Review 90: 980–994.CrossRef Fehr, Ernst, and Simon Gächter. 2000a. Cooperation and Punishment in Public Goods Experiments. American Economic Review 90: 980–994.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2000b. Fairness and Retaliation: The Economics of Reciprocity. Journal of Economic Perspectives 14: 159–181.CrossRef ———. 2000b. Fairness and Retaliation: The Economics of Reciprocity. Journal of Economic Perspectives 14: 159–181.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Friedman, Daniel. 2008. Morals and Markets: An Evolutionary Account of the Modern World. New York: Routledge.CrossRef Friedman, Daniel. 2008. Morals and Markets: An Evolutionary Account of the Modern World. New York: Routledge.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Frijda, Nico H. 1996. The Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Frijda, Nico H. 1996. The Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Galeotti, Fabio. 2013. An Experiment on Waiting Time and Punishing Behavior. Economics Bulletin 33 (2): 1383–1389. Galeotti, Fabio. 2013. An Experiment on Waiting Time and Punishing Behavior. Economics Bulletin 33 (2): 1383–1389.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2015. Do Negative Emotions Explain Punishment in Power-To-Take Game Experiments? Journal of Economic Psychology 49: 1–14.CrossRef ———. 2015. Do Negative Emotions Explain Punishment in Power-To-Take Game Experiments? Journal of Economic Psychology 49: 1–14.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gaus, Gerald. 2011. The Order of Public Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gaus, Gerald. 2011. The Order of Public Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2015. The Egalitarian Species. Social Philosophy and Policy 31: 1–27.CrossRef ———. 2015. The Egalitarian Species. Social Philosophy and Policy 31: 1–27.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2016. Tyranny of the Ideal: Justice in a Diverse Society. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef ———. 2016. Tyranny of the Ideal: Justice in a Diverse Society. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2018. It Can’t Be Rational Choice All the Way Down: Comprehensive Hobbesianism and the Origins of the Moral Order. In Tensions in the Political Economy Project of James M. Buchanan, ed. Peter J. Boettke, Virgil Henry Storr, and Solomon Stein. Arlington: Mercatus Center. ———. 2018. It Can’t Be Rational Choice All the Way Down: Comprehensive Hobbesianism and the Origins of the Moral Order. In Tensions in the Political Economy Project of James M. Buchanan, ed. Peter J. Boettke, Virgil Henry Storr, and Solomon Stein. Arlington: Mercatus Center.
Zurück zum Zitat Gaus, Gerald, and Shaun Nichols. 2017. Moral Learning in the Open Society: The Theory and Practice of Natural Liberty. Social Philosophy and Policy 34. Gaus, Gerald, and Shaun Nichols. 2017. Moral Learning in the Open Society: The Theory and Practice of Natural Liberty. Social Philosophy and Policy 34.
Zurück zum Zitat Grimm, Veronika, and Friederike Mengel. 2011. Let Me Sleep on It: Delay Reduces Rejection Rates in Ultimatum Games. Economics Letters 111: 113–115.CrossRef Grimm, Veronika, and Friederike Mengel. 2011. Let Me Sleep on It: Delay Reduces Rejection Rates in Ultimatum Games. Economics Letters 111: 113–115.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hardin, Russell. 1999. From Bodo Ethics to Distributive Justice. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2 (1999): 399–413.CrossRef Hardin, Russell. 1999. From Bodo Ethics to Distributive Justice. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2 (1999): 399–413.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2003. Indeterminacy and Society. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ———. 2003. Indeterminacy and Society. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2007. David Hume: Moral and Political Theorist. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef ———. 2007. David Hume: Moral and Political Theorist. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2013. The Priority of Social Order. Rationality and Society 25: 407–421.CrossRef ———. 2013. The Priority of Social Order. Rationality and Society 25: 407–421.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Henrich, Joseph. 2016. The Secret of Our Success: How Culture Is Driving Human Evolution, Domesticating Our Species, and Making Us Smarter. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef Henrich, Joseph. 2016. The Secret of Our Success: How Culture Is Driving Human Evolution, Domesticating Our Species, and Making Us Smarter. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Henrich, Natalie, and Joseph Henrich. 2007. Why Humans Cooperate. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Henrich, Natalie, and Joseph Henrich. 2007. Why Humans Cooperate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Henrich, Joseph, and Natalie Smith. 2004. Comparative Evidence from Machiguenga, Mapuche, and American Populations. In Foundations of Human Sociality: Economic Experiments and Ethnographic Evidence from Fifteen Small-Scale Societies, ed. J. Henrich, R. Boyd, S. Bowles, et al., 125–167. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Henrich, Joseph, and Natalie Smith. 2004. Comparative Evidence from Machiguenga, Mapuche, and American Populations. In Foundations of Human Sociality: Economic Experiments and Ethnographic Evidence from Fifteen Small-Scale Societies, ed. J. Henrich, R. Boyd, S. Bowles, et al., 125–167. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hoffman, Elizabeth, Kevin A. McCabe, and Vernon L. Smith. 1996. On Expectations and the Monetary Stakes in Ultimatum Games. International Journal of Game Theory 25: 289–301.CrossRef Hoffman, Elizabeth, Kevin A. McCabe, and Vernon L. Smith. 1996. On Expectations and the Monetary Stakes in Ultimatum Games. International Journal of Game Theory 25: 289–301.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hopfensitz, Astrid, and Ernesto Reuben. 2009. The Importance of Emotions for the Effectiveness of Social Punishment. The Economic Journal 119: 1534–1559.CrossRef Hopfensitz, Astrid, and Ernesto Reuben. 2009. The Importance of Emotions for the Effectiveness of Social Punishment. The Economic Journal 119: 1534–1559.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kitcher, Philip. 2010. The Ethical Project. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Kitcher, Philip. 2010. The Ethical Project. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Knight, Simon. 2012. Fairness or Anger in Ultimatum Game Rejections? Journal of European Psychology Students 3: 1–14.CrossRef Knight, Simon. 2012. Fairness or Anger in Ultimatum Game Rejections? Journal of European Psychology Students 3: 1–14.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Mackie, Gerry. 2017. Effective Rule of Law Requires Construction of a Social Norm of Legal Obedience. In Cultural Agents Reloaded: The Legacy of Antanas Mockus, ed. Carlo Tognato. Cambridge, MA: The Cultural Agents Initiative at Harvard University. Mackie, Gerry. 2017. Effective Rule of Law Requires Construction of a Social Norm of Legal Obedience. In Cultural Agents Reloaded: The Legacy of Antanas Mockus, ed. Carlo Tognato. Cambridge, MA: The Cultural Agents Initiative at Harvard University.
Zurück zum Zitat Mockus, Antanas. 2012. Building ‘Citizenship Culture’ in Bogotá. Journal of International Affairs 65: 143–146. Mockus, Antanas. 2012. Building ‘Citizenship Culture’ in Bogotá. Journal of International Affairs 65: 143–146.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2017. Bogotá’s Capacity for Self-Transformation and Citizenship Building. In Cultural Agents Reloaded: The Legacy of Antanas Mockus, ed. Carlo Tognato. Cambridge, MA: The Cultural Agents Initiative at Harvard University. ———. 2017. Bogotá’s Capacity for Self-Transformation and Citizenship Building. In Cultural Agents Reloaded: The Legacy of Antanas Mockus, ed. Carlo Tognato. Cambridge, MA: The Cultural Agents Initiative at Harvard University.
Zurück zum Zitat Moehler, Michael. 2014. The Scope of Instrumental Morality. Philosophical Studies 167: 431–451.CrossRef Moehler, Michael. 2014. The Scope of Instrumental Morality. Philosophical Studies 167: 431–451.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Nunnar-Winkler, Gertrude, and Beate Sodian. 1988. Children’s Understanding of Moral Emotions. Child Development 59: 1323–1338.CrossRef Nunnar-Winkler, Gertrude, and Beate Sodian. 1988. Children’s Understanding of Moral Emotions. Child Development 59: 1323–1338.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Prinz, Jesse. 2007. The Emotional Construction of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Prinz, Jesse. 2007. The Emotional Construction of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice. rev ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice. rev ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Reuben, Ernesto, and Frans van Winden. 2010. Fairness Perceptions and Prosocial Emotions in the Power to Take. Journal of Economic Psychology 31: 908–922.CrossRef Reuben, Ernesto, and Frans van Winden. 2010. Fairness Perceptions and Prosocial Emotions in the Power to Take. Journal of Economic Psychology 31: 908–922.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Richerson, Peter J., and Robert Boyd. 2005. Not by Genes Alone: How Culture Transformed Human Evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Richerson, Peter J., and Robert Boyd. 2005. Not by Genes Alone: How Culture Transformed Human Evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2008. The Evolution of Free Enterprise Values. In Moral Markets: The Critical Role of Values in the Economy, ed. Paul Zak. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ———. 2008. The Evolution of Free Enterprise Values. In Moral Markets: The Critical Role of Values in the Economy, ed. Paul Zak. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat ———. 2013. Rethinking Paleoanthropology: A World Queerer than We Supposed. In Evolution of Mind, ed. Gary Hatfield and Holly Pittman, 263–302. Phildelphia: Pennsylvania Museum Conference Series. ———. 2013. Rethinking Paleoanthropology: A World Queerer than We Supposed. In Evolution of Mind, ed. Gary Hatfield and Holly Pittman, 263–302. Phildelphia: Pennsylvania Museum Conference Series.
Zurück zum Zitat Rose, David C. 2011. The Moral Foundations of Economic Behavior. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Rose, David C. 2011. The Moral Foundations of Economic Behavior. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Schulz, Jonathan F., Urs Fischbacher, Christian Thön, and Verena Utikal. 2014. Affect and Fairness: Dictator Games under Cognitive Load. Journal of Economic Psychology 41: 77–87.CrossRef Schulz, Jonathan F., Urs Fischbacher, Christian Thön, and Verena Utikal. 2014. Affect and Fairness: Dictator Games under Cognitive Load. Journal of Economic Psychology 41: 77–87.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Schwab, David, and Elinor Ostrom. 2008. The Vital Role of Norms and Rules in Maintaining Open Public and Private Economies. In Moral Markets: The Critical Role of Values in the Economy, ed. Paul Zak. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Schwab, David, and Elinor Ostrom. 2008. The Vital Role of Norms and Rules in Maintaining Open Public and Private Economies. In Moral Markets: The Critical Role of Values in the Economy, ed. Paul Zak. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Slonim, Robert, and Alvin E. Roth. 1998. Learning in High Stakes Ultimatum Games: An Experiment in the Slovak Republic. Econometrica 66 (3): 569–596.CrossRef Slonim, Robert, and Alvin E. Roth. 1998. Learning in High Stakes Ultimatum Games: An Experiment in the Slovak Republic. Econometrica 66 (3): 569–596.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Stiner, Mary C., Ran Barkai, Avi Gopher, and James F. O’Connell. 2009. Cooperative Hunting and Meat Sharing 400–200 KYA at Qesem Cave, Israel. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 106 (32): 13207–13212.CrossRef Stiner, Mary C., Ran Barkai, Avi Gopher, and James F. O’Connell. 2009. Cooperative Hunting and Meat Sharing 400–200 KYA at Qesem Cave, Israel. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 106 (32): 13207–13212.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Thulin, Eric, and Cristina Bicchieri. 2015. I’m So Angry I Could Help You: Moral Outrage as a Driver of Victim Compensation. Social Philosophy and Policy 32 (2): 146–160.CrossRef Thulin, Eric, and Cristina Bicchieri. 2015. I’m So Angry I Could Help You: Moral Outrage as a Driver of Victim Compensation. Social Philosophy and Policy 32 (2): 146–160.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Turiel, Elliot, Melainie Killen, and Charles C. Helwig. 1987. Morality: Its Structure, Functions and Vagaries. In The Emergence of Morality in Young Children, ed. Jerome Kagan and Sharon Lamb, 155–243. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Turiel, Elliot, Melainie Killen, and Charles C. Helwig. 1987. Morality: Its Structure, Functions and Vagaries. In The Emergence of Morality in Young Children, ed. Jerome Kagan and Sharon Lamb, 155–243. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Turnbull, Colin M. 1963. The Forest People. New York: Simon and Schuster. Turnbull, Colin M. 1963. The Forest People. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Zurück zum Zitat van Damme, Eric, et al. 2014. How Werner Güth’s Ultimatum Game Shaped Our Understanding of Social Behavior. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 108: 292–318.CrossRef van Damme, Eric, et al. 2014. How Werner Güth’s Ultimatum Game Shaped Our Understanding of Social Behavior. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 108: 292–318.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Vanderschraaf, Peter. 2007. Covenants and Reputations. Synthese 157: 167–195.CrossRef Vanderschraaf, Peter. 2007. Covenants and Reputations. Synthese 157: 167–195.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Young, Iris Marion. 2011. Responsibility for Justice. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Young, Iris Marion. 2011. Responsibility for Justice. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
The Priority of Social Morality
verfasst von
Gerald Gaus
Copyright-Jahr
2018
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-61070-2_2