Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Minds and Machines 1-2/2016

01.03.2016

The Revenge of Ecological Rationality: Strategy-Selection by Meta-Induction Within Changing Environments

verfasst von: Gerhard Schurz, Paul D. Thorn

Erschienen in: Minds and Machines | Ausgabe 1-2/2016

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

According to the paradigm of adaptive rationality, successful inference and prediction methods tend to be local and frugal. As a complement to work within this paradigm, we investigate the problem of selecting an optimal combination of prediction methods from a given toolbox of such local methods, in the context of changing environments. These selection methods are called meta-inductive (MI) strategies, if they are based on the success-records of the toolbox-methods. No absolutely optimal MI strategy exists—a fact that we call the “revenge of ecological rationality”. Nevertheless one can show that a certain MI strategy exists, called “AW”, which is universally long-run optimal, with provably small short-run losses, in comparison to any set of prediction methods that it can use as input. We call this property universal access-optimality. Local and short-run improvements over AW are possible, but only at the cost of forfeiting universal access-optimality. The last part of the paper includes an empirical study of MI strategies in application to an 8-year-long data set from the Monash University Footy Tipping Competition.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 390 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe




 

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Anhänge
Nur mit Berechtigung zugänglich
Fußnoten
1
Cf. Gigerenzer et al. (1999), Todd and Gigerenzer (2012), and Hertwig et al. (2013).
 
2
The lack of connection between a high cue correlation and TTB's success is also reported in Czerlinski et al. (1999, p. 116f). The implication between high cue-validity dispersion and TTB's optimality holds only in "naive Bayes" environments (cf. fn. 13 and Katsikopoulos and Martignon 2006, Corollary 1). Gigerenzer and Brighton (2009, p. 143) and Brighton and Gigerenzer (2012, p. 55) describe an environment with zero cue validity dispersion (a so-called Guttman environment) in which TTB works particularly well.
 
3
See (among others) Gigerenzer et al. (1999), ch. III, Brighton and Gigerenzer (2012), Rieskamp and Dieckmann (2012), and Katsikopoulos et al. (2010).
 
4
Exceptions to (a) are Hoffrage et al. (2000), Hogarth and Karelaia (2005) and Katsikopoulos et al. (2010), who study prediction tasks based on continuous-valued cues. Exceptions to (b) are Dieckmann and Todd (2012), and Rieskamp and Otto (2006), who study prediction tasks in the course of online learning.
 
5
Other frequently studied methods are Dawes' rule (equal weights), regression (optimal weights), and "naive Bayes" (Gigerenzer et al. 1999, part III).
 
6
A related idea is anticipated in Katsikopoulos and Martignon (2006, p. 491), who interpret a cue as a juror voting for one of two options in a social choice task.
 
7
A clairvoyant P ‘sees’ the future, and can be identified with a function fP: |N × Ω → Ω.
 
8
For fixed n we approximate \( {\text{p}}(|{\text{suc}}_{\text{n}} - {\text{p}}| \ge\updelta) \approx {\text{c}}/({\text{n}}^{0.5} \cdot {\text{e}}^{{0.5 \cdot {\text{n}} \cdot\updelta^{2} }} ) \) (see de Finetti 1974, sect. VII.5.4). pδ is upper bounded by the infinite \( {\text{sum}}\,{\text{c}} \cdot \Sigma_{\text {n} \le \text {i} \le \infty } (1/({\text{i}}^{0.5} \cdot {\text{e}}^{{0.5 \cdot {\text{i}} \cdot\updelta^{2} }} )) \). This sum is lower-equal (c/n0.5)·Σn≤i≤∞xi), which is (by the sum-formula for a convergent geometric series) equal to (c/n0.5)·xn/(1−x).
 
9
This requirement guarantees that under the conditions of Theorem 3 the intermittent version of AW approximates TTB in the long run.
 
10
Cf. Cesa-Bianchi and Lugosi (2006, ch. 4.2). The randomization method presupposes that the event sequence does not react adversarially to AW's predictions. For adversarial event sequences, Theorem 4 can be transferred by assuming a collective of binary meta-inductivists who approximate real-valued predictions by the mean value of their binary predictions (cf. Schurz 2008, Theorem 5).
 
11
This dominance-claim can be strengthened (cf. Schurz 2008, Sect. 9.2). But AW is not universally access-dominant, since there are variations of AW with a different short-run performance.
 
12
(a) follows from the fact that there are uncountably many sequences but only countably many computable ones. (b) holds since the uniform prior distribution over {0,1} implies p(ei|ej) = p(ei) = 1/2, i.e., the distribution is IID, which entails (b) by the strong law of large numbers.
 
13
See next section. Katsikopoulos and Martignon (2006) proved that under the condition of known validities and "naive Bayes environments" (conditionally independent cue validities and uniform prior), the logarithmic version of iSW that takes log(val(Pi)/(1 − val(Pi))) as the weight of cue Pi is probabilistically optimal among all possible methods.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Arnold, E. (2010). Can the best-alternative-justification solve Hume’s problem? Philosophy of Science, 77, 584–593.CrossRef Arnold, E. (2010). Can the best-alternative-justification solve Hume’s problem? Philosophy of Science, 77, 584–593.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Brighton, H. & Gigerenzer, G. (2012). How heuristics handle uncertainty. In Todd & Gigerenzer (eds.), (pp. 33–60). (Note: This article is an abbreviated version of Gigerenzer and Brighton 2009.) Brighton, H. & Gigerenzer, G. (2012). How heuristics handle uncertainty. In Todd & Gigerenzer (eds.), (pp. 33–60). (Note: This article is an abbreviated version of Gigerenzer and Brighton 2009.)
Zurück zum Zitat Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press.MATH Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press.MATH
Zurück zum Zitat Cesa-Bianchi, N., & Lugosi, G. (2006). Prediction, learning, and games. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.CrossRefMATH Cesa-Bianchi, N., & Lugosi, G. (2006). Prediction, learning, and games. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.CrossRefMATH
Zurück zum Zitat Czerlinski, J., Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. G. (1999). How good are simple heuristics? In: Gigerenzer et al. (Eds.), (pp. 97–118). Czerlinski, J., Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. G. (1999). How good are simple heuristics? In: Gigerenzer et al. (Eds.), (pp. 97–118).
Zurück zum Zitat De Finetti, B. (1974). Theory of probability. New York: John Wiley.MATH De Finetti, B. (1974). Theory of probability. New York: John Wiley.MATH
Zurück zum Zitat Dieckmann, A., & Todd, P. M. (2012). Simple rules for ordering cues in one-reason decision making. In: Todd & Gigerenzer (Eds.), (pp. 274–306). Dieckmann, A., & Todd, P. M. (2012). Simple rules for ordering cues in one-reason decision making. In: Todd & Gigerenzer (Eds.), (pp. 274–306).
Zurück zum Zitat Feldbacher, C. (2012). Meta-induction and the wisdom of crowds. Analyse & Kritik, 34(2), 367–382.CrossRef Feldbacher, C. (2012). Meta-induction and the wisdom of crowds. Analyse & Kritik, 34(2), 367–382.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gigerenzer, G., & Brighton, H. (2009). Homo heuristicus: Why biased minds make better inferences. Topics in Cognitive Science, 1, 107–143.CrossRef Gigerenzer, G., & Brighton, H. (2009). Homo heuristicus: Why biased minds make better inferences. Topics in Cognitive Science, 1, 107–143.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gigerenzer, G., Todd, P. M., & The ABC Research Group (Eds.). (1999). Simple heuristics that make us smart. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press. Gigerenzer, G., Todd, P. M., & The ABC Research Group (Eds.). (1999). Simple heuristics that make us smart. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Hertwig, R., Hoffrage, U., & The ABC Research Group. (2013). Simple heuristics in a social world. New York: Oxford University Press. Hertwig, R., Hoffrage, U., & The ABC Research Group. (2013). Simple heuristics in a social world. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Hoffrage, U., Hertwig, R., & Gigerenzer, G. (2000). Hindsight bias: A by-product of knowledge updating? Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 26, 566–581.CrossRef Hoffrage, U., Hertwig, R., & Gigerenzer, G. (2000). Hindsight bias: A by-product of knowledge updating? Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 26, 566–581.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hogarth, R. M., & Karelaia, N. (2005). Ignoring information in binary choice with continuous variables: When is Less “More”? Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 49, 115–124.MathSciNetCrossRefMATH Hogarth, R. M., & Karelaia, N. (2005). Ignoring information in binary choice with continuous variables: When is Less “More”? Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 49, 115–124.MathSciNetCrossRefMATH
Zurück zum Zitat Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (1996). Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian approach (2nd ed.). Chicago: Open Court. Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (1996). Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian approach (2nd ed.). Chicago: Open Court.
Zurück zum Zitat Jekel, M., Glöckner, A., Fielder, S., & Bröder, A. (2012). The rationality of different kinds of intuitive decision processes. Synthese, 89(1), 147–160.CrossRef Jekel, M., Glöckner, A., Fielder, S., & Bröder, A. (2012). The rationality of different kinds of intuitive decision processes. Synthese, 89(1), 147–160.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Katsikopoulos, K. V., & Martignon, L. (2006). Naive heuristics for paired comparisons. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 50, 488–494.MathSciNetCrossRefMATH Katsikopoulos, K. V., & Martignon, L. (2006). Naive heuristics for paired comparisons. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 50, 488–494.MathSciNetCrossRefMATH
Zurück zum Zitat Katsikopoulos, K. V., Schooler, L. J., & Hertwig, R. (2010). The robust beauty of ordinary information. Psychological Review, 117(4), 1259–1266.CrossRef Katsikopoulos, K. V., Schooler, L. J., & Hertwig, R. (2010). The robust beauty of ordinary information. Psychological Review, 117(4), 1259–1266.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Kelly, K. (1996). The logic of reliable inquiry. New York: Oxford Univ. Press.MATH Kelly, K. (1996). The logic of reliable inquiry. New York: Oxford Univ. Press.MATH
Zurück zum Zitat Martignon, L., & Hoffrage, U. (1999). Why does one-reason decision making work? In: Gigerenzer et al. (Eds.), (pp. 119–140). Martignon, L., & Hoffrage, U. (1999). Why does one-reason decision making work? In: Gigerenzer et al. (Eds.), (pp. 119–140).
Zurück zum Zitat Popper, K. (1935/2002). Logic of discovery. London: Routledge. Popper, K. (1935/2002). Logic of discovery. London: Routledge.
Zurück zum Zitat Rieskamp, J., & Dieckmann, A. (2012). Redundancy: Environment structure that simple heuristics can exploit. In Todd & Gigerenzer (eds.), (pp. 187–215). Rieskamp, J., & Dieckmann, A. (2012). Redundancy: Environment structure that simple heuristics can exploit. In Todd & Gigerenzer (eds.), (pp. 187–215).
Zurück zum Zitat Rieskamp, J., & Otto, P. (2006). SSL: A theory of how people learn to select strategies. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 135(2), 207–236.CrossRef Rieskamp, J., & Otto, P. (2006). SSL: A theory of how people learn to select strategies. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 135(2), 207–236.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Schmitt, M., & Martignon, L. (2006). On the complexity of learning lexicographic strategies. Journal of Machine Learning Research, 7, 55–83.MathSciNetMATH Schmitt, M., & Martignon, L. (2006). On the complexity of learning lexicographic strategies. Journal of Machine Learning Research, 7, 55–83.MathSciNetMATH
Zurück zum Zitat Schurz, G. (2008). The meta-inductivist’s winning strategy in the prediction game: A new approach to Hume’s problem. Philosophy of Science, 75, 278–305.MathSciNetCrossRef Schurz, G. (2008). The meta-inductivist’s winning strategy in the prediction game: A new approach to Hume’s problem. Philosophy of Science, 75, 278–305.MathSciNetCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Schurz, G. (2009). Meta-induction and social epistemology. Episteme, 6, 200–220.CrossRef Schurz, G. (2009). Meta-induction and social epistemology. Episteme, 6, 200–220.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Schurz, G. (2012). Meta-induction in epistemic networks and social spread of knowledge. Episteme, 9(2), 151–170.MathSciNetCrossRef Schurz, G. (2012). Meta-induction in epistemic networks and social spread of knowledge. Episteme, 9(2), 151–170.MathSciNetCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Schurz, G. (2013). Philosophy of science: A unified approach. New York: Routledge. Schurz, G. (2013). Philosophy of science: A unified approach. New York: Routledge.
Zurück zum Zitat Schurz, G., & Thorn, P. (2014). TTB vs. Franklin’s rule in environments of different redundancy. Appendix to G. Schurz, Instrumental justifications of normative systems of reasoning. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, article 625, July 2014. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00625. Schurz, G., & Thorn, P. (2014). TTB vs. Franklin’s rule in environments of different redundancy. Appendix to G. Schurz, Instrumental justifications of normative systems of reasoning. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, article 625, July 2014. doi:10.​3389/​fpsyg.​2014.​00625.
Zurück zum Zitat Shanks, D. R., Douglas, L. M., & Holyoak, K. J. (Eds.). (1996). The psychology of learning and motivation. San Diego, CA: Academic Press. Shanks, D. R., Douglas, L. M., & Holyoak, K. J. (Eds.). (1996). The psychology of learning and motivation. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Simon, H. A. (1982). Models of bounded rationality (Vol. 1). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Simon, H. A. (1982). Models of bounded rationality (Vol. 1). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Solomonoff, R.J. (1964). A formal theory of inductive inference. Information and Control, 7, 1–22 (part I), 224–254 (part II). Solomonoff, R.J. (1964). A formal theory of inductive inference. Information and Control, 7, 1–22 (part I), 224–254 (part II).
Zurück zum Zitat Thorn, P., & Schurz, G. (2012). Meta-induction and the wisdom of crowds. Analyse & Kritik, 34(2), 339–366.CrossRef Thorn, P., & Schurz, G. (2012). Meta-induction and the wisdom of crowds. Analyse & Kritik, 34(2), 339–366.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Todd, P. M., & Gigerenzer, G. (Eds.). (2012). Ecological rationality: intelligence in the world. New York: Oxford University Press. Todd, P. M., & Gigerenzer, G. (Eds.). (2012). Ecological rationality: intelligence in the world. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Weibull, J. (1995). Evolutionary game theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATH Weibull, J. (1995). Evolutionary game theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATH
Zurück zum Zitat Wells, A. J. (2005). Rethinking cognitive computation: Turing and the science of the mind. Basingstoke: Palgrave. Wells, A. J. (2005). Rethinking cognitive computation: Turing and the science of the mind. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Zurück zum Zitat Wolpert, D. H. (1996). The lack of a priori distinctions between learning algorithms. Neural Computation, 8(7), 1341–1390.CrossRef Wolpert, D. H. (1996). The lack of a priori distinctions between learning algorithms. Neural Computation, 8(7), 1341–1390.CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
The Revenge of Ecological Rationality: Strategy-Selection by Meta-Induction Within Changing Environments
verfasst von
Gerhard Schurz
Paul D. Thorn
Publikationsdatum
01.03.2016
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Erschienen in
Minds and Machines / Ausgabe 1-2/2016
Print ISSN: 0924-6495
Elektronische ISSN: 1572-8641
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-015-9369-7

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 1-2/2016

Minds and Machines 1-2/2016 Zur Ausgabe

Premium Partner